Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

Similar documents
Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

Nominalism III: Austere Nominalism 1. Philosophy 125 Day 7: Overview. Nominalism IV: Austere Nominalism 2

Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism. Lecture 3: Properties II Nominalism & Reductive Realism

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 8: Overview

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Overview of Today s Lecture

Concepts and Properties

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

2 Why Truthmakers GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. INTRODUCTION

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Are All Universals Instantiated?

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Nature of Necessity Chapter IV

Book Reviews. The Metaphysics of Relations, by Anna Marmodoro and David Yates. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, 304 pages, ISBN:

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem II. Inverse Probability and Bayes s Theorem III

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

Theories of propositions

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

ARMSTRONGIAN PARTICULARS WITH NECESSARY PROPERTIES *

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

On An Alleged Non-Equivalence Between Dispositions And Disjunctive Properties

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Varieties of Apriority

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Platonism, Alienation, and Negativity

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Truthmakers for Negative Existentials

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Aboutness and Justification

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

The Question of Metaphysics

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

5 The necessary and the possible

I. Scientific Realism: Introduction

It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

AN EPISTEMIC STRUCTURALIST ACCOUNT

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Postmodal Metaphysics

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Is There Immediate Justification?

Constructing the World

Crawford L. Elder, Familiar Objects and Their Shadows, Cambridge University Press, 2011, 222pp., $85.00 (hardback), ISBN

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Two Kinds of Naturalism in Ethics

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Van Fraassen s Appreciated Anti-Realism. Lane DesAutels. I. Introduction

IF YOU BELIEVE IN POSITIVE FACTS, YOU SHOULD BELIEVE IN NEGATIVE FACTS *

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

REVIEW: James R. Brown, The Laboratory of the Mind

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Intermediate Logic Spring. Extreme Modal Realism

Trinity & contradiction

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Structuralism in the Philosophy of Mathematics

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Transcription:

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview Administrative Stuff Final rosters for sections have been determined. Please check the sections page asap. Important: you must get on the waitlist in order to be added to the rolls. If you re not already in the system, get yourself in. More texts should be at Ned s in the next few days. Meanwhile, you can download chapter 1 (see course home page, requires Adobe Reader 6). Remaining Agenda for Unit 1, Part 1 (Realism and the Problem of Universals) Remarks about applications of realist metaphysics Revisiting the Russellian self-exemplification Paradox: An Analogy Brief review of Parmenidean Regress & Responses Bradley s Regress & Responses Defined versus undefined predicates Unexemplified universals Armstrong s Alternative Realist Theory of Universals

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 2 Remarks About Applications of Realist Metaphysics We have seen three applications of realist metaphysics (attribute agreement, predication, abstract reference). What are they supposed to show? The realist is not merely showing that their metaphysics can be used to make sense out of attribute agreement, predication, and abstract reference. They also want these success stories to provide reasons to accept the underlying realist metaphysical (and ontological) claims. But, how? Analogy: Many scientific realists (e.g., Harman) would take the overwhelming explanatory success of science as evidence that its best theories are true, and (more to the point) that their theoretical (unobservable) terms refer. This is sometimes called inference to the best explanation (see Harman). The metaphysical realist wants to play an analogous game. If the realist accounts turn out to be the best explanations, then doesn t this count as evidence in favor of their truth, and that their theoretical terms refer?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 3 Restrictions on Realism I (Revisited): The Russellian Paradox & An Analogy We saw last time a paradox associated with assuming that there is a property (non-selfexemplification, or N for short) corresponding to the the predicate does not exemplify itself : N exemplifies N iff N does not exemplify N. Loux claims that To avoid the paradox, we have no option but to deny that there is a universal associated with the general term does not exemplify itself. And, I mentioned that I didn t see how this followed. Here s an analogy (and another very famous paradox involving self reference). Consider the following somewhat strange sentence: (*) Sentence (*) is not true. (*) says of itself that it is not true. Fact: (*) is true iff (*) is not true (exercise). This is paradoxical, to be sure. But, what should we conclude from this? One (not obviously crazy) thing we might conclude is that the sentence (*) is meaningless (hence, neither true nor false). Question: Couldn t we say the same thing about N exemplifies N? And, if so, isn t this another option?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 4 Restrictions on Realism IV (Review): The Parmenidean Predication Regress A Parmenidean regress also seems to plague the realist account of predication. The realist account of the truth of subject-predicate claims of the form: (9) a is F. postulates the existence of a universal (F-ness) and a relation (exemplification), such that the following obtains: (9 ) a exemplifies F-ness. Parmenidean: this just introduces a new predicate ( exemplifies F-ness ). And, to account for the truth this case of predication, we ll need to appeal to: (9 ) a exemplifies the exemplification of F-ness. which introduces another predicate ( exemplifies the exemplification of F-ness ) (9 ) a exemplifies the exemplification of the exemplification of F-ness. And so on, ad infinitum the promised account can t be completed.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 5 Restrictions on Realism V (Review): Three Responses to the Parmenidean Regresses #1 (real, vicious): Restrict the scope of ( ) & theory of predication. Say that only some distinct forms of attribute agreement involve distinct universals (only some semantically distinct general terms express distinct universals). Seems ad hoc. Do we have a principled way of setting such restrictions (aside from restrict so as to avoid objections )? Loux rejects this response. #2 (real, not vicious): Reject demand for deeper explanations. Once you explain that (9) is true because (9 ) is true, insist that (9 ) explains (9) completely, and that no further explanations of (9 ), etc. are needed. Loux is sympathetic. He argues that any account which does not eliminate subject-predicate discourse will fall prey to this regress (and should not view it as vicious). S.Q.: carefully reconstruct Loux s argument here. #3 (not real, not vicious): Deny there is a regress. Insist that is F in (9) and exemplifies F-ness in (9 ) (and so on) are (all) semantically equivalent. But, don t they have different ontological implications? This harkens back to horn 2 of our dilemma about the realist paraphrase of a is F into a exemplifies F.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 6 Restrictions on Realism VI: Bradley s Regress According to the realist account of predication, a is F is true only if: (i) the particular a exists (ii) the universal (property) F-ness exists (iii) a exemplifies 1 F-ness is true But, the relational claim (iii) a exemplifies 1 F-ness is true only if: (i ) the particular, property pair a, F-ness exists (ii ) the universal (relation) Exemplification 1 exists (iii ) a, F-ness exemplifies 2 Exemplification 1 is true But the relational claim (iii ) a, F-ness exemplifies 2 Exemplification 1 is true only if (i ) the particular, property, relation pair a, F-ness, Exemplification 1 exists (ii ) the universal (relation) Exemplification 2 exists (iii ) a, F-ness, Exemplification 1 exemplifies 3 Exemplification 2 is true ad infinitum the realist account of the truth of a is F can t be completed

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 7 Restrictions on Realism VII: Realist Responses to Bradley s Regresses #1 (real, vicious): Restrict the scope of the theory of predication. Deny that the realist account of predication applies to Exemplification itself. Many realists say Exemplification is not a relation but a tie or nexus, which links objects into relational facts without the mediation of any further links. Loux: can help avoid the Russellian paradox, too. How? #2 (real, not vicious): Reject demand for deeper explanations. Once you explain that a is F is true because (i) (iii) are true, insist that they explain the truth of a is F completely, and that no explanation of (iii) is needed. Loux is sympathetic (again). But, he does not repeat his argument that any (non-eliminative) account of predication will fall prey to regress. Why not? Isn t this just another example of his C-argument schema (p. 39)? #3 (not real, not vicious): Deny there is a regress. How might this be done? Note: Loux does not even consider this type of response to Bradley s regress. And, as far as I know, nobody else does either. Why not? What would be the analogous strategy, as compared to reply #3 to Parmenides?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 8 Restrictions on Realism VIII: Primitive versus Defined Predicates 1 Consider the predicate bachelor. Does bachelor connote a distinct universal? Or, are there only universals (say) corresponding to male, human, and married (in terms of which bachelor can be defined)? We saw a similar question in the Introduction, where there was a debate over whether summersault picked out a distinct universal (or was merely defined in terms of more primitive predicates like human, body, movement ). Some realists have argued that we should restrict the scope of realist theory to (metaphysically) ground only predicates which make direct contact with universals. Such predicates are called primitive (as opposed to defined). The problem with this distinction has mainly to do with its arbitrariness. We do not want our choice of primitive predicates to be a purely conventional matter of language chopping. We want to carve the world at its joints. Various proposals have been made concerning primitive predicates...

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 9 Restrictions on Realism IX: Primitive versus Defined Predicates 2 Some have proposed epistemically motivated criteria for the choice of primitive predicates. This involves taking as basic predicates that are favored by some epistemological stance. An empiricist stance might suggest taking certain sensory predicates (colors, sounds, smells, shapes, etc.) as primitive. Problem: relatively few (e.g., scientific) predicates have been definable purely in terms of empirical or sensory (even observable) predicates. Wittgenstein (and now many others) was skeptical about the possibility of reducing one set of universals (or predicates) to a primitive (or otherwise privileged) set of universals. Such skeptics are sometimes called holists. Non-holist realists (e.g., Armstrong) often accuse holists of apriorism, since they seem happy to use armchair speculation on the strucuture of language as a guide to what universals there are. Such non-holists often insist that which universals there are (or are primitive) is a matter for science to adjudicate. Here, our best scientific (usually, physical) theories are often taken as a guide. Defined predicates are either eliminable or supervene on physical primitives.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 10 Restrictions on Realism X: The Problem of Unexemplified Universals 1 Platonists believe that there are many Universals that are never exemplified. They even hold that many Universals are necessarily unexemplified (slogan: universalia ante rem, universals anterior to (or independent of) things ). Aristotle was not a Platonist (in this sense). Aristotle believed that Universals do not exist separately (or apart) from particulars exemplifying them. If a predicate is never satisfied by anything, then it doesn t correspond to any Universal (slogan: universalia in rebus, or universals in things ). Why be a Platonist especially one who believes (say) in a property corresponding to the necessarily empty predicate Round-Square-ness? Let s think a bit harder about the realist account of predication. Consider the claim (10) Glass is a solid. (10) is false (according to physics). The realist account still applies to (10). If (10) were true, it would be (partly) because the Universal (kind) Solid exists.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 11 Restrictions on Realism XI: The Problem of Unexemplified Universals 2 The Platonist will say that the (general) account of the truth of (10) shouldn t depend on whether or not (10) happens to be true. Now, consider the claim (11) That plane has a velocity greater than the speed of light. (11) is (nomologically) necessarily false (it is physically impossible to travel faster than light). So, having velocity greater than c is necessarily unexemplified. Is there such a universal? It seems a bit strange to say that there are universals corresponding to the predicates having velocity greater than x, for all x < c, but none for x c. The Platonist Challenge: Give a general, unified account of the truth conditions (semantics) for subject-predicate sentences, without ever positing an unexemplified Universal. This is not so easy to do. Another example: (12) God is omniscient. Even if we think omniscinent is (necessarily) unexemplified, how can we make sense of (12) without positing a Universal called Omniscience?

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 12 Restrictions on Realism XII: The Problem of Unexemplified Universals 3 Non-Platonists (including non-platonist realists, like Armstrong and perhaps Aristotle) complain that Platonism requires a Two-Worlds ontology. If there are universals that are never exemplified (at any place or any time by any particulars), then it seems that they cannot exist in the space-time world. Then, asks the non-platonist, where are these Platonic (uninstantiated) universals? This (mystical?) place is sometimes called Platonic Heaven. There seem to be both M & E problems with such a Two-Worlds ontology: M: How can concrete particulars and universals be connected or tied to each other if they occupy unrelated realms? Realism requires such a tie. Reply? Loux s (p. 50) is not very compelling (what is it?). Problem? E: How can humans (qua concrete particulars) ever come to know about (unexemplified) universals? How can we have cognitive access to them? Reply? Analogy/extrapolation with/on knowledge of exemplified ones.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 13 Armstrong s Alternative Realist Theory of Universals 1 Armstrong sketches an alternative, non-platonist realism about universals. According to Armstrong, Universals are ways things are (or attributes ). In order to sketch Armstrong s theory, we need to introduce some terminology: States of Affairs: If a is F, then a s being F (e.g., Socrates being courageous) is a state of affairs (some call these facts) Instantiation: If a is F, then a instantiates the attribute F-ness a s being F is the truthmaker of a is F. It is in virtue of a s being F that a is F is true. If true, a is F corresponds to the SOA a s being F. According to Armstrong, we need states of affairs in our ontology because we cannot account for the truth of a is F merely by positing the existence of a, F-ness, and a fundamental tie between them (exemplification or instantiation). Particulars and universals (and instantiation) are not ontologically basic. They only exist within states of affairs. States of affairs are ontological bedrock.

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 14 Armstrong s Alternative Realist Theory of Universals 2 The fundamental tie or nexus (called instantiation or exemplification ) is simply the coming together of particulars and attributes in states of affairs. On Armstrong s view, all universals are instantiated at some time & place (in the history of the universe). The World is the collection of all states of affairs. Armstrong is a physicalist, and he thinks that only physical attributes (those occurring as primitives in our best physical theories?) are real (or primitive). He uses causal considerations to rule-out universals. He rules-out disjunctive universals, on the grounds that A OR B adds no causal efficacy to its disjuncts A, B. a s being A has causal efficacy, but A s being A OR B does not. Similarly, Armstrong rules-out negative universals, on the grounds that only attributes a instantiates can give a causal powers (absences cannot cause). Conjunctive universals are OK d by Armstrong, so long as a instantiates both A and B at the same time (then A AND B can have causal significance).

Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 15 Armstrong s Alternative Realist Theory of Universals 3 In a way, Armstrong seems only to be paying lip service to universals (and particulars, for that matter!). It is states of affairs that do all the work in his metaphysics. S.Q.: why does he need/want particulars or universals at all? How (and why) does he carve up SOAs? He stresses SOAs (his ontological bedrock) are more than the sum of their parts (particular, attribute, instantiation). So, why does he care about their parts (even if there are any)? And, even if they do split, why should SOAs split along lines similar to the Platonic realist s subject-predicate-inspired lines? Note: Armstrong thinks arguments from subject-predicate discourse ( meaning arguments ) are bad reasons to believe in universals. Then, why does he believe in them? Why does he think states of affairs contain them? Imagine a pictorial language with no subject-predicate structure in which the SOA a s being F is represented by a picture of that SOA (e.g., snapshot of a red sphere). Why carve this picture along subject-predicate joints? Why not simply take the whole as the real thing, and view talk of parts as arbitrary?