Review of Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics by Thomas Hofweber Billy Dunaway University of Missouri St Louis

Similar documents
1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Replies to Giuliano Torrengo, Dan Zeman and Vasilis Tsompanidis

The Question of Metaphysics

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Conceptual idealism without ontological idealism: why idealism is true after all

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

What God Could Have Made

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks

Unrestricted Quantification and Reality: Reply to Kim. Takashi Yagisawa. California State University, Northridge

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Quine: Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE SEVEN MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings *

SOME RADICAL CONSEQUENCES OF GEACH'S LOGICAL THEORIES

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Coordination Problems

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

1 Existence: Essays in Ontology. By Peter van Inwagen. Cambridge University Press, viii pp cloth, paper.

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

What am I? An immaterial thing: the case for dualism

Russell: On Denoting

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Yuval Dolev, Time and Realism, MIT Press, 2007

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

That -clauses as existential quantifiers

Russell on Plurality

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Logic is Metaphysics

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

Revisiting the Socrates Example

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

5 A Modal Version of the

August 8, 1997, Church s thesis, formal definitions of informal notions, limits of formal systems, Turing machine, recursive functions - BIG

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

IT is frequently taken for granted, both by people discussing logical

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

How Subjective Fact Ties Language to Reality

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Accommodation, Inference, Generics & Pejoratives

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Russell on Descriptions

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

(1) A phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything; e.g., 'the present King of France'.

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Quantificational logic and empty names

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Bob Hale: Necessary Beings

Prior, Berkeley, and the Barcan Formula. James Levine Trinity College, Dublin

(1) a phrase may be denoting, and yet not denote anything e.g. the present King of France

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

INHISINTERESTINGCOMMENTS on my paper "Induction and Other Minds" 1

Aboutness and Justification

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Theories of propositions

Transcription:

Review of Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics by Thomas Hofweber Billy Dunaway University of Missouri St Louis Are there are numbers, propositions, or properties? These are questions that are traditionally at the heart of metaphysics. But they appear to have depressingly easy answers. Each of the following innocent statements appears to entail an affirmative answer to a metaphysical question: The number of moons of Jupiter is four. It is true that Madagascar is in Africa. Fido has the property of being a dog. This is because each entails the metaphysically loaded claim that there is a number, a truth, or a property. The innocent statements are not particularly controversial. Everyone agrees that Jupiter has four moons, that Madagascar is in Africa, and that Fido is a dog. Metaphysics has a reputation as an obscure and (at best) difficult discipline. But it appears to be remarkably easy, if the loaded statements are answers to central metaphysical questions, and are serled by ordinary innocent facts. (20 ff) These arguments are not unfamiliar. One might expect that all of the main responses, and the considerations for and against them, to be well-known. In Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics, Thomas Hofweber a refreshing new take, supported by subtle considerations not only from within traditional metaphysics, but also linguistics and psychology. Hofweber s central claim is that innocent statements do entail what we called their metaphysically loaded counterparts, but these counterparts are not, in fact, metaphysically loaded. When we say that there is a number of moons that Jupiter has, these are statements with a quantifier in natural language. But there are, according to Hofweber, two readings of this sentence. One reading of the quantifier (expressed by the determiner a ), is what Hofweber dubs the domain conditions reading of the quantifier. It asserts that, among the domain of objects, one of them is the number of moons of Jupiter. (59) The other is the inferential-role reading. Its meaning is determined, as its name suggests, solely by the role it plays in stating generalizations. Any true sentence of the form t is F

where the term t occupies the grammatical position of a subject entails something is F where the quantifier has its inferential-role reading. Moreover when the quantified sentence is true on its inferential-role reading, it follows that there is some true sentence of English of the form t is F. (72) Obviously it marers a great deal to Hofweber that the domain conditions and inferential-role readings of the quantifier are not equivalent. So Hofweber argues for this. One case involves empty names. It is true that Santa Claus gives presents. But does it follow that someone gives presents? Only on the inferential-role reading: this follows from the semantics of someone on its inferential-role reading, plus the fact that 'Santa Claus is a term of English in subject position. But not on the domain conditions reading of the quantifier: there is no one in the domain of objects who is Santa Claus. (68) The more interesting case for metaphysics involves terms in subject-position that are not even in the business of trying to refer to something. This is the situation with number-terms like four, Hofweber argues. These are not, in English, proper names which arempt to refer to an object: witness cases where four cannot be replaced with the referring expression the number four while preserving grammaticality. (115) Nevertheless our innocent statement with four in subject position will entail that there is some number of moons which Jupiter has so long as we use the inferential-role quantifier. The upshot is that, on one reading, it is true that there is a number. But this is the inferential-role reading and, for a variety of reasons, this does not tell us anything about ontology. (109) Parts of this picture are hard to dispute. But one wonders how much of a role the non-referential character of number-terms has to do with the force of the arguments from innocent to loaded statements. Presumably we could have spoken a language where number-terms behave syntactically just like proper names. In this case they would be in the business of referring. And it is natural to think that we would still find the inferences to quantified, apparently loaded statements compelling. (Few would want to say that we find these inferences compelling only because of some tacit awareness of the non-referential character of number-terms in English). Perhaps we should pause to ask how heavily a solution to ontological questions should rely on the linguistic peculiarities of English. If we follow this far, Hofweber invites us to accept an additional conclusion that, if correct, is striking. This is the claim that there are no numbers on the domain conditions

reading. And this follows from the fact that these loaded statements are true on the inferential-role reading of the quantifier. This is striking because we started with a claim about polysemy in the quantifier to the effect that it has multiple non-equivalent readings. We should not expect, in general, for an affirmative answer to one reading of a question containing a polysemous term to imply a negative answer to that question on a different reading. For instance man is polysemous, designating either the species homo sapiens (as in mankind ), or adult male humans. But we would not ordinarily infer from the claim that Seamus is a man (in the first sense) that Seamus is not a man (in the second sense). However Hofweber has an argument that we should make the analogous inference about loaded statements on the two readings of the quantifier. He applies this in detail to loaded statements about numbers (110), but the same point applies to loaded statements about properties and propositions. Here is the argument, in summary form. Number-terms, like the number 2, are not referring expressions. A domain-conditions reading of the statement there are numbers is true only if there are numbers in the domain of quantification. But: since the number 2 does not pick out or denote any object, whatever objects there may be, none of them is the number 2. So among all the objects, none is the number 2. (111) Notably, the central premise in this argument is linguistic: it concerns the semantic function of number-terms, which Hofweber argues for at length. The conclusion is metaphysical: the domain of quantification (unrestrictedly) contains no numbers. Of course, the linguistic premise won t rule out the an ontology of unnamed (in English) number-like entities, but the argument is one worth pondering. There is, on this view, a close relationship between existence (in the sense conveyed by the domain-conditions quantifier) and expressibility. Hofweber is sensitive to this. Chapter 9 is dedicated to this type of quantification over properties we don t have a term for. The stock of terms in the language we actually speak is prery impoverished. Perhaps there is a grad student in some lab who is right now whose sole focus is investigating how to make a drink that has the property of tasting berer than Diet Pepsi. So we can truly say that there is a property the grad student is investigating, namely the property of tasting berer than Diet Pepsi. But a speaker of Ancient Greek Jimmy, say would not speak a language that contains a term for Diet Pepsi. It appears that Jimmy will not be able to truly say, with an inferential-role quantifier, a sentence that means the same as our sentence there is a property the grad student is investigating. Presumably we present-day English speakers are in the same position with respect to some other properties. (233)

Ancient Greek may not have a term for Diet Pepsi, but this does not mean that there is no sense in which Jimmy s inferential-role quantifier generalizes over being Diet Pepsi. There is an extension of the Jimmy s language which includes variables ranging over everything that exists at some time including the Diet Pepsi in the vending machine outside my office. I could walk to the vending machine and point to the Diet Pepsi, saying the grad student is investigating the property of tasting berer than this, and thereby say the same thing as an English sentence containing Diet Pepsi. Hofweber s extension of the Greek s language, which is supplemented with variables ranging over objects, is supposed to have the same expressive power. (235) Similar extensions allegedly allow for inferential-role quantifiers to generalize over all the properties we could conceivably want to talk about. It is not clear that this is so. Merely by demonstrating a Diet Pepsi and saying tasting berer than this I do not thereby express the property of tasting berer than a Diet Pepsi. (For instance if I take a sip from an expired borle of Diet Pepsi, I not commenting on Diet Pepsis in general if I say anything else would have the property of tasting berer than this.) Nor will we arrive at adequate truth conditions for the inferential-role quantifier by simply adding further references to additional Diet Pepsis. (The expression being either this, or this, or this, where one demonstrates every Diet Pepsi that ever has or will come into existence, will not necessarily be equivalent to being a Diet Pepsi.) The method of extending impoverished languages to include variables ranging over existing objects is not an incidental component of Hofweber s overall view. He accepts an ontology of ordinary objects, and hence domain-conditions quantification over objects (Chapter 7). But since he wishes to deny domain-conditions quantification over numbers, properties, and propositions, he needs to specify adequate truth conditions for an inferential-role quantifier over them, using only domain-conditions quantification over objects. This is a difficult task. The overall ambitions of his project place restrictions on the resources he has to make inferential-role quantifiers do the job he has employed them for. Readers of Ontology and the Ambitions of Metaphysics will nonetheless be treated to a constant flow of useful insights about important philosophical questions concerning ontology and quantification (Chapters 1-4). These are followed by careful argumentation geared toward providing Hofweber s own answers and solutions (Chapters 5-11). The book closes with reflections on metametaphysical issues (Chapters 12-13), situating his preferred solutions to the metaphysical puzzles in his book with alongside other fashionable approaches to these same issues. Hofweber might not succeed in dissuading metaphysicians from plying their trade with the notions of fundamentality and ground, convincing them instead that they should do ontology in the old-school way, with first-order quantifiers souped up with Hofweberian distinctions between different

readings. But he has certainly provided a sparse alternative that deserves to be taken seriously, even by those who do not share his skepticism.