Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Similar documents
Qualified Realism: From Constructive Empiricism to Metaphysical Realism.

Reconstructed Empiricism

CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICISM AND EPISTEMIC MODESTY: RESPONSE TO VAN FRAASSEN AND MONTON

Van Fraassen s Appreciated Anti-Realism. Lane DesAutels. I. Introduction

Should the Empiricist be a Constructive Empiricist? Marc Alspector-Kelly. Department of Philosophy. Western Michigan University

Realism and Anti-Realism about Science A Pyrrhonian Stance

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Structural realism and metametaphysics

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN 1. AGAINST ANALYTIC METAPHYSICS

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

145 Philosophy of Science

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

A Modest Defense of Manifestationalism

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Empiricism. Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Stance relativism: empiricism versus metaphysics

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

I assume some of our justification is immediate. (Plausible examples: That is experienced, I am aware of something, 2 > 0, There is light ahead.

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

Are Scientific Theories True?

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Practical Inadequacy: Bas van Fraassen's Failures of Systematicity. Curtis Forbes

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Stance relativism: empiricism versus metaphysics

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Chapter One. Constructive Empiricism and the Case. Against Scientific Realism

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

ONE CANNOT BE JUST A LITTLE BIT REALIST: PUTNAM AND VAN FRAASSEN*

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

A number of epistemologists have defended

A Defense for Scientific Realism:

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

The Cosmological Argument

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Structural Realism or Modal Empiricism?

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Psillos s Defense of Scientific Realism

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Empiricism, Stances, And The Problem Of Voluntarism

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Evidential arguments from evil

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Howard Sankey Department of History and Philosophy of Science University of Melbourne

Bayesian Probability

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

ON JESUS, DERRIDA, AND DAWKINS: REJOINDER TO JOSHUA HARRIS


A Priori Bootstrapping

The linguistic-cultural nature of scientific truth 1

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

Mind Independence and Modal Empiricism

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Transcription:

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Constructive Empiricism (CE) quickly became famous for its immunity from the most devastating criticisms that brought down the logical empiricist view of science. But at least early on, CE was widely assumed to have inherited essentially the same epistemological grounding: empiricism teaches us that there are limits imposed by experience, and so our conception of science had better respect those limits or undermine the widely held assumption that scientific inquiry is rational. But in the thirty- odd years since he introduced CE, it has become increasingly apparent that Bas van Fraassen s conception of CE s epistemological backdrop represents at least as much departure from the past as does CE itself. In particular, CE is formulated and defended from within a voluntarist epistemology, according to which the only constraints on rational opinion are logical and probabilistic consistency, beyond which remarkably meager limits anything is permitted. It is very much to his credit that in his book Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Paul Dicken emphasizes the role that voluntarism plays in van Fraassen s views. It is also to his credit that he recognizes that one could endorse CE while rejecting voluntarism, and takes steps to characterize an alternative CE view along such alternative lines. The first three chapters of Dicken s book directly address the relationship between voluntarism and CE. In the first chapter, Dicken surveys some of the standard criticisms of CE concerning the epistemological value of the observable/unobservable distinction. While he is unimpressed by those arguments on their own merits, Dicken is primarily concerned to emphasize that voluntarism undermines their relevance: if anything goes beyond logical and probabilistic consistency, then no argument can be made out from the distinction s being arbitrary to our being obliged to manage opinion in the same way on both sides. The second chapter reviews what Dicken takes to be van Fraassen s three primary arguments in favor of voluntarism, and finds them wanting. The third chapter aims to undermine voluntarism as a suitable epistemological basis for CE. And in the fourth chapter Dicken proceeds to formulate and defend an acceptance/belief distinction, claiming that this distinction can fill the lacuna left by the rejection of voluntarism in the characterization and defense of CE. The first three chapters survey a wide range of issues related in one way or another to van Fraassen s views. Much of it would be instructive for those unfamiliar with these issues in relation to CE. It is unclear, however, that the structure that Dicken imposes upon it all is either illuminating or dialectically effective in the way he suggests. The second argument for voluntarism Dicken identifies in the second chapter, for example, runs from the various well- known sceptical arguments that van Fraassen has mounted against various forms of ampliative inference. The upshot of Dicken s response is that these arguments threaten to undermine even his own very permissive epistemological framework. But I don t see how. Van Fraassen s sceptical arguments are designed, not to undermine the rationality of ampliative inference- - which the constructive empiricist

employs as does the realist, albeit to a more limited extent- - but to defuse the realist s insistence that the demonstrable reliability of such inferences mandates their application across the board (to unbservables in particular). Those arguments generate scepticism only if the rational is bounded by those inferences whose reliability we can demonstrate. Voluntarism is, however, precisely the view that the limits of rationality extend well beyond that boundary. So van Fraassen has no need to limit the force of his arguments in the way that Dicken suggests. For example, Dicken claims that van Fraassen will undermine his own epistemology if he does not endorse the ranking premise that we can at least reliably rank potential explanations (even if we cannot ensure that the correct explanation among them, as per the famous best of a bad lot argument). But I do not see why van Fraassen cannot cheerfully claim that how one ranks explanations is as much a matter of pragmatics and background philosophical inclination as is one s selection of candidate explanations. What radical scepticism with respect to both the ranking premise and the no- privilege premise (that the truth is among those explanations under consideration) demonstrates is not the irrationality of the employment of IBE but rather the permissibility of not doing so when it suits one. The other two arguments for voluntarism that Dicken identifies in the second chapter concern van Fraassen s argument for diachronic coherence constraints (encoded in his reflection principle ) and his conception of empiricism as stance. But the first argument, if successful, would only demonstrate a constraint on rational opinion in addition to (synchronic) logical and probabilistic consistency; that can hardly constitute an argument for the greater doxastic freedom beyond those constraints as advocated by the voluntarist. And van Fraassen s primary argument for stance empiricism- - which Dicken challenges- - has little to do with the voluntarism. It appeals instead to a supposed incoherence in conceiving of empiricism as a doctrine in conjunction with the (for van Fraassen, laudible) intention to deliver a critique of metaphysics. This is not to say that voluntarism and empiricism- as- stance are incompatible (although the critique of metaphysics does seems a rather un- voluntarist thing to attempt). But it is far from obvious that there is an argumentative line from one to the other as Dicken seems to suggest, such that an argument against empiricism- as- stance simultaneously undermines an argument for voluntarism. The same concern arises with respect to the third chapter. In it, Dicken reviews Alan Musgrave s well- known objection that electrons are unobservable is about unobservables, and so appears to be un- endorsable by the constructive empiricist who believes only what a theory says about observables. Dicken makes much of this argument, seeing in it a pattern repeated in arguments against the compatibility of CE with modal and mathematical anti- realism (Ladyman 2000 and Rosen 1994, respectively). He claims that the voluntarist s response to Musgrave depends on the response to Ladyman, which in turn depends on the response to Rosen- - and that voluntarism lacks the resources to provide the last response. I worry, however, that this artificially links three independent problems. For example, it is true that empirical adequacy concerns what s observable, not just what s actually observed, and that observable is at least prima facie a modal concept, thereby ensnaring the constructive empiricist in questions concerning what to make of those parts

of a theory that appear to represent observable but unobserved reality. But this- - the apparently modal dimensions of observability- - is not Musgrave s problem, which concerns only what someone who believes a theory to be empirically adequate- - thereby apparently limiting belief to representations of observables- - can make of electrons are unobservable. For what it s worth, it seems to me that Musgrave s problem is satisfactorily handled by simply expanding to electrons, if they exist, are unobservable. To believe a theory to be empirically adequate is not really to be agnostic concerning all a theory s assertions about unobservables; it s to be agnostic about all such claims that assert their existence. At any rate, this issue is independent of the modality issue. Dicken is right to emphasize the significance of voluntarism in van Fraassen s views, and to apply pressure upon those views by criticizing it. But it seems to me that the most trenchant criticism is the easiest to state: voluntarism is so wildly permissive that it countenances as rational belief- sets that are obviously completely crazy, including belief- sets which completely disregard all empirical evidence. So if voluntarism is the only epistemological basis upon which CE and associated views can be erected, then so much the worse for CE and those associated views. Dicken does emphasize this concern with voluntarism at various points; but its presentation is overshadowed by the more convoluted critique of the second and third chapters. The fourth chapter is, however, different. In it Dicken formulates a distinction between acceptance and belief, argues that the distinction has utility aside from issues concerning the viability of CE, and provides at least the outline of a response to the three arguments against CE reviewed in chapter three. The gist is that acceptance is a voluntary act, something that one does, in contrast to belief which (Dicken claims) is involuntary. Dicken then suggests that the constructive empiricist can respond to Musgrave s, Ladyman s, and Rosen s concerns in essentially the same way: we accept, but do not believe, those consequences that concern unobservables (including electrons are unobservable ), unactualized possibles (called modal agnosticism ), and mathematical entities. (The latter is, in fact, only barely discussed on pp. 208-209.) This amounts to extending the agnosticism originally applied to unobservables broadly enough to encompass other entities that are problematic from an empiricist standpoint, certainly a plausible move to make for one drawn to CE. There are, of course, problems. First, as with most such maneuvers, it s hard to know when to stop. Why not merely accept those portions of theory that concern actual, but in fact unobserved, objects and events (a view Rosen once called manifestationalism ; see Rosen 1994, Alspector- Kelly 2001, and Alspector- Kelly 2006)? Indeed, why not only accept even claims concerning the actually observed? This would be incoherent on van Fraassen s account of acceptance, which is initially predicated of a theory and incorporates belief concerning observables. But Dicken s formulation appears to be predicated primarily of sentences rather than theories, and it is at least not obvious that one could not simply accept- - voluntarily act on its basis but not believe- - everything the theory says, even when it speaks of the observed. Second, Dicken insists that one can accept what one does not believe. But then one s acceptance of electrons are unobservable is compatible with one s not believing that

electrons are unobservable: one could well believe that they are observable while accepting that they aren t. But then belief that the theory is empirically adequate would not generate agnosticism with respect to electrons, since that agnosticism is intended to apply only to those entities represented by the theory that are- - that one believes to be- - unobservable. The same concern applies to Dicken s intention to accept modal claims: my acceptance of if I lived then I would see the dinosaurs is compatible with my believing that conditional to be false. But to construe dinosaurs as observable- - and so as accurately represented by an empirically adequate theory- - is to believe that they are so; nothing follows from our merely accepting their observability. Perhaps Dicken would respond by claiming that we accept the modal conditional, but believe the observability claim. But this would presumably require that modal agnosticism does not capture the semantics of modal claims, which Dicken intends it to do (pp. 206-207). Third, it is unclear that reliance on the acceptance- belief distinction will address the accusations of arbitrariness often directed against van Fraassen s views. The voluntarist s response, in essence, is that there s nothing wrong with being arbitrary, so long as one s choices deliver a coherent view of scientific practice, are compatible with one s own philosophical commitments, and satisfy the minimal constraints imposed by logical and probabilistic consistency. Without voluntarism, however, those objections seem to return in full force; the viability of an acceptance/belief distinction itself provides no reason to believe only so much and accept the rest. Dicken recognizes in the last chapter that his distinction is compatible with voluntarism. But perhaps his version of CE employing that distinction needs voluntarism as much as does that of van Fraassen. These are not knock- down criticisms. But they do suggest that the book might have been more rewarding if it had concentrated less on the construction of the overly elaborate critique of the second and third chapters, and instead developed the acceptance/belief distinction and its role in the formulation and defense of CE more fully. References Alspector- Kelly, M. 2001, Should the Empiricist be a Constructive Empiricist?, Philosophy of Science 68, pp. 413-431. Alspector- Kelly, M. 2006, Constructive Empiricism and Epistemic Modesty: Response to van Fraassen and Monton, Erkenntnis 64, 371-379. Dicken, P. 2010, Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science, Palmgrave McMillan. Ladyman, J. 2000, What s Really Wrong with Constructive Empiricism: van Fraassen and the Limits of Modality, The British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 51, 837-856. Monton, B. & van Fraassen, B. C. 2003, Constructive Empiricism and Modal Nominalism, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54, 405-422.

Rosen, Gideon 1994, What is Constructive Empiricism?, Philosophical Studies 74, 143-178.