Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Similar documents
THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000

Introduction: Taking Consciousness Seriously. 1. Two Concepts of Mind I. FOUNDATIONS

Materialism and the Metaphysics of Modality

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

BOOK REVIEWS. The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 4 (October 2002)

Annotated Bibliography. seeking to keep the possibility of dualism alive in academic study. In this book,

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Philosophical Review.

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Week Eleven: Objections to Jackson 1. The Objection From Linguistic Ignorance

DECONSTRUCTING NEW WAVE MATERIALISM

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

DUALISM VS. MATERIALISM I

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Chapter 11 CHALMERS' THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. and yet non-reductive approach to consciousness. First, we will present the hard problem

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

Minds and Machines spring Hill and Nagel on the appearance of contingency, contd spring 03

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Philosophical Review.

Philip Goff a a University of Hertfordshire. To link to this article:

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Coordination Problems

Debate on the mind and scientific method (continued again) on

Chalmers on Epistemic Content. Alex Byrne, MIT

A Posteriori Necessities

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

David Chalmers on Mind and Consciousness Richard Brown Forthcoming in Andrew Bailey (ed) Philosophy of Mind: The Key Thinkers.

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Property Dualism and the Knowledge Argument: Are Qualia Really a Problem for Physicalism? Ronald Planer Rutgers Univerity

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

The Possibility of Materialism

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCES, PROPERTIES, AND STRUCTURES

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

What God Could Have Made

To appear in J. Greco, ed., Philosophers and their Critics: Ernest Sosa, Oxford: Blackwell. Sosa on Abilities, Concepts and Externalism

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Varieties of Apriority

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

The Phenomenal Concept Strategy

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

TWO DIMENSIONAL MODAL ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

The knowledge argument

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 5. (May, 1986), pp

Reply to Kirk and Melnyk

A note on science and essentialism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Thinking About Consciousness

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Constructing the World

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Here s a very dumbed down way to understand why Gödel is no threat at all to A.I..

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Experiences Don t Sum

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Minds and Machines spring The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited spring 03

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Review of Torin Alter and Sven Walter (eds.) Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal Knowledge: New Essays on Consciousness and Physicalism

Conceivability, Possibility and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

The Unsoundness of Arguments From Conceivability

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

ZOMBIES, EPIPHENOMENALISM, AND PERSONAL EXPLANATIONS: A TENSION IN MORELAND S ARGUMENT FROM CONSCIOUSNESS

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Hitoshi NAGAI (Nihon University) Why Isn t Consciousness Real? (2) Day 2: Why Are We Zombies?

Skepticism and Internalism

Transcription:

Review: Concepts and Consciousness Author(s): Stephen Yablo Reviewed work(s): The Conscious Mind by David Chalmers Source: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 59, No. 2, (Jun., 1999), pp. 455-463 Published by: International Phenomenological Society Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2653683 Accessed: 15/07/2008 20:42 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showpublisher?publishercode=ips. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org

Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LIX, No. 2, June 1999 Concepts and Consciousness STEPHEN YABLO Massachusetts Institute of Technology I. The Conscious Mind is a hugely likable book. Perceptive, candid, and instructive page by page, the work as a whole sets out a large and uplifting vision with cheeringly un-dover-beach-ish implications for "our place in the universe." A book that you can't helping wanting to believe as much as you can't help wanting to believe this one doesn't come along every day. It is with real regret that I proceed to the story of why belief would not come. Almost everything in The Conscious Mind turns on a single claim. The claim is that there can be zombie worlds: worlds physically like our own but devoid of consciousness. Zombie worlds provide a counterexample to psychophysical supervenience; which refutes physicalism; which sets the stage for Chalmers's "naturalistic dualism" with its contingent correlational laws; which comes scarily close to casting consciousness as an epiphenomenal byproduct of its physical basis; which startles us into a measure of open-mindedness about Chalmers's "way out," in which the by-product role is abandoned for a powerful new position as the physical's intrinsic realizer; which sets up the panpsychic speculations of the final chapters. Zombie worlds are possible because they seem possible; one can conceive a scenario in which, with no physical provocation whatever, the phenomenal lights blink out. Any argument in this style has got, of course, to come to terms with Kripke's treatment of conceivability in Naming and Necessity. But Kripke can seem to be teaching a "good news/bad news" lesson about modal intuition with favorable implications for Chalmers's case. II. The bad news is that conceivability evidence, particularly of a "conceptual" or "a priori" sort, is highly fallible. Very often one finds a statement E conceivable, when as a matter of fact, E-worlds cannot be. So it is with the conceivability of water in the absence of hydrogen. The good news is that the failures always take a certain form. A thinker who (erroneously) conceives E as possible is correctly registering the possibility of something, and mistaking the possibility of that for the possibility of E. There are illusions of possibility, if you like, but no outright delusions or hallucinations. BOOK SYMPOSIUM 455

The good news is important because it gives a way of living with the bad. Conceivability is not per se proof of possibility, but that is what it becomes in the absence of an E* such that it was really E* that was possible, and whose possibility was misread as the possibility of E. What is the relation between E and E* whereby the one's possibility is so easily misread as the possibility of the other? The quick answer is that E* maps out the way the proposition that E is presented in thought; it is, for short, a presentation of E. The usual sort of presentation takes name-like expressions in E and replace them with descriptive and/or demonstrative phrases that, as Kripke says, fixes their reference; thus, "water" might be replaced by "the predominant local clear drinkable stuff," or (for short) "the watery stuff." All that really matters, though, is that E* delivers the propositional content of E as a function of the world of utterance; what E actually says, if the actual world is w, is what E* says about w.1 III. These ideas can be called "textbook Kripkeanism" or TK. A signal contribution of The Conscious Mind is to have laid out TK in something like canonical terms. The details are of course different. Where Kripke had two statements E and E*, Chalmers has just E, but with two meanings: a primary intension IEI1 = the set of E-verifying worlds = the set of worlds that, considered as actual, make E true, and a secondary one IEl2 = the set of E-satisfying worlds, or simply E-worlds, = the set of worlds that, considered as counterfactual, E truly describes. These intensions-the second amounting to what Kripkeans would call E's propositional content, the first to the propositional content of E*-can be seen as arrived at compositionally from the intensions of E's component terms. The reason that "water = H20" has a necessary secondary intension and a contingent primary one is that "water" and "H20" agree in secondary intension only. With "water = the watery stuff," it's the other way around; the primary intension is necessary, because "water" and "the watery stuff' co-refer in all worlds-considered-as-actual, but the secondary intension is not, because a counterfactual stuff (Putnam's XYZ) describable as "the watery stuff' may not be describable as "water." 1 Better, what it says about w on a referential reading. 456 STEPHEN YABLO

How does any of this support TK? Well, together with the two kinds of intension we have two kinds of possibility. Conceptual possibility2 "comes down to the possible truth of a statement when evaluated according to the primary intensions involved...the primary intensions of "water" and "H20" differ, so it is [conceptually] possible...that water is not H20" (132). Socalled conceivability errors occur because this is not the kind of possibility that licenses the claim that "it could have been that E," or hence the kind that interests the metaphysician. "'[M]etaphysical possibility' comes down to the possible truth of a statement when evaluated according to the secondary intensions involved...the secondary intensions of 'water' and 'H20' are the same, so it is metaphysically necessary that water is H20" (132). Now, if "conceivability error" reflects nothing more than the mismatch just noted, then one may wonder what all the fuss was about. The world we imagine is real enough; our mistake is only to think that it is an E-satisfying world as opposed to an E-verifying one. Which means that the textbook Kripkean had it right all along. Whether we are accurate or not in conceiving E as metaphysically possible, there is a genuine possibility we are picking up on, viz. E's conceptual possibility = the nonemptiness of the primary intension. Should it happen that the primary intension is, or entails, the secondary one, even this "descriptional" sort of error is ruled out; conceivability now becomes decisive evidence that it could have been that E. IV. How well TK corresponds to any actual belief of Kripke's is something I take no stand on. What I do think is that TK is not right. The good news that conceivability ensures metaphysical possibility in the absence of an obfuscating primary "presentation" is too good to be true. A half a century ago, the philosopher Charles Hartshorne put a neat twist on the ontological argument for God's existence.3 That existence is part of God's essence does not itself establish theism; it shows only that if existence were possible for God, he would exist necessarily. But God is certainly not impossible, for he is "coherently conceivable." And if not impossible, he is possible, and so by our earlier reasoning necessary, and so actual. A response that was made even at the time is that Hartshorne is punning on "possible." What God's conceivability establishes is his conceptual possibility; the premise needed to establish his necessity is that he really could have existed. Only if there is a world w that really contains him can we say: God exists in w, so his essence is satisfied there, so he exists in every world, this one included. 2 Chalmers calls it "logical", as in "[the] distinction between 'logical' and 'metaphysical' possibility stemming from the Kripkean cases" (67). This causes some confusion, since Kripke uses "logical" and "metaphysical" essentially interchangeably. 3 Man's Vision of God (New York: Harper & Row, 1941). BOOK SYMPOSIUM 457

All of this is very familiar; the reason for mentioning it is that given TK, it fails to block the argument. A statement's conceivability suffices for its metaphysical possibility except in those special cases where all we have cottoned onto is an 0E11-world passing itself off as El2. And it is hard to think where in "there is a being whose essence includes existence" we are to look for the expression whose primary and secondary intensions differ, or hence what the genuine possibility is that we mistake for the possibility of an essentially existent being. To make matters worse, another thing that seems clearly conceivable is that there shouldfail to be a being whose essence includes existence; it seems conceivable, in fact, that there shouldn't be anything whatsoever. Where are we to look for a presentation of "there isn't anything" such that it is really this presentation that is possible, and whose possibility is mistaken for the possibility of emptiness? (Some die-hard may want to maintain that emptiness is itself presented by way of a contingent reference-fixer whose satisfaction in w by a form of non-emptiness misleads us into thinking of w as empty. Surely emptiness is not that kind of concept.) For the same reason as before, then, we should conclude that Hartshorne's God could have failed to exist. And now we have talked ourselves into a contradiction. TK makes Hartshorne's God metaphysically contingent; yet it is part of the concept of this God to exist in every world or none. The same problem arguably arises for other modally extreme entities: numbers, pure sets, transcendent universals, and so on. To go by TK, these are worse than enigmatic. They are out and out paradoxical.4 V. How do we apply TK to the case where E is "things are physically like so [insert here a full physical description of reality] but devoid of consciousness"? The strategy closest to Kripke is to say that "with consciousness, the primary and secondary intensions coincide...if something feels like a conscious experience, even in some counterfactual world, it is a conscious experience" (133). What if someone disagrees (as they have disagreed with Kripke), insisting that the way the reference of "consciousness" is fixed can potentially come apart from the state itself? Maybe "consciousness" stands for a condition of the brain that (although implicated in our experiences) could in principle occur without phenomenal accompaniment. This wouldn't necessarily bother Chalmers; his basic and underlying point, which he repeats again and again, is meant to be without prejudice to the proper semantics for phenomenal terms. We surely conceive some kind of 4 A reply Chalmers gave in conversation was that only the nonexistence (not the existence) of an Anselmian God was ultimately conceivable; and vice versa for the numbers. If he is right, then TK gives the same sort of evidence for atheism and platonism as for antiphysicalism. 458 STEPHEN YABLO

world when we find zombies conceivable; and that world constitutes a counterexample to physicalist supervenience regardless:...nothing about Kripke's a posteriori necessity renders any [conceptually] possible worlds impossible. It simply tells us that some of them are misdescribed... if there is a conceivable world that is physically identical to ours but which lacks certain positive features of our world, then no considerations about the designation of terms such as "consciousness" can do anything to rule out [its] metaphysical possibility.. the relevant possible world clearly lacks somnething...the mere possibility of such a world, no matter how it is described, is all the argument [against physicalism] needs to succeed (134). This is textbook Kripkeanism at its purest and best: even the illusion of zombies is a correct perception of something, and that something is all we need to put physicalistic supervenience to rest. VI. According to Chalmers, the difference between conceptual and metaphysical possibility is all at the level of statements; where worlds are concerned, the two come to the same. If this is granted, then the following argument looks strong: (a) it is conceptually possible that there be zombies, so (b) zombie worlds are conceptually possible, so (c) zombie worlds are metaphysically possible. But wait. Although (b), on a natural reading, follows from (a), and (c) follows from a natural reading of (b), the two readings don't agree. What (a) supports is (b') it is conceptually possible that there be zombie worlds. (If you can conceive zombies, then you can conceive them plus their surrounding worlds.) To get (c), though, you need (b') there are conceptually possible zombie worlds. The de dicto possibility of zombie worlds asserted by (b') would seem to fall well short of the de re possibility asserted by (b'). The principal charm, as I see it, of Chalmers's argument is that he has found is a way of reaping the rewards of this modal fallacy without having actually to commit it. He maintains, remember, that conceptual possibility "comes down to the possible truth of a statement when evaluated according to the primary intensions involved" (132). From this it follows that BOOK SYMPOSIUM 459

CP If it is conceptually possible that E, then E's primary intension contains at least one world.5 And CP allows him to reach (b') directly from (a): (a) it is conceptually possible that there be zombies, so (by CP) (a) there are worlds in the primary intension of "there are zombies," so (a") there are worlds which if actual make "there are zombies" true, so (b') there are conceptually possible zombie worlds. It is CP that saves the argument from being a straightforward modal fallacy, by guaranteeing a witnessing world. CP is also a crucial prop in the argument for textbook Kripkeanism; indeed if conceptual possibility is equated with robust conceptual conceivability, it has TK as an immediate consequence. VII. Why believe CP? Nobody doubts that a primary-intension-like notion has shown itself to have some predictive value in this area. But the inference from (1) to (1') presupposes that there is no way whatever of arranging for conceptual coherence short of including a world in the primary intension. Here is my best shot at a supporting argument. Start with Chalmers's idea that we can "think of the primary and secondary intensions as the a priori and a posterior aspects of meaning, respectively" (62). What is understanding if not grasping "the a priori aspect of meaning"? A speaker's understanding of E is thus given by the (actual-world) conditions under which E is true, as encoded in the set of E-verifying worlds. Now, clearly, that E is conceptually possible implies that a speaker's understanding of it-her grasp of the relevant set of worlds-leaves it open that E might be true. This would not be left open, however, if E was verified by no worlds whatsoever. So we can conclude that E's primary intension is nonempty. Explicitly: 1. E is conceptually possible. (P) 2. The speaker's understanding of E leaves it open that E might be true. (1) 3. Understanding is knowing truth-conditions: how truth-value depends on worldly context. (P) 5 "Conceptual possibility" stands in CP for the intuitive notion; the gap between intuitive conceivability and Chalmers's theoretical apparatus has to be bridged somewhere, and I am putting the bridge here. 460 STEPHEN YABLO

4. Knowing how E's truth-value depends on worldly context leaves it open that E might be true. (2, 3) 5. E is true in some such context: some possible w considered as actual. (4) 6. E is true in w, considered as actual, iff w is an IEI1-world. (Def. of IEI1) 7. So, IEI, contains at least one world. (5, 6) This at least has the right shape to advance us from de dicto to de re possibility. The trouble is that, everything above it granted, line 5 doesn't follow. All we get from 4 is that my way of thinking of { w I w makes E true } leaves it open that the set might have members. And that is compatible with its being the empty set in fact. Suppose for example that E is P&-'C, where P = "everything is physically like so" and C = "there is consciousness." To understand E, it's enough to understand its conjuncts, that is, to know that P is verified by the worlds that are physically like so, and that C is verified by the worlds where there is consciousness. Obviously though to know in these sorts of ways the truth-conditions of P and C does not even begin to tell me whether a world verifying the first can avoid verifying the second. Understanding is knowing what a world has to be like to verify a statement; how easy or difficult it may be for worlds like that to exist is another matter entirely. VIII. The gap in the argument has to do with disparate ways of conceiving the same collection of worlds. One response would be to equate understanding with some sort of unmediated grasp of the verifying worlds; see below. Another is to concede that these worlds have got to be conceived under a description, but to constrain the type of description so that opacity phenomena cannot arise. Understanding E is knowing its verifying worlds in a special canonical way-a way that respects what worlds in their innermost nature are. Now, since the physicalist thinks that worlds are in their innermost nature physical, she will presumably insist on a physical specification. How then can it be claimed that speakers "miss the fact" that any world physically like so contains consciousness through failing to think of the consciousnessworlds in physical terms? Thinking of them in such terms is a condition of understanding, and we are talking about speakers who understand. Conclusion: if physicalism were correct, and understanding were "physical" understanding, then merely to understand P &-'C would be enough for the realization that it could not possibly be true. True, but so what? The intuition the physicalist must not flout is that a normal understanding of P and C leaves open the possibility of zombie worlds. That a physical understanding of P and C should rule out zombie worlds is not counterintuitive in the least; for a physical understanding of C BOOK SYMPOSIUM 461

is by definition an ability to tell whether worlds presented in physical terms contain consciousness. Physicalism was supposed to be an ontological theory, not a theory of understanding. This distinction is trampled on when understanding is equated with canonical grasp of truth-conditions; it now becomes a "consequence" of physicalism that speakers (even anti-physicalistic ones!) don't know the meaning of their own word. Why should anyone's claim to semantic competence hang on the outcome of an arcane modal debate? IX. The second or "immaculate conception" strategy tries to relate speakers to sets of worlds directly, by which I mean: not as the worlds meeting such and such a condition. Rather than knowing a condition on the E-verifying worlds, I must know how to recognize such a world when I encounter it. Encounter it where, though? Not in imagination, for worlds are imagined under descriptions, hence not immaculately. The idea has got to be that plopped down in w with the mission of determining E's truth value there, I would conclude that E is indeed true; the primary intension of an expression F is the function taking w to the extension I would assign F as an inhabitant of w. ("If it had turned out that the liquid in lakes was H20 and the liquid in oceans XYZ, then we probably would have said that both were water" (58).) This will have to be a me that is idealized in various respects: computing power, mobility, physical strength, and so on. But the shape of the strategy is clear enough. For the strategy to work, my in-world representative's descriptive inclinations need to be a function of his (= my) concepts, and not extraneous "nonsemantical" factors.6 An example taken from Mark Wilson suggests this condition may not be met: what we count as falling under the extension of a [word may] depend on various accidental historical factors... druids might end up classifying airplanes as "birds" if they first saw a plane flying overhead, but not if they first found one crashed in the jungle (365). This calls to mind lots of other considerations capable of influencing a speaker's referential behavior: her hunches about how representative the observed cases have been, her larger theoretical and practical projects, how anxious she is to avoid multiplying entities, how physicalistic she is-the whole sorry mess of presumptions and prejudices that guide us in our application of old words to new cases. Suppose my idealized self takes up residence in a world where events he is inclined to call pains co-occur with events he would describe as c-fiberfirings. Do "pain" and "c-fiber firing" pick out the same type for him? Unaided understanding cannot decide such questions, even given a full state- 6 Two other worries I am skipping over. Do I have a priori cognitive access to ideal-me's reactions? And doesn't "access" entail a departure from immaculateness? 462 STEPHEN YABLO

ment of pertinent facts: up to, but not including of course, facts about how those very questions are to be answered. (Remember the great identity debates of the 1950s, when it was assumed that mental/physical correlations would soon be found and the question was what ontological conclusions to draw.) This seriously limits the dialectical use that can be made of our alter egos' inworld judgments. If the dualist is allowed to claim w as a world where pain isn't c-fiber firings, because that is a conclusion that speakers could reasonably draw, why shouldn't the physicalist be allowed to claim it as a world where they're identical, for the same reason? The anti-physicalist could reply that there are other worlds whose antiphysicalistic import is so clear and unmistakable that all well-informed observers are going to agree. Take a zombie world, for instance; no one could think that pain was identical to c-fiber firings there, because that world (my alter ego aside, let's say) doesn't have any pain. But to assume that zombie worlds are indeed possible just forgets the reason we handed descriptive authority to our in-world representatives in the first place. Their role was to clear the way to a nonempty primary intension, i.e., to a zombie world. For my representative to be told outright whether w verifies E (whether others feel pain) just returns authority to myself, which obviously defeats the purpose. If he is not told outright, though, then a zombie-world has no better claim to membership in there are zombiesll than does a world like ours; my representative cannot tell them apart. To the extent that the strategy buys us a world, then, physicalism is unbothered. The world might be our own, consciousness and all. BOOK SYMPOSIUM 463