Consistency and Christian Ethics

Similar documents
FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Asian Philosophy Timeline. Confucius. Human Nature. Themes. Kupperman, Koller, Liu

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Philosophy HL 1 IB Course Syllabus

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Deontological Ethics

The Ethics of Self Realization: A Radical Subjectivism, Bounded by Realism. An Honors Thesis (HONR 499) Kevin Mager. Thesis Advisor Jason Powell

STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

The Episcopal Diocese of Kansas

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

IMPUTABILITY, ASCRIPTION, RESPONSIBILITY: MORAL IDENTITY AND ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION. William Schweiker, University of Chicago

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Bartolomé De Las Casas Essay Series

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Combining Conviction with Compassion by Dr. Mark Labberton, Senior Pastor (First Presbyterian Church, Berkeley, CA)

Same-Sex Marriage, Just War, and the Social Principles

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

EVIL, SIN, FALSITY AND THE DYNAMICS OF FAITH. Masao Abe

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

EL CAMINO COLLEGE Behavioral & Social Sciences Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy, Summer 2016 Section 2510, MTWTh, 8:00-10:05 a.m.

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

This passage consists of three parts:

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Rashdall, Hastings. Anthony Skelton

TOWARDS A THEOLOGICAL VIRTUE ETHIC FOR THE PRESERVATION OF BIODIVERSITY

PHIL 1313 Introduction to Philosophy Section 09 Fall 2014 Philosophy Department

(Transition: Paul then explains in more detail how the truth about God has been suppressed in unrighteousness. He does this in three exchanges.


The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum

Chapter 12: Areas of knowledge Ethics (p. 363)

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

Being Human Prepared by Gerald Gleeson

Worship. A Thomistic Perspective on. Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo, PhD

A Blessed Child and a Light Bulb

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

CHAPTER 13: UNDERSTANDING PERSUASIVE. What is persuasion: process of influencing people s belief, attitude, values or behavior.

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

A Modern Defense of Religious Authority

Christianity and Pluralism

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

The Christian Vision of the Person and Society

Kant and his Successors

A-level RELIGIOUS STUDIES 7062/1

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Coordination Problems

Natural Law. 2A.1 Handout on Natural Law

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Master of Arts in Health Care Mission

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

The Early Church worked tirelessly to establish a clear firm structure supported by

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Orientation and Choice

A Very Short Essay on Mormonism and Natural Law. by The Lawyer. I was recently talking with a friend of mine at Harvard Law School who describes

LGBTQ Issues: A Third Way Approach

THE REVOLUTIONARY VISION OF WILLIAM BLAKE

The Expository Study of Romans

Class 23 - April 20 Plato, What is Right Conduct?

Themelios. An International Journal for Pastors and Students of Theological and Religious Studies. Volume 19 Issue 1 October, 1993.

International Bible Lessons Commentary Romans 1:16-32

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

John Haugeland. Dasein Disclosed: John Haugeland s Heidegger. Edited by Joseph Rouse. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2013.

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Undergraduate Calendar Content

The role of the conscience

A Rational Approach to Reason

Going beyond good and evil

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

BLEEDING HEARTS AND BLOODY MINDS REASON IN ACTION IN ALTRUISTIC BENEVOLENCE. Howard Adelman

Page 2 of 8 Stage 2 Religion Studies Student Response

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Admin Identifying ethical issues Ethics and philosophy The African worldview Ubuntu as an ethical theory

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

CHRISTIAN MORALITY: A MORALITY OF THE DMNE GOOD SUPREMELY LOVED ACCORDING TO jacques MARITAIN AND john PAUL II

II. THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE THE SOCIAL ASPECT OF THE SACRAMENT OF PENANCE

Transcription:

ATR/90:3 Consistency and Christian Ethics William Schweiker 1 There are many moral and political issues the churches need to address. For instance, by some estimates present worldwide consumption rates could mean within thirty to fifty years global environmental collapse. 1 How will we respond in order to avert a barren future? When if at all will we respond? Who is the relevant we? The challenges of our day seem much more perplexing and dire than matters of sexual preference. Still, it is good to reflect before rushing to judgment about any moral or political question. Richard Norris, in his Notes, furthers Christian reflection on the question of homosexuality. My tactic in this essay will be to isolate paradigms of moral and religious consistency and their significance for that question. Richard Norris opens his Notes with a story of inconsistency. A churchwoman condemns homosexuality as a sin, yet holds that homosexuals are nice people. 2 This story poses the question of the form of consistency that can and ought to characterize a morally good life. A distinction must be quickly drawn. We can distinguish the consistency of judgment from the consistency of character or life, what I will call moral consistency. Of course these are deeply related, but they are not identical. Consistency of judgment requires that similar cases be judged similarly, so, in terms of Norris s story, the woman, to be consistent in judgment, must judge every homosexual act a sin and every homosexual to be nice. (Given human lives, it is hard to see how she could sustain that conclusion!) In other words, the demand for consis- 1 See, for instance, Jared Diamond, Collapse: How Societies Choose to Fail or Succeed (New York: Penguin, 2006). 2 One should note that good people are not always nice. But in our culture it is important to be nice rather than to be good! On this see Iris Murdoch s novel The Nice and the Good. 567

568 Anglican Theological Review tency of judgment is an attack on special pleading and hypocrisy, the attempt to exempt some case (usually one s own) or person (usually oneself or a loved one) from equal assessment. Consistency in this logical sense is what Immanuel Kant meant by the universalizability of maxims, which he believed defined the form of morality. As noted, consistent judgments are related to but not identical with moral consistency, Kant s claim notwithstanding. Usually we expect the morally consistent person, that is, someone who embodies her or his convictions, or at least struggles to do so, to be consistent in her or his judgments. And we also often assume, rightly or wrongly, that the capacity to make consistent judgments rests somehow on the kind of person one is and the formation of one s character. Yet that is not always the case. A person might make a consistent judgment and yet be inconsistent in her or his actual life; an individual might be morally consistent as a person and find, through the dictates of wisdom, that she or he must bend the rules, as it were, in a specific judgment. In fact, wisdom is often depicted precisely as a capacity to see the moral and religious import of a unique situation, one that cannot be reduced to uniform judgment. These distinctions let us grasp some important ideas about moral goodness and evil. With thanks to Dante, we can easily see why the devil can be absolutely consistent in judgment and incarnate pure evil, willing to make evil his good. Radical evil is logically consistent and embodies ideals consistently. The saint, conversely, is someone who embodies a consistent life as well, but who is (supposedly) infallible in judgment and act about what is truly good. A hypocrite, and that is most of us at least some of the time, has her or his life ajar; inconsistency in judgment and character are episodic, and so are instances of moral weakness or maybe even willful intent. And, finally, there are cases of moral error, even profound error, where one lives and judges consistently, but the values and norms judged by and embodied are in fact wrong and even evil. The Nazi doctor doing his duty consistently and faithfully in obedience to the Reich was nevertheless engaged in moral evil due to a profound lapse or coercion of judgment. It would be possible to explore these forms of consistency, their interrelations and conflicts, the kinds of moral fault they bespeak, and how all of that bears on the question of homosexuality. Neither space nor time will allow that breadth of inquiry here. Given this, I want to focus mostly on the consistency of life. More specifically, I want, at

Consistency and Christian Ethics 569 Norris s prompting, to explore the relation between motives and actions that should characterize a consistent life. 2 At least since St. Paul, Christians have insisted that motives and actions can conflict. The good that I know I ought to do, I do not do, as Paul puts it in Romans 7. That is the abyss of the will (as philosophers call it). But it is also true that Christians can and ought to struggle to reconcile motive and action under the norm of love. In this light, one can track in the history of Western Christian and philosophical ethics very different conceptions of the kind of consistency that ought to characterize a good life. First, one can conceive a life s unity in terms of a hierarchy or single principle of overriding concern. As Søren Kierkegaard famously put it, purity of heart is to will one thing. The unity sought in a life is one in which all motives are subsumed under a dominant one. One is to love God in a categorically different way than one loves one s neighbor in order to avoid an idolatry of human affections. Our love of others (sexual and otherwise) could, on this account, be a form of sin and thus morally wrong if they, rather than God, capture the whole of one s heart and soul. Other similar accounts of unity are possible. Thomas Aquinas held a unity of virtues. The virtues have love (caritas) as their origin and end because God is love and God is the origin and end of all things. In the early church, St. Augustine famously showed in his On the Morals of the Catholic Church that virtues, insofar as they are genuine, are really forms of love (caritas) rooted in the love of God rather than love of self. On this paradigm whether in Thomistic virtue discourse, Kierkegaardian voluntarism, Augustinian ideas about love, or some other form the good person is the unified self where unity means strict adherence to one love or one principle which subsumes or overrides all others. In the truly good person s life the diversity of virtues, loves, or intentions masks their deeper unity. I will call this the purity paradigm of moral consistency. Another line of thought is that the unity of a life is a complex coherence which is not ordered top-down by some overriding virtue (Thomas) or willful devotion to God or single principle (Kierkegaard) or unity of form (Augustine). Those positions, on this second account, risk denying or demeaning aspects of a life for the sake of purity.

570 Anglican Theological Review Ought we really love the neighbor only as a way to the love of God and thereby make others a means to our God-relation? Is it really the case that love of neighbor is a possible idol? What is sought on this second account is a reflexive coherence among capacities, needs, and goods of a life so that richness of existence is found. This too requires consistency between belief and action, but one does not understand that consistency in terms of a unity of the virtues, purity of conviction, or a single form of love, to stick with the examples given above. I coin the term integrity paradigm for this outlook. There are many versions of this paradigm, from Plato and Aristotle in the ancient world to contemporary thinkers interested in a range of human goods and capacities. 3 On my account, human life is saturated with a host of differentiated yet interacting motives. Stated too briefly: pleasure and pain and thus the capacity for sympathy saturate our embodied existence; recognition and shame and so the capacity for benevolence permeate our social being; feelings of innocence and guilt and so an idea of justice (as Aquinas knew) arise because we are reflective creatures; participation and alienation give rise to the motive of empathy because human life is also located in some community. Because we are complex creatures, these sensibilities and motives interpenetrate and conflict with one another. Yet sensibilities are also ways of perceiving value, and that is why sympathy and empathy and the rest can and do arise within our emotional lives. This insight into perceptions of the value of others seems missing in Norris s Notes since he is so concerned, wrongly I judge, with the relation of the involuntary and the voluntary as defining morality. That is, since he is concerned to see the realm of the involuntary simply as naturally given desires and impulses, and so outside of moral evaluation, he seems not to have grasped how our emotions (desires and impulses) are also perceptions of value. This truncates, in my judgment, the complexity of his account of moral action and character. And, besides, Christians have always known that love is a form of perception and knowledge, even if Aristotle and the Stoics could never quite get this insight. The task of integrating motives (e.g., sympathy, benevolence, justice, empathy) with respect to their constitutive emotions and feelings 3 See William Schweiker, Responsibility and Christian Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995). For other positions see the works of Amaryta Sen, Martha Nussbaum, Philippa Foot, Mary Midgley, John Finnis, and Protestant thinkers like Don S. Browning and Max L. Stackhouse.

Consistency and Christian Ethics 571 is, on my thinking, the work of conscience. Yet conscience, despite what some theorists hold, is not a legislative power that sets up a hierarchy. Conceiving it that way conforms to the purity paradigm. Conscience is, rather, the capacity of the whole self to order the whole self. 4 It is a concept for the moral labor of our being. The conscience of a community is the whole community ordering the whole community with respect to social motivations and goods. The unity sought in life is called moral integrity because it is the integration the right relating of multiple capacities with and for others through the work of life, through conscience, when there is truthfulness of self and community, to the project of respecting and enhancing the integrity of all life. True integrity of life is, of course, an aspiration, a going on to perfection; it requires self-labor as a necessary but not sufficient condition. Our lives are only complete in grace and love. And insofar as genuine love is an integrative power a power that does not mutilate but fulfills and completes then love (human and divine) is the norm of the morally consistent life. Properly understood, love respects and enhances the complex coherence of oneself and others, human and non-human. On this account, the threat of disintegration arises with pain, shame, guilt, and alienation which make it impossible to assume the human labor of rightly integrating life. The distinction between paradigms of consistency returns us to the opening story that Norris tells. The woman believes that homosexuality is wrong (in Christian terms a sin), but that belief does not motivate action. She is, to put not too fine a point on it, a hypocrite, just like the rest of us. Her statement is neither the ravings of the devil nor the utterance of a truly good person, a saint. Her life lacks purity as well as integrity, but those different paradigms of consistency suggest very different recommendations for her life. The idea of integrity fastens on perceptions of the value of others and organizes the complexity of life around that insight; it does not seek a top-down consistency for fear that purity might violate what is due others and oneself. This does not relieve one of the demand or ideal aspiration required by a robust understanding of moral goodness. The converse is the 4 In Anglican thought, one finds an analogous position presented by Bishop Butler in his Sermons at Royce Chapel. While Butler thinks that conscience tells us our duty, it is developed with respect to a rather complex, and we could say phenomenological, account of the self in which desire and middle level principles (self-love and benevolence) need to be harmonized or ordered.

572 Anglican Theological Review case. Living with integrity is more demanding, more complex, than adherence to one overriding principle or norm. One is claimed by the demand to live with and for others in all of their distinctive and nonreducible complexity in the adventure of respecting and enhancing the integrity of life. This brings us to the religious depth of thinking about the moral life. 3 The paradigms just noted imply different ways of inhabiting the Christian faith. The insight of the purity paradigm is that faith in the one, true living God can have no rivals; monotheistic conviction seems to require purity. Even love of neighbor, the second great command, is never to rival love of God. God and God alone should be loved with heart and soul and mind. The neighbor, as both the Hebrew Scriptures and Jesus teach, is to be loved as one loves oneself. Neighbor love is reciprocal among individuals; the love of God is not. The purity paradigm speaks to the deep religious longing for the sovereignty of the divine. Truth be told, I imagine that when folks appeal to what the Bible says, the concern is the religious longing for purity. However, one needs to grasp the deep seduction of the idea of purity. It bespeaks a heroic ideal of exclusive fidelity. That is why it has been the position of existentialists, like Kierkegaard, and is too often the default position in Christian communities. No doubt, this is because of the centrality the great command has in Christian piety. Yet this vision of moral consistency can breed hypocrisy (come what may, we live in an impure world) or a kind of religious self-obsession and so the desire for utter authenticity unmoored from constitutive bonds to, with, and for others. In this way, the religious relation to the divine with heart, soul, and mind can actually threaten the sustaining relations we have to others, including sexual relations. Little wonder that most religious violence is driven by a conception of purity that must be imposed on others, individually and politically. It is a form of moral madness. 5 Thus, purity threatens to tear asunder the religious and moral life, the danger Jesus saw when he insisted, after healing 5 On this see William Schweiker, Theological Ethics and Global Dynamics: In the Time of Many Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2004) and Amartya Sen, Identity and Violence: The Illusion of Destiny (New York: W.W. Norton, 2006).

Consistency and Christian Ethics 573 someone, that the Sabbath was made for human beings and not human beings for the Sabbath. The woman of Norris s story says that homosexuality is a sin (religious relation) and yet homosexuals are nice people (moral relation) and thereby enacts a profound contradiction within Christian living. Is there scriptural warrant for the integrity paradigm and also a way beyond the possible contradiction in Christian life between the two great commands? Can we integrate love of God with love of neighbor? Yes, under scriptural warrants. The insight is found, again, in Jesus claim that the Sabbath was made for humans and not humans for the Sabbath. It is seen in the letters of John where anyone who hates the neighbor and claims to love God is called a liar. It is part of the prophetic denunciation of cultic purity when used to trample the poor, the weak, and the outcast. The integrity paradigm is rooted in the insight that the lives of others make a claim, a demand, to respect and enhance the integrity of their lives and one s own. 6 That claim is the call of conscience; at the same time it is, religiously, an utterance of the divine. The space of the moral life is not simply the relation between me and my God, me and my intention, or me and my principle/virtue. It is defined by relations that claim respect and enhancement required for integrity. Immoral actions are ones that thwart the integrity of life and aid forces of disintegration, which in their tired and horrible ways reduce the living to the dead. The integrity paradigm means, to use another biblical trope, learning to walk in the ways that lead to life. From this ethical perspective the important issue in our sexual lives is whether actions and relations respect and enhance the integrity of life with and for others. The claim to integrity arises within perceptions of value that saturate desires and emotions factored through the moral labor of our being, conscience. Sexuality is, in this ideal respect, a perception of the value of the other and the integrity of life, a perception that arises, as Norris rightly says, with the first genuine occasion of desire for another. My contention, then, is that what matters morally and religiously is the exercise of one s sexual embodiment so that the integrity of life in and with others is respected and not demeaned, enhanced and not destroyed. Sexual desire is neither a simple good (Norris) nor good only when between 6 David E. Klemm and William Schweiker, Religion and the Human Future: An Essay in Theological Humanism (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2008).

574 Anglican Theological Review heterosexuals (common Christian morality), nor a threat to the purity of the religious life (rigorism), nor necessarily ordered under a single virtue (Augustine), nor a means only of procreation and thus a bulwark against lust and a sacrament (traditional Christian teaching). Rather, sexuality is a moral space, a field of interrelations, among many others in which we are called and challenged to live integral, responsible lives. The claim of responsibility is neither a respecter of persons nor the possession of a single sexual orientation. It is, rather, the full meaning of moral freedom and so the joy and burden of our lives. The real task, then, is to live responsibly within the moral space called sexuality. It is that challenge that ought to engage the energy and concern of the churches on questions of sexual ethics and the many other questions we face in these global times.