contrary to empiricism.

Similar documents
The Argument (for rationalism) from Induction. More than observation is needed

The CopernicanRevolution

The Argument (for rationalism) from Induction. More than observation is needed

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

The British Empiricism

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Cartesian Rationalism

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Descartes and Foundationalism

Cartesian Rationalism

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

David Hume ( )

Class 2 - Foundationalism

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Kant and his Successors

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Kant s Transcendental Idealism

EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Lecture 18: Rationalism

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

FIL 4600/10/20: KANT S CRITIQUE AND CRITICAL METAPHYSICS

Introduction to Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

A Case for Dispositional Innatism

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

Class 11 - February 23 Leibniz, Monadology and Discourse on Metaphysics

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

It is not at all wise to draw a watertight

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

The Argument from Induction for Rationalism

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Class #9: Kant Our in class discussion of these notes will be lamentably abbreviated, focused on the first three sections.

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Free will & divine foreknowledge

The logic of the success/failure system

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

John Locke No innate ideas or innate knowledge

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

John Locke Innate ideas and innate knowledge

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

PHI2391: Logical Empiricism I 8.0

My purpose is to persuade all those who think metaphysics worth studying

GOD, Scientists & the Void

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

CONTENTS. CHAPTER 1. CHAPTER II. THE PROBLEM OF DESCARTES, -

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY

1/9. The First Analogy

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY

Transcription:

Rationalism and Empiricism

Rationalism Rationalism, as the term is used in philosophy, is contrary to empiricism. Rationalism says that our minds have been made to fit the world we are in (or vice versa). Hence there is a happy prior agreement between the structure of our concepts and the structure of the world. Our intuitive feelings about how the world ought to be are often correct, therefore.

Geometry, which h before the origin i of things was coeternal with the divine mind and is God himself (for what could there be in God which would not be God himself?), supplied God with patterns for the creation of the world, and passed over to Man along with the image of God; and was not in fact taken in through the eyes. Johannes Kepler (Harmonice Mundi, The Harmony of the World (1619), book IV, ch. 1. Trans. E. J. Aiton, A. M. Duncan and J. V. Field (1997), 304)

What led me to my science and what fascinated me from a young age was the, by no means self-evident, fact that our laws of thought agree with the regularities found in the succession of impressions we receive from the natural world, that it is thus possible for the human being to gain enlightenment regarding these regularities by means of pure thought Max Planck, A Scientific Autobiography (1948)

1. Effects can be logically inferred from their causes, i.e. from a suitably complete description of the total cause....we welive in a rational universe, in the sense that the world is structured according to logical and mathematical principles.

Empiricism Inphilosophy, empiricism is the claim that allof our knowledge and concepts come from experience. There is no innate (inborn), or a priori knowledge (prior to experience), or a priori concepts. In the context of scientific knowledge, empiricism is used a little more loosely. It can just mean an emphasis on empirical rather than theoretical methods.

Francis Bacon, Novum Organon, 1620. 26. To help me get my ideas across, I have generally used different labels for human reason s s two ways of approaching nature: the customary way I describe as anticipating nature (because it is rash and premature); and the way that draws conclusions from facts in the right way I describe as interpreting nature.

36. There remains for me only one way of getting my message across. It is a simple way, namely this: I must lead you to the particular events themselves, and to the order in which they occur; and you for your part must force yourself for a while to lay aside your notions and start to familiarize yourself with facts.

45. The human intellect is inherently apt to suppose the existence of more order and regularity in the world than it finds there. Many things in nature are unique and not like anything else; but the intellect devises for them non-existent parallels and correspondences and relatives. That is how it comes about that all the heavenly bodies are thought to move in perfect circles....

Rationalism and Theology The reason for this second rule is the same as the reason for the first rule, namely the unchangingness and simplicity of the operation by which God preserves motion in matter. (Descartes, Principles)

Without t all doubt this World, so diversified ifi d with that t variety of forms and motions we find in it, could arise from nothing but the perfectly free will of God directing and presiding over all. From this fountain it is that those laws, which we call the laws of Nature, have flowed; in which there appear many traces indeed of the most wise contrivance, but not the least shadow of necessity. These therefore we must not seek from uncertain conjectures, but learn them from observations and experiments Roger Cotes, preface to the 1713 edition of Newton's Principia.

Newtonian rationalism? It is inconceivable that inanimate Matter should, without the Md Mediation of something else, which h is not material, operate upon, and affect other matter without mutual Contact That Gravity should be innate, inherent and essential to Matter, so that one body may act upon another at a distance thro a Vacuum, without the Mediation of any thing else, by and through which their Action and Force may be conveyed from one to another, is to me so great an Absurdity that I believe eve no Man who has in philosophical Matters a competent Faculty of thinking can ever fall into it. Gravity must be caused by an Agent acting constantly according to certain laws; but whether this Agent be material or immaterial, I have left to the Consideration of my readers. Isaac Newton, Letters to Bentley, 1692/3

Strong rationalism And the demonstrations [of the rules of collision] are so certain, that even if experience seemed to show us the contrary, we would nonetheless have to trust our reason more than our senses (Descartes, Principles) As [the principles of mechanics] have heretofore been insufficiently established, I demonstrate them in such a manner that they will be understood to be not only certain but even necessarily true Leonhard Euler, 1736.

Leibniz s weaker rationalism Leibniz also differed from Descartes in his higher tolerance of final causes (what we would now call aim or purpose). He believed that such causes, for instance the principle that light takes the easiest path in a series of transparent bodies, were often more accessible to human inquiry and that they offered a pleasant demonstration of God s wisdom: God selects the best of all possible worlds. Olivier Darrigol, Physics and Necessity (2014), p. 21.

Principle of Sufficient Reason When two incompatible things are equally good, and when neither in themselves, nor by their combination with other things, has the one any advantage over the other. God will produce neither of them. Leibniz, EssayinDynamics Dynamics, 1695. E ti l ith l f b th id t E.g. a symmetric lever, with equal forces on both sides, at equal distances.

As we will see in a moment, this usage of the principle of sufficient i reason became very popular in eighteenth-century h natural philosophy. It lends a sort of rational necessity to some contingent truths, even though they do not result from the principle of contradiction. According to Leibniz, some other contingent truths have a moral necessity: they find their reason in God s wisdom. This is the case for the conservation of live force and for the optical principle p of the easiest est path. In the best possible world, some quantities should be conserved and some others should he a minimum. Unfortunately, this metaphysical argument does not tell which the conserved or minimized ii i quantities ii are. Darrigol, p. 22.

Einstein s s rationalismwas similarin in this regard to Leibniz s s. In 1919, after an experiment confirmed Einstein s theory of general relativity, a reporter asked Einstein what would it have meant if his theory was wrong. He replied: God would have missed a great opportunity. Einstein actually didn t believe in a personal god, but was guided in his theorizing by the idea that the universe ought to make sense, and should conform to Einstein s own standards of elegance.

What really interests me is whether God could have made the world any differently: in other words, whether the demand for logical simplicity leaves any freedom at all. (Albert Einstein, late 1940s, as remembered by his assistant Ernst Straus)

Leibniz s modest nativism Leibniz (1704) says that the mind is not a tabula rasa, but more like a block of marble, the veins of which determine what sculpted figures it will accept. if there were veins in the stone which marked out the figure of Hercules rather than other figures, this stone would be more determined thereto, and Hercules would be as it were in some manner innate in it, although labour would be needed to uncover the veins, and to clear them by polishing, and by cutting away what prevents them from appearing.

It is in this way that ideas and truths are innate in us, like natural inclinations and dispositions, natural habits or potentialities, ti and not like activities, iti (1704, Preface, p. 153)

When historians of physics encounter rationalist arguments, they tend to regard them as short-lived illusions implying unconscious assumptions, cultural biases, and even errors of reasoning. At best they recognize that these arguments function as useful motors of research. Today s physicists have a more ambiguous attitude. They may profess empiricism and yet secretly flirt with rationalism. Although they commonly assert that experience is the only criterion of truth, some of them engage in a quest for natural axioms from which the most fundamental theories would follow. Olivier Darrigol, Physics and Necessity (2014), Preface.

in a few felicitous cases the rational deduction can be mended to provide a genuinely convincing proof of necessity. These cases fall under the category of what I call comprehensibility arguments, in homage to Helmholtz s idea that t nature, if it is at all comprehensible, must a priori icomply with certain theoretical structures these deductions d are not purely rational: they rely on empirically refutable assumptions of comprehensibility, as well as on empirical background knowledge inspiring the definition of the ideal systems to which these assumptions are applied. They are not completely rigorous, and there is always a remnant of subjectivity in judging the premises of comprehensibility. They nonetheless make it very difficult to imagine, in given domains of experience, theories different from or not equivalent to those already known to be successful.

Hume Matters of fact, which are the second objects of human reason, are not established in the same way; and we cannot have such strong grounds for thinking them true. The contrary of every matter of fact is still possible, because it doesn t imply a contradiction ti and is conceived by the mind as easily and clearly as if it conformed perfectly to reality. That the sun will not rise tomorrow is just as intelligible as and no more contradictory than the the proposition that the sun will rise tomorrow. It would therefore be a waste of time to try to demonstrate [= prove absolutely rigorously ] its falsehood. If it were demonstratively false, it would imply a contradiction and so could never be clearly conceived by the mind. (True enough)

I venture to assert, as true without exception, that knowledge about causes is never acquired through a priori reasoning, and always comes from our experience of finding that particular objects are constantly associated with one other. Hume argues for this by examples. Adam taking a bath, gunpowder, magnets, slabs of marble, digestive systems, etc. But these all involve complicated systems, with hidden mechanisms. What about simple systems?

Hume on the collision problem We are apt to imagine that we could discover these effects purely through reason, without experience. We fancy that if we had been suddenly brought into this world, we could have known straight off that when one billiard ball strikes another it will make it move knowing this for certain, without having to try it out on billiard balls. Custom has such a great influence!

If you re not yet convinced that absolutely all the laws of nature and operations of bodies can be known only by experience, consider the following. If we are asked to say what the effects will be of some object, without consulting past experience of it, how can the mind go about doing this? It must invent or imagine some event as being the object s effect; and clearly this invention must be entirely arbitrary. The mind can t possibly find the effect in the supposed cause, however carefully we examine it, for the effect is totally different from the cause and therefore can never be discovered in it. Hume doesn t examine any rationalistic solutions to the collision problem, and criticise the reasoning. Is this just an a priori, dogmatic rejection of rationalism?

Reasoning can eliminate possible laws? The claim that Huygens established collision laws, with certainty, using entirely a priori reasoning, is tough to accept. But what of the weaker claim that a priori reasoning might eliminate many putative laws (e.g. those of Descartes) thus narrowing the field of possibilities?... clearly this invention must be entirely arbitrary Darrigol says that rationalist arguments rely on empirical background knowledge inspiring the definition of the ideal systems to which these assumptions are applied.

Rationalism and induction The senses, although they are necessary for all our actual knowledge, are not sufficient to give us the whole of it, since the senses never give anything but instances, that is to say particular or individual truths. Now all the instances which confirm a general truth, however numerous they may be, are not sufficient to establish the universal necessity of this same truth, for it does not follow that what happened before will happen in the same wy way again. Leibniz, New Essays on Human Understanding.

experience never gives its judgments true or strict universality, but only assumed and comparative universality through h induction, i enabling us to say of this or that rule We haven t yet observed any exception to it. Kant, Introduction to the second edition of the Critique (B3 4)

IsaacNewton assumed that nature is economical: To this purpose the philosophers say that Nature does nothing in vain, and more is in vain when less will serve; for Nature is pleased with simplicity, and affects not the pomp of superfluous causes. Principia Mathematica (1687), Book III.

Kant and Euclidean Geometry The apodeictic certainty of all geometrical propositions, p and the possibility of their a priori construction, is grounded in this a priori necessity of space. Were this representation of space a concept acquired a posteriori, and derived from outer experience in general, the first principles of mathematical determination would be nothing but perceptions. They would therefore all share in the contingent character of perception; p that there should be only one straight line between two points would not be necessary, but only what experience always teaches. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, A24.

Euclid s axioms (or postulates) 1. A straight line segment can be drawn joining any two points. 2. Any straight line segment can be extended indefinitely in a straight line. 3. Given any straight line segment, a circle can be drawn having the segment as radius and one endpoint as centre. 4. All right angles are congruent. 5. Given any straight line and a point not on it, there exists one and only one straight htline which h passes through h that t point and never intersects the first line, no matter how far they are extended.

These axioms entail that the internal angles of a triangle sum to 180. But is this true? Do we need to measure it? Kant says there s no need to measure it.(?) Physicists say that, with a large triangle, the angles don t sum to 180.

Or is Euclidean geometry still true ofthe human visual field, intuition of space, etc.? Euclidean geometry is true in cognitive science, even if false in physics? Axiom 5 was long regarded as less certain than the other four.

Rationalism and chance One fundamental idea of rationalism is: 1. Effects can be logically inferred from their causes, i.e. from a suitably complete descriptions of the total cause. This seems to entail determinism. (Historically, many rationalists have regarded determinism as a priori.) But the advent of quantum mechanics (arguably) shows that determinism is false.

E.g. the Stern Gerlach apparatus Suppose a physicist sets up an experiment and observes the outcome (e.g. up or down). o 36

Spontaneous symmetry breaking Many physical theories allow the possibility of Many physical theories allow the possibility of spontaneous symmetry breaking, where a system that is initially symmetry evolves all by itself to an asymmetric state.

A rationalist s theory of chance 38

A rationalist ss theory of chance The idea of a complete description of a concrete physical system is perhaps fishy. Propositions are mental, abstract, etc. Perhaps there are inherent limitations to how completely a physical system can be represented in such terms? Hence the maximal description of a cause may be incomplete. In such cases, the maximal description of the cause may not entailthe the effect. Instead, rationality dictates only a certain degree of belief in a possible effect, given the cause. This is in fact the physical chance of the effect.

A rationalist ss theory of chance Spontaneous symmetry ybreaking is possible, on this view. The preservation of logical symmetry requires only that symmetric alternatives have equal probability. bili Buridan s ass need not starve! Of course, physical reality is not entirely rational and, p y y y comprehensible on this view. It s a small retreat for rationalism.

Rationalism and the origin of complexity From a rationalist s s perspective, it is impossible for novel complexity to appear in a physical system. (Since complex conclusions don t logically follow from simple premises.) E.g. Embryonic development. Rationalists (e.g. g y p ( g Descartes) had to be preformationists in the broad sense of a pre determined phenotype.

... if one knew in detail all the parts of the seed of a particular species of animal, for instance, Man, one could deduce from that alone for reasons entirely mathematical and certain, the whole figure and conformation of each of its parts. Descartes, De laformation de l animal animal, 1664. AT 11: 277. The chicken may logically follow from the egg (plus physical The chicken may logically follow from the egg (plus physical laws) but it doesn t logically follow from a billiard ball.

Why not?