Friends and strangers

Similar documents
MITOCW Lec 2 MIT 6.042J Mathematics for Computer Science, Fall 2010

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

MITOCW ocw f99-lec18_300k

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

MITOCW ocw f99-lec19_300k

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

Mathematics. The BIG game Behind the little tricks

CS 2104 Intro Problem Solving in Computer Science Test 1 READ THIS NOW!

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

ABC News' Guide to Polls & Public Opinion

MITOCW watch?v=ogo1gpxsuzu

Module - 02 Lecturer - 09 Inferential Statistics - Motivation

Module 02 Lecture - 10 Inferential Statistics Single Sample Tests

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

The Gift of the Holy Spirit. 1 Thessalonians 5:23. Sermon Transcript by Rev. Ernest O'Neill

MITOCW MITRES18_006F10_26_0703_300k-mp4

Under the command of algorithms

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 21

It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It. a play by Chris Binge

MITOCW watch?v=6pxncdxixne

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

SID: So we can say this man was as hopeless as your situation, more hopeless than your situation.

Lesson 07 Notes. Machine Learning. Quiz: Computational Learning Theory

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

The following content is provided under a Creative Commons license. Your support

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

*WHY DO I DO WHAT I DON'T WANT TO DO? Romans 7:15, 21-25

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

A romp through the foothills of logic Session 3

Grade 6 Math Connects Suggested Course Outline for Schooling at Home

SUMMARY COMPARISON of 6 th grade Math texts approved for 2007 local Texas adoption

HOW TO GET A WORD FROM GOD ABOUT YOU PROBLEM

On Infinite Size. Bruno Whittle

Richard P. Feynman. I'm trying to figure out what to say, when the guy says to her, "I'm, uh, studying massage. Could I practice on you?

YOGA is all about Yoga is concerned with your total being, with your roots. It is not philosophical. So with Patanjali we will not be

The Development of Knowledge and Claims of Truth in the Autobiography In Code. When preparing her project to enter the Esat Young Scientist

Lecture 4: Deductive Validity

ABSOLUTISM. The absolutist believes mathematics is:

Pojman, Louis P. Introduction to Philosophy: Classical and Contemporary Readings. 3rd Ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2004.

Absolutism. The absolutist believes mathematics is:

Grade 7 Math Connects Suggested Course Outline for Schooling at Home 132 lessons

Diocese of Niagara. Anglican Church of Canada. A Beginner s Guide to the. Anglican Church

Lesson 10 Notes. Machine Learning. Intro. Joint Distribution

Learning Skills Centre

MITOCW 3. V: Recursive Structures and Processes

Ep #130: Lessons from Jack Canfield. Full Episode Transcript. With Your Host. Brooke Castillo. The Life Coach School Podcast with Brooke Castillo

Introduction to Inference

Cash Register Exercise

Que sera sera. Robert Stone

A Romp through the Foothills of Logic: Session 2

PHIL-176: DEATH. Lecture 15 - The Nature of Death (cont.); Believing You Will Die [March 6, 2007]

>> Marian Small: I was talking to a grade one teacher yesterday, and she was telling me

Lecture Notes on Classical Logic

=EQUALS= Center for. A Club of Investigation and Discovery. Published by: autosocratic PRESS Copyright 2011 Michael Lee Round

Kanga Joe. Story 1. The King s Garden. Fruit of the Spirit: love

Grade 6 correlated to Illinois Learning Standards for Mathematics

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Logicola Truth Evaluation Exercises

Artificial Intelligence Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Curriculum Guide for Pre-Algebra

TwiceAround Podcast Episode 7: What Are Our Biases Costing Us? Transcript

A Beginner s Guide to the Anglican Church

6.00 Introduction to Computer Science and Programming, Fall 2008

GUIDE THE GROUP INTO DISCOVERING WHAT THE BIBLE SAYS AND MEANS.

Richard van de Lagemaat Relative Values A Dialogue

RSA Animate - Drive: The surprising truth about what motivates us

Probability Foundations for Electrical Engineers Prof. Krishna Jagannathan Department of Electrical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Shahriar Shahriari William Polk Russell Professor of Mathematics. Pomona College Convocation 2010 August 31, 2010

Logical Omniscience in the Many Agent Case

Georgia Quality Core Curriculum

6.00 Introduction to Computer Science and Programming, Fall 2008

In Defence Of Reductionism In Ethics 1. Frank Jackson

Macmillan/McGraw-Hill SCIENCE: A CLOSER LOOK 2011, Grade 4 Correlated with Common Core State Standards, Grade 4

175 Chapter CHAPTER 23: Probability

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

Existential Claims and Platonism

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Frank Montano, Red Cliff Ojibwe, Wisconsin

Difference between Science and Religion? A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding...

MITOCW watch?v=a8fbmj4nixy

Virtual Logic Number and Imagination

GOD, CHANCE AND PURPOSE

Death: Lecture 4 Transcript

Parts of Speech. Underline the complete subject and verb; circle any objects.

Welcome to the SeaComm Federal Credit Union podcast, your guide to financial information and what's going on at your credit union.

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

A Beginner s Guide to the Anglican Church

Calisthenics October 1982

How I became interested in foundations of mathematics.

The Wealthy Mind: The Not-So-Obvious Secrets To Guarantee Health, Wealth, Happin: The Not-So- Obvious Secrets To Guarantee Health, Wealth, Happiness

Secret Rapture 3 Days of Darkness, Our Discernment Process, True or False?

WITH CYNTHIA PASQUELLA TRANSCRIPT BO EASON CONNECTION: HOW YOUR STORY OF STRUGGLE CAN SET YOU FREE

PROSPECTIVE TEACHERS UNDERSTANDING OF PROOF: WHAT IF THE TRUTH SET OF AN OPEN SENTENCE IS BROADER THAN THAT COVERED BY THE PROOF?

McDougal Littell High School Math Program. correlated to. Oregon Mathematics Grade-Level Standards

UNIVALENT FOUNDATIONS

Trust in God, Pt. 1 Wayne Matthews February 14, Welcome to this Sabbath, brethren.

Acts Of God: Why Does God Allow So Much Pain? By Bob Russell, Kyle Idleman READ ONLINE

High Power Manifesting by Richard Lee McKim Jr.

How do We Know God Exists

The Birthday Problem

Transcription:

1997 2009, Millennium Mathematics Project, University of Cambridge. Permission is granted to print and copy this page on paper for non commercial use. For other uses, including electronic redistribution, please contact us. Sep 2001 Features Friends and strangers by Imre Leader In 1928, Frank Ramsey was wrestling with a problem in mathematical logic. To solve it, it seemed to him, he needed to show that the mathematical systems he was studying would always have a certain amount of order in them. At first sight, the systems were free to be as disorderly as they liked, but Ramsey thought that even in the most unruly, the sheer size of the system should force parts of it to exhibit some kind of order. In proving that his intuition was correct he invented a new branch of mathematics, which is now known as Ramsey Theory. He read the resulting paper to the London Mathematical Society, but died, at the age of 26, before it was published in their Proceedings. Ramsey Theory still has applications in the study of logic. But it is also a very attractive subject in itself, since its basic ideas can be understood very easily, and involve drawing colourful pictures. On the other hand, it's also an active research area, since it raises some spectacularly difficult questions. When the last round of Fields Medals were announced in 1998 the Fields is mathematics' most prestigious award, its nearest equivalent to a Nobel prize one of them went to the British mathematician Tim Gowers, in part for his work in Ramsey theory. In this article we'll see that Ramsey Theory has the ability to ask even very simple looking questions which have defied all attempts to answer them so far. Order from chaos The fundamental kind of question Ramsey theory asks is: can one always find order in chaos? If so, how much? Just how large a slice of chaos do we need to be sure to find a particular amount of order in it? (Incidentally, when talk about "chaos" in this article we just mean something disordered or jumbled. There's no connection with the technical meaning of "chaos" in mathematics, which is to do with dynamical systems.) Friends and strangers 1

That sounds like an odd question, here is a concrete example. Suppose there is a room with six people in it. We are interested in whether people in this room know each other or not. Let's call two people friends if they know each other, strangers if they don't. We're looking for examples of order, and clearly the most orderly case would be if the six are either all friends, or all strangers. Unfortunately the people have been chosen at random, so there will probably be a jumble of friends and strangers in the room. Suppose we draw lines joining every pair of people in the room and colour them blue if the two are friends, red if they are strangers. Then the result might look something like this: This picture mathematicians call it a graph looks totally chaotic. We certainly don't have six friends or six strangers! But we can still ask: can we at least find three people in the room, who are either all friends or all strangers? Put another way, can we find a blue triangle (three friends), or a red triangle (three strangers)? In this case the answer is "yes". Charlie, Evelyn and Fred are all strangers to each other. But what if the original graph had been different? Would we always have been able to find an orderly set of three people? Before reading on, you can try an experiment to answer this question. Below is a graph showing six people. You can decide, by colouring the lines, which are friends and which are strangers. Can you colour all the lines blue or red so that no triangle is monochromatic (all one colour, from the Greek monos, "single", and chroma, "colour"), or does a monochromatic triangle always appear? Friends and strangers 2

You can see an interactive version of this picture by downloading Flash Player 5 and ensuring that Javascript is enabled, and then reloading this page. It seems that, with six points, there is always a monochromatic triangle. But how would we prove this is true? One way would be simply to list all possible colourings, and check each one in turn. Unfortunately there are over 30,000 possible colourings, so this proof would be more than a little tedious. Luckily it turns out that we can prove it much more easily. First we choose any point, and note that five lines come out of it one to each of the other five points: With five lines, there must be at least three of one colour at least three red lines or at least three blue lines. Let's suppose there are three red lines (if there were three blue lines instead, the argument would be exactly the same but with "red" and "blue" swapped). So we have four points like this: What colours are the three remaining lines? Well, if even one of them is red, then it makes a red triangle together with point A (left). And if not, the three together make a blue triangle (right): Friends and strangers 3

Either way, we have our monochromatic triangle. Would 5 points be enough? We've proved that with six points (or more, of course), there must always be a monochromatic triangle in other words that with six people or more, there must be three friends or three strangers. This suggests the question, "How many people do we need, to be sure of finding either three friends, or three strangers?" This is our first example of a Ramsey number, and is written as R(3,3). We've seen that six people is certainly enough; in other words, R(3,3) isn't any larger than 6. But would five points have been enough in other words, is it the case that any group of five people will have either three friends or three strangers? The graph below with five points shows that the answer is no, since it has no monochromatic triangle: This shows that R(3,3) cannot be less than 6. Taking these two results together proves that R(3,3)=6. Looking for more order Now that we have understood what a Ramsey number is, we can try to find other examples. For example, R(5,5) would tell us how many people are needed to be sure of finding either five mutual friends or five mutual strangers. Of course, we don't yet know that there is always an answer: perhaps no amount of people will guarantee, say, 10 friends or 10 strangers. (In fact we'll prove at the end of this article that there always is an answer, even though we usually don't know what it is!) To make sure you've followed thus far, you might like to consider the following two questions: 1. What is R(2,5)? 2. If we know R(a,b), what can we say about R(b,a)? Check the answers before reading on. Now let's be more ambitious: we want to find four people who are either all friends or all strangers. In our brand new notation, we want to find R(4,4). For the moment, though, this is too hard, so we'll content ourselves with something a little easier, namely finding R(3,4). Would 5 points be enough? 4

Finding R(3,4) How many points do we need, to guarantee that we can find either three points all connected by blue lines, orfour points all connected by red lines in other words, one of the following? Firstly, we claim that 10 points is certainly enough. Let's try to prove this. Suppose we have 10 points, joined with red and blue lines in the usual way. Choose a point, and note that 9 lines come out of it. There must either be at least 6 red ones, or at least 4 blue ones (otherwise there won't be 9 in all!) So we are in one of these two possibilities (I'll only draw the lines we're interested in): Case (i) Case (ii) Let's look at case (i) first. What colour are the lines in (i) other than the blue ones shown? If even one of them is blue, we have a blue triangle, in other words three friends (left); if not, they are all red and we have four strangers (right). Either way we are done: Finding R(3,4) 5

So now let's look at case (ii). There are 6 points (besides A) there. And we have already discovered that R(3,3)=6, so of these 6 points, 3 must form either a blue triangle or a red triangle, putting us in one of these two cases: In the case on the left we have our three friends, and in the case on the right our four strangers. So once more we are done. This argument has put a bound on R(3,4): we know it exists and it cannot be more than 10. But it could still be less than 10. In fact, by a cunning variation on the argument above, we can show that 9 points will do. Eight points aren't enough On the other hand, 8 points would not be enough, as the following diagram shows. (All the blue lines are shown; all the remaining lines are assumed to be red.) No 3 points form a blue triangle, and no 4 points are all connected with red lines. So now we know that R(3,4)=9. Also, as we saw earlier, we can exchange the places of "red" and "blue", so the same argument shows that R(4,3)=9. Finding R(4,4) Now we can use this knowledge to find R(4,4). First, we claim that 18 people is enough to guarantee either four friends or four strangers. The method of proof should begin to look familiar by now. Say we have a graph with 18 points, and lines between them coloured blue or red. Take one point. 17 lines come out of it, so at least 9 of them must be one colour red, say: Eight points aren't enough 6

We already know that R(4,3)=9, so among those 9 points there must be either four friends in which case we're done or three strangers. In the latter case, since all three are strangers to A, we have four strangers including A. So we have either four friends or four strangers, which is just what we claimed. Once again, we have found a bound: R(4,4) certainly exists and it is at most 18. This time, by luck, the bound happens to be the best possible: 17 points aren't enough to guarantee a monochromatic set of four points. To show this, we need to find a graph with 17 points with no such monochromatic set! This has been done, but as the graph is big and not very illuminating, I'll omit it here. As a result we know that R(4,4)=18. Bigger Ramsey numbers With a bit of work, we were able to find R(4,4) exactly. But proving it existed was not so hard. The final step showed that we could put a bound on R(4,4) as long as we had bounds for R(3,4) and R(4,3). These also broke down into simpler steps: we can bound R(3,4) as long as we can bound R(3,3) and R(2,4), and so on. In mathematical notation, we know that R(a,b) exists as long as R(a 1,b) and R(a,b 1) both exist. Also we've already seen that R(a,2) and R(2,a) always exist (they're simply equal to a). So to show that, for instance, R(5,5) exists will break down into a series of steps, as in the diagram: Bigger Ramsey numbers 7

Each case breaks down into the two cases below it, and we've already done the cases in the bottom row. So R(5,5) certainly exists, and similarly for R(6,6) or for that matter any R(a,b). This is Ramsey's Theorem, and it tells us that however much orderliness we want, we can find it as long as the graph we are given is big enough. However, it's important to remember that this method doesn't find the exact Ramsey numbers for us, even though it enables us to find bounds. Nobody knows So what is the true value of R(5,5)? The answer is: nobody knows! In fact, very few Ramsey R(a,b) numbers are known (with a and b both bigger than 2). We've already seen that R(3,3)=6, R(4,3)=9 and R(4,4)=18. Besides this only three more values are known: R(5,3)=14, R(6,3)=18 and R(7,3)=23. The most we can say about R(5,5) with our present knowledge is that it is somewhere between 42 and 55. How can it be so difficult to get an accurate value? Arguments like the ones I've used in this article allow us to find upper bounds on the Ramsey numbers we're interested in for example, we saw quite easily that R(4,3) could not be bigger than 10. But to show that it could not be as small as 8, we had to construct explicitly a graph with 8 points, as a counterexample. The problem is that we are looking for examples of order, so the best counterexamples will usually have lots of disorder they will look random. This makes it hard or impossible to find a "rule" that gives good counterexamples. Anything constructed by rule will probably have too much order in it. Also, our upper bounds may be too high, but how will we ever prove it? Perhaps by examining all the possibilities on a computer? But a simple example will show this will never work. Say we wanted to show that R(5,5) is at most 54 in other words, to show that 54 points will always guarantee the existence of 5 points all connected together by lines of one colour. We would have to look at all the possible ways of colouring lines between 54 points either red or blue. How many ways are there? First we need to know the number of lines, which, by a well known formula, is (54 53) / 2 = 1431. Each line can be coloured either red or blue, so the number of possible colourings is 2 2 2... 2, where the number of 2's multiplied together is 1431 in mathematical notation this is 2 1431 or over 10 400. This number is far, far bigger than the number of particles in the known Universe (about 10 80 ). So there is no chance of even the fastest computer imaginable ever finishing such a search. This is a puzzle we may never know the answer to. About the author Friends and strangers Imre Leader is a fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge and a lecturer in the Department of Pure Mathematics and Mathematical Statistics, Cambridge University. Nobody knows 8

Plus is part of the family of activities in the Millennium Mathematics Project, which also includes the NRICH and MOTIVATE sites. Nobody knows 9