PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen

Similar documents
To link to this article:

Judging Subsistence Rights by their Duties Eric Boot

Justifications and Excuses: A Systematic Approach

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

HARE S PRESCRIPTIVISM

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Kant's Moral Philosophy

Fundamental Principles Of The Metaphysic Of Morals By Immanuel Kant

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Lincoln-Douglas: The Inquistive Debate of Philosophy

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Kant and his Successors

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Philosophical Review.

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

GCE Religious Studies Unit B (RSS02) Religion and Ethics 2 June 2009 Examination Candidate Exemplar Work: Candidate A

Israel Kirzner is a name familiar to all readers of the Review of

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Constitutional Law 312 Applied Assignment 2017 Application A

Fundamental Principles Of The Metaphysics Of Morals By Immanuel Kant

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

Philosophical Underpinnings of the First Amendment

Rawls and Kant: On the Primacy of the Practical

Fundamental Principles Of The Metaphysic Of Morals: Groundwork Of The Metaphysic Of Morals (Immanuel Kant) By Immanuel Kant READ ONLINE

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Groundwork For The Metaphysics Of Morals By Allen W. Wood, Immanuel Kant

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

CHURCH LAW BULLETIN NO. 25

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

THE REFUTATION OF PHENOMENALISM

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

The influence of Religion in Vocational Education and Training A survey among organizations active in VET

Rethinking Development: the Centrality of Human Rights

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Feedback Constitutional Law 312 Applied Assignment 2017 Application B

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

Sample Questions with Explanations for LSAT India

English II Pre-AP 1 st Quarter Extra Credit

1/8. The Third Analogy

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE!

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

The Important Questions: a Dialogue between Cary Smith and Ph.D Candidate

Kant's Natural Law. Brian David Janssen Iowa State University

THE WAY, THE TRUTH, AND THE LIFE

This document consists of 10 printed pages.

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

Golden Rule Thomas Carson

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

The Utilitarian Approach. Chapter 7, Elements of Moral Philosophy James Rachels Professor Douglas Olena

Scanlon on Double Effect

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Transcription:

PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen The following full text is a publisher's version. For additional information about this publication click this link. http://hdl.handle.net/2066/129890 Please be advised that this information was generated on 2018-09-12 and may be subject to change.

http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1677-2954.2013v12n2p355 BYRD, B. Sharon; HRUSCHKA, Joachim. Kant s Doctrine of Right. A Commentary Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 2010; 336 p. REVIEW THOMAS MERTENS (Radboud Universiteit Nijmegen/ Netherlands) The contrast could scarcely be bigger. Kant s theory of law is a very bad book, writes Schopenhauer at the beginning of the 19 th century, a collection of mistakes hanging together. It must have been Kant s old age! The book is indeed badly composed, writes Ludwig some 30 years ago. It must have been due to the process that led from manuscript to printed book! Therefore Ludwig provided us with a new, not uncontested, edition of Kant s theory of law, in which various parts of the text are presented in a different place. None of this is true, say Byrd and Hruschka at the beginning of the 21 th century. Kant s doctrine of right, as it is now often called (I always hesitate when I find Rechtsphilosophie translated as philosophy of right ; why not simply: philosophy of law, and thus here: doctrine of law?), is a highly structured and meticulously formulated masterpiece on legal and political philosophy. From a very limited number of assumptions Kant develops here, so we are told, in a Euclidean manner a complete system of individual rights. Subsequently, Kant indicates what these rights entail for the constitution of the legal order of the state, the order between states and for the cosmopolitan legal order. Nobody before or after Kant has drawn in a such a radical manner the consequences of what it means that human beings have the innate right of freedom to own external objects as their property. While it must be admitted that Kant did not make life easy for his readers, it must also be presumed that he was primarily interested in getting the theory right, not in presenting his theory in an easily accessible manner. Herewith the first assumption of this commentary is presented: Kant got it right in his doctrine of right, according to Byrd and Hruschka; where Kant s text seems impenetrable or confused, the problem lies not with Kant but with the reader who should feel encouraged to try harder to understand him. Therefore, the doctrine of right should not be criticised as inconsistent or contradictory but interpreted in such a manner that it comes out as a unique, complete and logically consistent whole. The second assumption of this commentary is that

MERTENS, T. Kant s Doctrine of Right. A Commentary 356 Kant s earlier texts in legal and political philosophy, such as On the common saying and Towards perpetual peace are of limited use for interpreting Kant s system of legal philosophy as developed in the doctrine of right. In comparison with these earlier texts, Kant has not only drastically extended his position by adding a treatise on private law but has also drastically changed his position, most notably with regard to war and peace. Thirdly, according to this commentary, the influence of Achenwall on Kant s mature philosophy of law, both with regard to substance and to formulations, is of such importance that the difficulties with Kant s text can only be solved with the help of Achenwall s works. The final assumption follows from this: Kant s text should be understood within the context of his contemporaries, most notably Achenwall, and thus references to much of the contemporary literature on Kant s doctrine of right is neither needed nor very helpful. Kant was familiar with much of his contemporary literature and therefore that body of texts helps us understand his texts. The result of this approach is, in one word, stunning. Following the introduction of these assumptions, one finds a highly structured book in which Kant s doctrine of right is reconstructed on the basis of an extensive analysis of Paragraph 41. In this crucial Paragraph, Kant not only sketches the transition of private law to public law, but also introduces the three so-called leges (lex iusti, lex iuridica and lex iustititae) which are then subsequently connected to the three essential institutions of the Kantian state: the legislative power, the market and the juridical power. The book subsequently discusses, respectively, the opposition between the state of nature and the juridical state; the right to freedom; the juridical postulate of practical reason on the basis of which property is possible; the distinct forms of property that Kant distinguishes; the state and the international and cosmopolitan order. The authors do not shy away from well-known textual difficulties, such as the meaning of the many adages stemming from Roman law that Kant uses, among which the already mentioned leges and the three rules of Ulpian. They also discuss e.g. Kant s statements that the criminal law is a categorical imperative and that ought implies can. This all leads to the picture of a Kantian state as a minimal state, the sole aim of which is to protect and secure the natural rights of human beings and (thus) to guarantee the functioning of the market in which humans are fully free to buy and sell their property: volenti non fit iniuria! The state is prohibited from interfering within the sphere of private relations between citizens since these relationships should develop autonomously on the basis of the freedom of contract. Since Kant rejects any form of paternalistic government and rejects Cicero s dictum that public well-being is the first law of the state, this commentary

357 MERTENS, T. Kant s Doctrine of Right. A Commentary concludes that the welfare state is incompatible with Kant s principles. The free market interpretation of Kant s doctrine of right is not restricted to the state alone, but leads to an interpretation of Kant s cosmopolitan legal order as a plea for facilitating and securing international commercial trade. This commentary is very useful for those who are already (somewhat) familiar with Kant s doctrine of right and who are prepared to read Kant s text anew alongside this commentary. This book is certainly not an easy introduction. As I belong to the first category of readers (at least, so I think), this commentary was at times very illuminating. Nevertheless, I also often disagree, for a variety of reasons, with the interpretations that Byrd and Hruschka present in an often quite apodictic manner. Let me summarize a few of my hesitations. First with regard to the relationship between Kant s earlier texts and the doctrine of right: How likely is the assumption that Kant fundamentally changed his views on the state and in particular on the international legal order between 1792 and 1795 on the one hand and 1797 on the other? Take the following example: in the doctrine of right Kant acknowledges, according to Byrd and Hruschka, the right to wage war as the permitted way for a state to assert its rights. This is the opposite to his position in Perpetual Peace. I argue (in: Kant and the Just War Tradition, in: H.G. Justenhoven, W.A. Barbieri Jr. (eds.), From Just War to Modern Peace Ethics, De Gruyter Berlin 2012, 231-247) that Kant s remarks to this effect in the doctrine of right should be understood not as a prescription, but as a description of the state of nature between states. In other words, Kant does not acknowledge a ius ad bellum, which would not only make him into a sorry comforter like all the other representatives of the just war tradition, but which would also destroy the prospect of a lasting peace. Nor is the portrait of Kant as a proto-libertarian entirely convincing. Whereas this commentary goes into great detail when commenting on certain passages of Kant s text, it is telling that no attention at all is given to General Remark C of Paragraph 49, in which Kant discusses, as is well known, the socio-economic duties of the state to support organizations for the poor. It could be argued more generally that certain provisions with regard to the redistribution of property by the state can indeed not be justified on the basis of paternalism (which Kant rejects indeed), but that they can be justified on the basis of protecting civil independence, on the basis of which no one should be dependent upon the choice of someone else (to which Kant subscribes). There are quite a few other interpretations in this commentary with which one can take issue, but let me conclude with a general observation. Kant s Die Metaphysik der Sitten is a

MERTENS, T. Kant s Doctrine of Right. A Commentary 358 diptych in which one finds a doctrine of law alongside a doctrine of virtue. Yet we do not find in this commentary any reflection on the unity of Kant s metaphysics of morals. Byrd and Hruschka suggest that the doctrine of right stands on its own and that it deals with individual rights and the implications of these rights only. Yet throughout the critical period, Kant consistently announced his intention to publish a metaphysics of morals and, finally, at the end of his life, he published this book as one book in two parts. Writing and commenting on the first part of this book (with only a few comments on the doctrine of virtue) has far reaching implications. Think e.g. of the first of the Ulpian rules: honeste vive. This rule is indeed found in the doctrine of right and is interpreted by Byrd and Hruschka as emphasizing the fact that everyone is a person with individual rights. Yet, it would seem to me that the duty to live an honorable life cannot itself be a right. Honeste vive seems primarily a duty, namely the duty someone has towards himself. Therefore it seems to fit badly within the doctrine of right. We know that Kant hesitated where to place the Ulpian rules: should they not fit better within the doctrine of virtue (see e.g.: A. Pinzani, Der systematische Stellenwert der pseudo-ulpianischen Regeln in Kants Rechtslehre, in: Zeitschrift fuer philosophische Forschung (59) 2005, 73-4)? And indeed, one can find the duty to lead an honourable life as a part of the doctrine of virtue as well. Such a reflection on Ulpian s first rule as a duty to self, however, forces us to abandon the narrow perspective on Kant s doctrine of right as a protolibertarian treatise and to approach Kant s Metaphysics of Morals very different, namely as a rich and a rather classical work which takes its starting point in duties and then moves on to discuss not only rights, but virtues as well.