Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

Similar documents
Validity & Soundness LECTURE 3! Critical Thinking. Summary: In this week s lectures, we will learn! (1) What it is for an argument to be valid.

As noted, a deductive argument is intended to provide logically conclusive support for its conclusion. We have certainty with deductive arguments in

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan

Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan. Fallacies of Presumption, Ambiguity, and Part-Whole Relations

Marquis. Stand-off in Abortion Debate

C. Problem set #1 due today, now, on the desk. B. More of an art than a science the key things are: 4.

INDUCTION. All inductive reasoning is based on an assumption called the UNIFORMITY OF NATURE.

Introduction to Philosophy

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

A. Problem set #3 it has been posted and is due Tuesday, 15 November

Argument. What is it? How do I make a good one?

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Also, in Argument #1 (Lecture 11, Slide 11), the inference from steps 2 and 3 to 4 is stated as:

AO1 Content: A: Aquinas Natural Law: Laws and Precepts B: Aquinas Natural Law: Virtues and Goods

PHIL2642 CRITICAL THINKING USYD NOTES PART 1: LECTURE NOTES

SHORT ANSWER. Write the word or phrase that best completes each statement or answers the question.

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

b) The meaning of "child" would need to be taken in the sense of age, as most people would find the idea of a young child going to jail as wrong.

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

Instructor s Manual 1

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

In view of the fact that IN CLASS LOGIC EXERCISES

Arguments. 1. using good premises (ones you have good reason to believe are both true and relevant to the issue at hand),

LOGIC LECTURE #3: DEDUCTION AND INDUCTION. Source: A Concise Introduction to Logic, 11 th Ed. (Patrick Hurley, 2012)

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

Test Item File. Full file at

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Evaluating Arguments

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

Review Deductive Logic. Wk2 Day 2. Critical Thinking Ninjas! Steps: 1.Rephrase as a syllogism. 2.Choose your weapon

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

Basic Concepts and Skills!

What is an argument? PHIL 110. Is this an argument? Is this an argument? What about this? And what about this?

Example Arguments ID1050 Quantitative & Qualitative Reasoning

Critical Reasoning for Beginners: Four. Marianne Talbot Department for Continuing Education University of Oxford Michaelmas 2009

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Philosophical Arguments

PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS

Views on Ethnicity and the Church. From Surveys of Protestant Pastors and Adult Americans

Introduction to Philosophy Crito. Instructor: Jason Sheley

In a previous lecture, we used Aristotle s syllogisms to emphasize the

Philosophical approaches to animal ethics

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Three Ethics Reasoning Assessment (TERA) Lene Arnett Jensen, Clark University

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

Inductive Logic. Induction is the process of drawing a general conclusion from incomplete evidence.

Critical Thinking - Section 1

Argumentation. 2. What should we consider when making (or testing) an argument?

Reason and Argument. Richard Feldman Second Edition

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

National Quali cations

Philosophy Courses Fall 2011

Second Term,

Exhibit C. Sample Pediatric Forensic Informed Consent Form (Longer Version) {Insert Letterhead} INFORMED CONSENT FOR NEUROPSYCHOLOGICAL ASSESSMENT

5.6.1 Formal validity in categorical deductive arguments

1 Chapter 6 (Part 2): Assessing Truth Claims

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Why Speciesism is Wrong: A Response to Kagan

Session 10 INDUCTIVE REASONONING IN THE SCIENCES & EVERYDAY LIFE( PART 1)

Lecture 6 Keynes s Concept of Probability

Clarifications on What Is Speciesism?

2nd International Workshop on Argument for Agreement and Assurance (AAA 2015), Kanagawa Japan, November 2015

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

PHILOSOPHER S TOOL KIT 1. ARGUMENTS PROFESSOR JULIE YOO 1.1 DEDUCTIVE VS INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

The Critique (analyzing an essay s argument)

Argument Writing. Whooohoo!! Argument instruction is necessary * Argument comprehension is required in school assignments, standardized testing, job

Why Good Science Is Not Value-Free

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Announcements. Quiz #4. Review, see me before the Final Exam for help. Average? High Score? BUT, everyone will get +1pt!

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

AS Religious Studies. 7061/1 Philosophy of Religion and Ethics Mark scheme June Version: 1.0 Final

According to Russell, do we know the self by acquaintance? (hint: the answer is not yes )

Re: Main difference between Hasty Generalizations and Slippery Slope by Catherine - Wednesday, 5 September 2012, 8:57 PM

Application Form Non Teaching Position

Sermon: Mission in Christ

T. Parent. I shall explain these steps in turn. Let s consider the following passage to illustrate the process:

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

ELC VITAL SIGNS CHURCH ASSESSMENT SUMMARY. C.A.T. Task Force Team Presentation, March 16th

NT501 New Testament Survey Course Syllabus, Spring 2018 RTS-Orlando

ST507: Contemporary Theology II: From Theology of Hope to Postmodernism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

Transcription:

CRITICAL THINKING Norva Y S Lo Produced by Norva Y S Lo Edited by Andrew Brennan LECTURE 4! Nondeductive Success: Statistical Syllogism, Inductive Generalization, Analogical Argument Summary In this week s lecture, you will learn: (1) The concept of nondeductive success. (2) Three types of nondeductive arguments (a) Statistical Syllogism (b) Inductive Generalization (c) Analogical Argument

Part I. Nondeductive Success & Deductive Validity An argument from premises Ps to conclusion C is deductively valid (i.e., valid) = df The truth of Ps logically guarantees the truth of C. = Under the assumption that all Ps are true, there is exactly a 100% chance for C to be true. i.e., Conditional Probability for C given Ps is exactly 100%. (for short: cp = 100%)! Deductive validity is a matter of all or nothing. An argument cannot be more or less valid. An argument from premises Ps to C is nondeductively successful = df The truth of Ps makes C more likely to be true than false. = Under the assumption that all Ps are true, there is a greater than 50% chance for C to be true. i.e., Conditional probability for C given Ps is greater than 50%. (for short: cp > 50%)! Nondeductive success comes in degrees. An argument can be more or less nondeductively successful.! If cp = 100%, the argument is successful (because cp > 50%) and also valid (because cp = 100%).! Deductive validity is said to be the limiting case of nondeductive success. Examples on next slide! more unsuccessful Unsuccessful cp! 50% less unsuccessful Invalid cp < 100% less successful Successful cp > 50% more successful Valid (limit of success) cp = 100% cp = 0% 50% 100% Argument A. 80% of Australians watch TV regularly.. Tom is Australian. -------------------------------------------------------------- C. Tom watches TV regularly. Argument B *. 70% of Australians read newspapers regularly. *. Tom is Australian. ------------------------------------------------------------------------- C*. Tom reads newspapers regularly.! If both and are true, then the probability for C to be true is 80%.! The conditional probability of C given and is 80%, which is greater than 50%.! Argument A is nondeductively successful.! But It is logically possible for C to be false under and. Argument A is still deductively invalid.! The conditional probability of C* given * and * is 70%, which is greater than 50%.! Argument B is nondeductively successful.! But Argument B is nondeductively less successful than Argument A. It is also invalid. Argument C **. 50% of Australians work part time. **. Tom is Australian. ----------------------------------------------------------- C**. Tom works part time. Argument D ***. 100% of Australians have the right to life. ***. Tom is Australian. ---------------------------------------------------------------------- C***. Tom has the right to life.! The conditional probability of C** given ** and ** is 50% (which is not greater than 50%).! Argument C is nondeductively unsuccessful. It is also invalid.! The conditional probability of C*** given *** and *** is 100%.! Argument D is nondeductively successful as well as deductively valid.

Part II. Three Types of Nondeductive Arguments! Many text books define nondeductive arguments as arguments that are (a) not meant to be deductively valid, but (b) meant to be nondeductively successful. It follows from this definition that the author s intention determines whether an argument is a deductive argument or a non-deductive argument.! What if an author intends to put forward a deductively invalid but nondeductively successful argument (and so it is a nondeductive argument by the above definition), but the author reasoned wrongly and the argument turns out to be actually deductively valid? Given the above definition, it would be a deductively valid nondeductive argument! (It looks like a potentially confusing definition )! When we assess an argument, it will be simpler just to evaluative whether it is or is not deductively valid, and whether it is or is not nondeductively successful independently of what the author intends. (But what do we call a given argument if we have not yet worked out whether it is deductively valid or not, nondeductively successful or not? There are specific names for different forms of arguments (see below). If an argument fits a form that has a specific name, call it by that name.) (a) Statistical Syllogism. N% members of group X have feature F.. Individual i is a member of group X. ----------------------------------------------------------------- C. Individual i has feature F.! Conditional probability for C given and = N% What a group is like What a group member Is like generalize! A statistical syllogism is nondeductively successful only when N > 50. It is valid only when N = 100.! Among all different types of nondeductive arguments, it is the easiest to determine the degree of nondeductive success in the case of statistical syllogisms. Example #1 (complex argument containing multiple Statistical Syllogisms). 80% of Australians watch TV regularly.. Tom is Australian. C1. Tom watches TV regularly. (intermediate conclusion, from & ) P3. 70% of those who watch TV regularly watch TV commercials regularly. --------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- C2. Tom watches TV commercials regularly. (final conclusion, from C1 & P3)! This is a complex argument. It contains two sub-arguments - all in the form of statistical syllogism.! 1st sub-argument goes from and to C1. Conditional probability for C1 given & = 80%. 1st sub-argument is nondeductively successful. 80% C1! 2nd sub-argument goes from C1 and P3 to C2. Conditional probability for C2 given C1 & P3 = 70%. 2nd sub-argument is also nondeductively successful. P3! Overall conditional probability for C2 given & & P3 = 80% x 70% = 56%! The whole complex argument is nondeductively successful overall. Method: To get the overall conditional probability for the final conclusion given all the premises, multiply together all the individual conditional probabilities for the conclusions in all the sub-arguments. P3 70% C2 80% x 70% C2 56% overall

Example #2. 80% of Australians watch TV regularly.. Tom is Australian. C1. Tom watches TV regularly. (intermediate conclusion, from & ) P3*. 60% of those who watch TV regularly watch TV news reports regularly. ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- C2*. Tom watches TV news reports regularly. (final conclusion, from C1 & P3*)! 1st sub-argument goes from and to C1. Conditional probability for C1 given & is 80%. 1st sub-argument is nondeductively successful.! 2nd sub-argument goes from C1 and P3* to C2*. Conditional probability for C2* given C1 & P3* is 60%. 2nd sub-argument is also nondeductively successful.! Overall conditional probability for C2* given & & P3* = 80% x 60% = 48%! The complex argument is nondeductively unsuccessful overall. P3* 80% C1 P3* 60% C2* 80% x 60% C2* 48% overall Important: Even if all the sub-arguments are individually successful, the complex argument as a whole can still be unsuccessful overall. Example #3. 60% of university students earn a taxable income.. Jane is a university student. C1. Jane earns a taxable income. (from and ) P3. 100% of those who earn a taxable income pay tax. C2. Jane pays tax. (from C1 and P3) P4. 80% of those who pay tax pay less than $50,000 on tax p.a. -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- C3. Jane pays less than $50,000 on tax p.a. (from C2 and P4) 60% P3 P4 C1 100% C2 P3 P4 80% C3 80% x 100% x 60% C3 48% overall! Conditional probability for C1 given & = 60% (1st sub-argument successful)! Conditional probability for C2 given C1 & P3 = 100% (2nd sub-argument successful and valid)! Conditional probability for C3 given C2 & P4 = 80%. (3rd sub-argument successful)! Overall conditional probability for C3 given all the premises = 60% x 100% x 80% = 48%.! The whole complex argument is nondeductively unsuccessful overall. Again: Even if all the sub-arguments are individually nondeductively successful (and even some of valid), the whole complex argument can still be nondeductively unsuccessful overall. which is

We are going to look at other types of nondeductive arguments. It will be considerably more difficult to determine whether or not arguments of those other types are nondeductively successful. (b) Inductive Generalization P. N% of a sub-group in group X have feature F. ------------------------------------------------------------------------ C. N% of the whole group X have feature F. What a sub-group is like What the whole group Is like generalize! Clearly, whether an argument in the form of inductive generalization is nondeductively successful depends on whether the sub-group under consideration is representative of the whole group.! An inductive generalization is successful only when the sub-group (or sample group) is representative.! A common way to defend (or reject) an inductive generalization is to argue that the sub-group considered is (or isn t) representative of the whole group e.g., by whether or not the sub-group was selected by methods of random and diverse sampling. P. 80% of 1,000 randomly selected Australians below 25 years old support a ban on the Mosquito device. --------------------------------------------------------------------- C. 80% of Australians support the ban. Sample group should also include people at/above 25 P. 80% of 1,000 randomly selected shop owners and shopkeepers in Australia support the use of the Mosquito device. --------------------------------------------------------------------- C. 80% of Australians support its use. Sample group should also include P. N% of a sub-group in group X have feature F. ----------------------------------------------------------------------- C. N% of the whole group X have feature F. P. 70% of randomly surveyed university academics regularly work 60 hours a week. --------------------------------------------------------------- C. 70% of university workers regularly work 60 hours a week. P. 40% of men randomly surveyed by Coles cook at least once a week. --------------------------------------------------------------- C. 40% of Australian men cook at least once at week. P. 90% of the year 2005 PHI1CRT students who filled in an anonymous university survey for the subject were satisfied with the subject. ------------------------------------------------------------------ C. 90% of the year 2005 PHI1CRT students were satisfied with the subject. Date of survey: Friday, Week 13 P. 65% of Australians randomly surveyed outside the Flinders Street railway station support carbon tax. --------------------------------------------------------------- C. 65% of Australians support carbon tax. For each argument above, point out its potential weaknesses.

(c) Analogical Argument A1 has the set of features {Fs} and also feature K. (established) A2 has the set of features {Fs} and also feature K. (established) : Ai has the set of features {Fs} and also feature K. (established) B is similar to A1, A2,, Ai in having the set of feature {Fs}. (new case) --------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- B is also similar to A1, A2,, Ai in having feature K. (analogically inferred) Items A1, A2,..., Ai = primary analogues Item B = secondary analogue established old cases generalize a new similar case In an analogical argument, the items being compared (e.g., items A1, A2,, Ai, and B) are called analogues. Items A1, A2, Ai are called the primary analogues. They are used as precedents (i.e., established cases). Item B is called the secondary analogue. It is the new case being compared to the established ones. There are five criteria for evaluating analogical arguments: (1) Relevance of the similar features {Fs} between the As and the B to the extra feature K in question (the more relevant features {Fs} are to feature K, the more successful the analogical argument). (2) Number of similar features {Fs} (the more similar features between the As and the B, the more successful the analogical argument). (3) Number of primary analogues A1, A2,..., Ai (the more primary analogues, the more successful the argument). (4) Diversity among primary analogues A1, A2,..., Ai (the more diversity, the more successful the argument). (5) Disanalogies between primary analogues A1, A2,..., Ai and the secondary analogue B (the fewer disanalogies, the more successful the argument). Arguments from analogy are very often used in reasoning about morality (examples coming). Example #4. People who are victims of a sexual offence are victims of a violent crime, and they are entitled to financial compensation from state or territory government. People who are victims of an actual or threatened assault or injury are victims of a violent crime, and they are entitled to financial compensation from state or territory government. P3. Members of the Stolen Generations are victims of a violent crime. ------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ C. Members of the Stolen Generations are (or should be) entitled to financial compensation from state or territory government. (from, & P3)! Primary analogues: (A1) people who are victims of a sexual offence, (A2) people who are victims of an actual or threatened assault or injury.! Secondary analogue: (B) members of the Stolen Generations.! Similar feature: (F) being victims of a violent crime.! Further similar feature inferred by analogy: (K) being entitled to financial compensation from their state or territory government. Question (1): Can the analogical argument be strengthened by adding more similar features (Fs)? Question (2): Can the analogical argument be weakened by any disanalogy between the primary and secondary analogues? Question (3): Are all the premises actually true?

Example #5. People like you and me have a future that will be valuable to themselves, and it is wrong to kill them.. Temporarily unconscious people have a future that will be valuable to themselves, and it is wrong to kill them. P3. Suicidal teenagers have a future that will be valuable to themselves, and it is wrong to kill them. P4. Infants and very young children have a future that will be valuable to themselves, and it is wrong to kill them. P5. Human fetuses (usually) have a future that will be valuable to themselves. ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- C. It is (usually) wrong to kill human fetuses. Don Marquis, Why abortion is immoral, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 86 (1989), pp. 183-202. Question (1): What are the primary analogues and the secondary analogue? Question (2): What is the similar feature between the analogues? And what is the further similar feature inferred by analogy? Question (3): Is the similar feature in question, when possessed by X, relevant to the issue on whether it is wrong to kill X? Question (4): Is there any disanalogy between the primary and secondary analogues that might weaken the argument? Question (5): Are all the premises true? e.g., Does a human fetus really have a future that will be valuable to itself in the same way that a temporarily unconscious person s future will be valuable to him/her? Examples #6 & #7. Racism is the disregard of an individual s interest due to some morally irrelevant quality possessed by the individual (membership in a racial group), and it is morally wrong.. Sexism is the disregard of an individual s interest due to some morally irrelevant quality possessed by the individual (membership in a gender group), and it is morally wrong. P3. Speciesism is the disregard of an individual s interest due to some morally irrelevant quality possessed by the individual (membership in a species). ---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- C. Speciesism is morally wrong. Peter Singer, Practical Ethics, Cambridge University Press (1979). Infants and very young children are subjects of a life, and they have the moral rights to life and not to be harmed.. People who are born mentally impaired are still subjects of a life, and they have the moral rights to life and not to be harmed. P3. People who suffer from dementia and other mental illness are still subjects of a life, and they have the moral rights to life and not to be harmed. P4. Animals are subjects of a life. ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- C. Animals have the moral rights to life and not to be harmed. Tom Regan, The Case for Animal Rights, University of California Press (1985)

Summary In this week s lecture, you have learnt: (1) The concept of nondeductive success. (2) Three types of nondeductive arguments (a) Statistical Syllogism (b) Inductive Generalization (c) Analogical Argument BACK TO Critical Thinking Homepage