The Grounding for Moral Obligation

Similar documents
God is a Community Part 1: God

The Goodness of God in the Judaeo-Christian Tradition

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Words and their Meaning

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

QUESTIONS BUDDHISM MUST ANSWER

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Reasons Community. May 7, 2017

Philosophy & Religion

Moral Argument. Theistic Arguments: The Craig Program, 4. Edwin Chong. God makes sense of the objective moral values in the world.

DOES GOD EXIST? THE MORAL ARGUMENT

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

The Ontological Argument

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Introduction to Philosophy Practice Exam One. True or False A = True, B= False

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

5 A Modal Version of the

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Wednesday, April 20, 16. Introduction to Philosophy

Methods for Knowing Transphysical Truths and Its Obstacles in Transcendent Philosophy

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

Book Review: From Plato to Jesus By C. Marvin Pate. Submitted by: Brian A. Schulz. A paper. submitted in partial fulfillment

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

Theocentric Morality?

The Euthyphro Dilemma

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

Session 03: The Argument from Morality

THE INTERNAL TESTIMONY OF THE HOLY SPIRIT: HOW DO YOU KNOW THAT THE BIBLE IS GOD S WORD?

Worldviews Foundations - Unit 318

ETHICS AND RELIGION. Prof. Dr. John Edmund Hare

Trinitarianism. Millard Erickson, Christian Theology (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker, 2001), 290. Copyright , Reclaiming the Mind Ministries.

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Five Arguments for God - by Peter S. Williams

Re-evaluation of the Nature of Free Will: A Response to Libet s Experiments

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Divine command theory

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

The Kalam Cosmological Argument provides no support for theism

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

PHIL 176: Death (Spring, 2007)

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Introductory Matters

Calvary Classroom WORLD RELIGIONS

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

He is There and He is Not Silent

A Comparative Study of the Ethics of Christine M. Korsgaard and Jean-Paul Sartre

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

PHIL 1313 Introduction to Philosophy Section 09 Fall 2014 Philosophy Department

Introduction to Philosophy 1301

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

An Article for Encyclopedia of American Philosophy on: Robert Cummings Neville. Wesley J. Wildman Boston University December 1, 2005

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

(naturalistic fallacy)

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

New Chapter: Philosophy of Religion

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

Philosophy (30) WINTER 2005

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

A History of Western Thought Why We Think the Way We Do. Summer 2016 Ross Arnold

-1 Peter 3:15-16 (NSRV)

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

The Freedom to Live an Authentic Life

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Jan Narveson, Pacifism: A. Philosophical Examination 1

Does Morality Require God? 2010 James Gray

latter case, if we offer different concepts by which to define piety, we risk no longer talking about piety. I.e., the forms are one and all

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

EUTHYPHRO, GOD S NATURE, AND THE QUESTION OF DIVINE ATTRIBUTES. An Analysis of the Very Complicated Doctrine of Divine Simplicity.

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

doogieduff Basketball Court: "Is the future settled or open?" doogieduff v. Jaltus doogieduff Is God free? Jaltus Re: Is God free?

Immanuel Kant: Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals First Section Summary Dialogue by Micah Tillman 1. 1 (Ak. 393, 1)

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

Transcription:

Bradley 1 The Grounding for Moral Obligation Cody Bradley Ethics from a Global Perspective, T/R at 7:00PM Dr. James Grindeland February 27, 2014

Bradley 2 The aim of this paper is to provide a coherent, sufficient foundation for objective moral obligation. Learning about the various religions, ethical theories, and cultures around the world in order to engage in some sort of morally permissible way when we visit those regions of the world is ultimately futile and self-stifling if there is no basis on which objective morals even exist. The view that I will be defending will be the idea that objective moral obligation is grounded in a personal God. For clarification, the notion is in regards to moral ontology, not moral epistemology. The Yale philosophy professor Dr. Shelly Kagan engaged in a debate with philosopher and theologian Dr. William Lane Craig on the issue of whether God is necessary for the existence of objective morality in 2009. Despite expectations, the entire debate was essentially worthless because the two participants could not come to agree upon a shared definition of the word objective. Thus, let me define what I mean by objective. What I mean by objective is existing and binding independent of human opinion or conjecture. So, when I say morals exist objectively, I am saying, for example, that torturing a child for the fun of it is wrong regardless of what anyone thinks on the matter, even if everyone on Earth thinks it to be okay a hundred years from now. I am putting the moral realm on the same existential plane as the physical realm. It doesn t matter what one thinks about the existence of the planet Earth, even if one is correct or incorrect about its existence, it simply exists. I will continue to define any potentially ambiguous terms as the paper progresses. The key ingredient of any attempt towards grounding objective moral obligation is to first assign intrinsic value and worth to human persons. By intrinsic value I mean that something is not merely a means to an end, but an end in of itself, and to be loved or sought after for its own sake. If human persons have no intrinsic value, and are at best of extrinsic worth, a means to an

Bradley 3 end, then the entire notion of what we intuitively understand morality to be crumbles to the ground. What then can provide us with establishing that human persons have intrinsic value? I suggest that the only non-arbitrary way to assign intrinsic value to human persons is to assert that human persons are created in the image of a personal God. God, classically understood in the monotheistic tradition, is a maximally great being. Thus, loaded in the word God are inherent great-making properties that carry moral significance, such as maximal goodness, maximal worth, intrinsic worth, and worthiness of worship. So, if human beings are created in the image of such a God, then human persons require a respect that resembles respect for God, who is to be valued in Himself. When we begin to investigate the characteristics of morality, the premise that its source is found in a personal God makes all the more sense. Morality is prescriptive, commanding, authoritative, and objective. Prescriptions and commands are forms of communication, and communication occurs only between persons. Morals deal with a purpose and a will, so its source must also have a purpose and a will, and purpose and will only occurs in persons. Morals are authoritative, so they must come from an authority, and authority can only be held by a person. Morals, properly and intuitively understood, are objective and transcend human individuals, society, and time, so its source must also transcend human individuals, society, and time. This brings us to a personal source that transcends human individuals, societies, and time. Since abstract objects aren t personal, only a personal God fits the description of the source of morality. Many object that God being the source of morality does nothing to solve the issue because it creates a fatal dilemma to theism. This objection was originally made by Plato, and is

Bradley 4 known as the Euthyphro dilemma, which argues that either (1) if something is good only because God wills it, then the good is arbitrary and even murder or rape could have been good things; and (2) if something is only God s will because it is good, then goodness lies outside of God, which shows that He isn t the source of morality (which would also rob Him of His sovereignty and aseity!) (Plato and Grube). The dilemma, however, is a false one; there is a third option. God doesn t will something because it is good, nor is it good by an arbitrary will, but God s will and commandments flow from and reflect His character, which is the good. In other words, He is the good; He is the moral standard. Thus, morality is not something that is created ex nihilo, but is changeless and eternal, so as the character and the will of the Source. Speaking of Plato, another objection sometimes made is that of moral Platonism, which asserts that morals are abstract entities that exist independently of any person, human or divine they are ideals that exist in the realm of the Forms (Kraut). There are two problems with this, though. Firstly, morals can t be abstract platonic forms floating around in Plato s Heaven existing independently of persons, because morals are completely dependent on persons, as mentioned earlier. Although moral Platonism can account for moral objectivity, it is persons, not ideals, who issue commands, prescriptions, and hold authority. Duties only arise in relation to people, not metaphysical concepts. Secondly, there is no way to assign intrinsic value to human persons on moral Platonism. The same problems arise in trying to ground moral obligation in an impersonal God, such as the ones in Eastern religions. Francis Schaeffer said that if one starts with an impersonal beginning, the answer to morals eventually turns out to be the assertion that there are no morals. This is true whether one begins with the Eastern pantheism or with energy particles. With an impersonal beginning, eventually morals are just another form of metaphysics, of being. Man has a feeling of moral motions, yet in the universe as it is, his feeling is

Bradley 5 completely out of line with what is there, and we are left with a feeling of cosmic alienation. There is no standard in the universe which gives final meaning to such words as right and wrong. If you begin with the impersonal, the universe is totally silent concerning any such words. Thus, to the pantheist, the final wrong or tension is the failure to accept your impersonality, and morality is, ultimately, illusory. Immanuel Kant once said that we should treat people not just as means but as ends in themselves. In contemporary American culture a common argument for grounding moral obligation begins with oneself. The argument goes: I value myself, and I expect others to treat me with respect, so, by logical extension, I ought to treat others with the same respect. So, respect for other human persons arises by logical consistency with valuing and respecting oneself. The problem with this, however, is that it assigns intrinsic value to persons (myself) from the beginning, which is question-begging. The argument begins with the descriptive statement that I value myself, but ought I do so? Moreover, what would give me the value that I claim? This basis for moral obligation is entirely self-imposed/subjective, and fails to give an account for objective intrinsic value of human persons both individually and collectively. The same problems emerge from a theory of moral obligation that is simply socially imposed. It doesn t matter which way you turn. Attempting to ground objective moral obligation in oneself, society, a platonic realm, or even an impersonal God are all insufficient. The former half of these attempts are inherently subjective, the latter half of these attempts are impersonal, and none of them can assign intrinsic value to human persons. The only way to ground objective moral obligation is if there is a personal, eternal, immutable, maximally great God, whose nature is the standard of what is good, and we as human persons are created in His image. Jean-Paul Sartre recognized this reality when he said, It [is] very distressing that God does not exist,

Bradley 6 because all possibility of finding values in a heaven of ideas disappears along with Him; there can no longer be an a priori Good, since there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it. Nowhere is it written that the Good exists, that we must be honest, that we must not lie; because the fact is we are on a plane where there are only men. As Dostoyevsky said, If God didn t exist, everything would be possible.

Bradley 7 References Plato, and G. M. A. Grube. Five Dialogues. 2. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2002. Print. Kraut, Richard. "Plato." Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 11 Sep 2013. Web. 27 Feb 2014. <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/>. Schaeffer, Francis. Francis A. Schaeffer Trilogy. Wheaton: Crossway, 1990. 292-293. Print. Kant, Immanuel. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals. 3. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1993. Print. Sartre, Jean-Paul. Existentialism and Human Emotions. New York: Philosophical Library, 1957. 22. Print.