UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Similar documents
Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following, social holism

My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Gonseth and Quine Michael Esfeld Universität zu Köln, Philosophisches Seminar Albertus-Magnus-Platz, D Köln

Assertion and Inference

145 Philosophy of Science

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

THE PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. jennifer ROSATO

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Biographical review. Hilary Putnam ( ): a tireless and sensitive mind

The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

A Distinction between Science and Philosophy

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Class 6 - Scientific Method

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Epistemology Naturalized

Varieties of Apriority

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Postmodal Metaphysics

Quine on Holism and Underdetermination

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Contents EMPIRICISM. Logical Atomism and the beginnings of pluralist empiricism. Recap: Russell s reductionism: from maths to physics

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

MODERATE HOLISM AND THE INSTABILITY THESIS * Mental or semantic holism can be roughly characterized as the doctrine that the meanings of

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

CLASS PARTICIPATION IS A REQUIREMENT

Areas of Specialization and Competence Philosophy of Language, History of Analytic Philosophy

ACCOUNT OF SOCIAL ONTOLOGY DURKHEIM S RELATIONAL DANIEL SAUNDERS. Durkheim s Social Ontology

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Intro to Science Studies I

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

Critical Scientific Realism

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Florida State University Libraries

Skepticism, Naturalism, and Therapy

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs Lisa Bortolotti OUP, Oxford, 2010

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Anaphoric Deflationism: Truth and Reference

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

ETHOS: Felsefe ve Toplumsal Bilimlerde Diyaloglar // Sayı: 4 (1) Ocak 2011

Alan W. Richardson s Carnap s Construction of the World

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Theoretical Virtues in Science

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

Kertész, András: Philosophie der Linguistik. Studien zur naturalisierten Wissenschaftstheorie.

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

CONTRASTIVE EMPIRICISM AND INDISPENSABILITY

Transcription:

PHILOSOPHICAL HOLISM M. Esfeld Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Germany Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following, social holism Contents 1. Introduction 2. Holism in epistemology and semantics 2.1 Confirmation holism 2.2 Holism about justification 2.3 Semantic holism 2.4 Rule-following and social holism 3. Holism in methodology 4. Holism in ontology 5. A philosophical characterization of holism 5.1 Holism in contrast to monism and atomism 5.2 Properties that make something a part of a holistic system 5.3 Bottom-up and top-down conceptualizations of holism Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch Summary Holism is a view about the internal organization of certain systems. The claim can be summed up in this way: Holistic systems are such that their constituent parts have some of the properties that are characteristic of these things only if they are organized in such a way that they constitute a whole of the kind in question. Holism is widely accepted in epistemology. Systems of beliefs of persons, scientific theories and finally our system of knowledge as a whole are considered to be holistic systems. It is claimed that experience cannot confirm or refute single beliefs or statements in isolation. Experience always confirms or refutes a whole system of beliefs or statements. What is more, the meaning and the justification of a belief or a statement consists in inferential relations to other beliefs or statements within a whole system of beliefs or statements. If these inferential relations are taken to be determined by social practices, social holism ensues. Methodological holism is the view that systems have to be studied by considering the things that are their parts in the context of the whole. Holism as methodology applies to holistic systems in the first place; but it may also be an appropriate heuristic approach to study other systems. Methodological holism is widespread in the human sciences. In ontology, holism is in the last resort the claim that the whole world is one holistic system in the described sense.

1. Introduction This article considers holism insofar as it is a philosophical position, defended by rational argument. It first goes into examples of holism in specific areas of today s philosophy, namely in epistemology and semantics (section 2), in methodology (section 3), and in ontology (section 4). It then sums up these examples in a philosophical characterization of holism (section 5). In the field of transdisciplinary knowledge ontological holism is the most prominent form of holism, but epistemological and methodological holism are also discussed (see Unity of Knowledge and Transdisciplinarity: Contexts of Definition, Theory and the New Discourse of Problem Solving). The examples of holism in the sciences are considered in detail in a separate article (see Holism in the Sciences). 2. Holism in epistemology and semantics 2.1 Confirmation holism Holism is a position that is widely accepted in today s epistemology. The best way to introduce holism in epistemology is to consider the confirmation of statements or beliefs by experience. The claim of holism in that respect is that a statement cannot be confirmed or refuted by experience in isolation. What is confirmed or refuted by experience always is a whole system of statements, that is, a whole theory, and finally the system of our knowledge as a whole. This position is known as epistemological holism, or, more precisely, confirmation holism. The contemporary discussion on confirmation holism goes back to the French scientist and philosopher of science Pierre Duhem (1861 1916). In his work on the object and the structure of the physical theory, Duhem maintains that it is not possible to put a hypothesis of physics to the test in isolation. Every experiment involves assumptions about the way in which the measuring instruments function, and these assumptions, in turn, imply physical laws. Therefore, Duhem claims that an ensemble of hypotheses or theories is put to the test in any experiment. If the experimental results do not agree with our predictions, we only know that at least one of the hypotheses in question is false. But we do not know which hypothesis or which hypotheses are false. We have a number of options for changing our theory in such a way that it accords with the experimental results. Duhem proposes bon sens as a criterion for deciding which option should be endorsed. Consequently, even the first principles of physics are subject to empirical control in the same way as all the other statements that are contained in a physical theory. If a conflict with experimental evidence occurs, it is not logically determined which statements are to be rejected. It may be reasonable to change even fundamental hypotheses of physics subsequent to the results of experiments. Duhem concludes that the entire physics is one theory that is confronted as a whole with the whole of the experimental facts. Experience does hence not determine a unique system of physics. There may be several logically possible systems of physics that all agree with the whole of the experimental data that are at our disposal.

Duhem refers only to physics. He excludes common sense knowledge as well as sciences such as physiology on the one hand and logic and mathematics on the other hand from his thesis about confirmation. The American philosopher Willard V. O. Quine (1908 2000) generalizes Duhem s thesis in such a way that it applies to all sorts of knowledge, including common sense statements as well as logical laws. However, Duhem s holism is not Quine s background. In his famous paper Two Dogmas of Empiricism (1951), Quine sets out confirmation holism in opposition to the logical empiricism of the twenties and the thirties. Quine maintains that there is no separation between analytic statements of logic and mathematics, which are true or false independently of the way the world is, and synthetic, empirical statements about the way the world is. It is not possible to reduce empirical statements to logical constructs upon statements that describe sense experience and that can be directly confirmed or refuted by sense experience. What is confirmed or refuted by experience be it scientific experience, be it common sense experience is a whole system of statements. Consequently, no statement is immune against revision as a result of experience. Even statements that are regarded as logical laws can be abrogated in order to accommodate new experience. The demarcation between what counts as logic and what counts as empirical science can hence be subject to change. One famous example of this demarcation being variable is the debate about abrogating logical laws such as the law of the excluded middle consequent upon new experience in the domain of quantum physics. Quine suggests regarding our system of knowledge as a seamless web. This web touches experience at its edges. Statements such as There are brick houses on Elm Street are on the periphery of this web. Statements of logic are located in its center. This web is not determined by experience: If a conflict with experience occurs, we have several options for adjusting the web to experience. Quine proposes a pragmatic attitude: It is rational to opt for those changes which imply the slightest perturbation within our system of knowledge as a whole in order to accommodate this system to new experience. Hence, this position implies not only that experience cannot confirm or refute any statement taken in isolation, but also that there is no separation between science and philosophy in the sense of metaphysics. Paying tribute to both Duhem and Quine, confirmation holism is often referred to as the Duhem Quine thesis. To put the matter in a nutshell, confirmation holism is the claim that experience be it common sense experience, be it scientific experience cannot confirm or refute statements in isolation. What is confirmed or refuted by experience is a whole system of statements and in the last resort the system of our knowledge as a whole. Consequently, (a) there is no separation between empirical statements about the way the world is and statements of logic, which are taken to be true come what may. Furthermore, (b) experience does not determine a unique system of knowledge. There are always rival logical possibilities to account for the same experience. Although confirmation holism is widely accepted in today s philosophy, a precise conceptualization of this position faces a number of problems. The most important problems are the following two ones: What is the methodology of science to which confirmation holism leads? The point of confirmation holism is not a psychological theory about the way in

which persons change their beliefs in reaction to experience. The issue is the normative one how we shall change knowledge that is shared in our culture consequent upon new scientific experience. It is granted that there always are several logical possibilities for adapting shared knowledge to new experience. The point at issue is whether there are rational criteria that distinguish particular ways as being the plausible ones, or, ideally, one particular way as the true one. Relativists deny that there are such criteria. Scientific realists, by contrast, are committed to the view that there are such rational criteria, although we may ignore them at present. What is experience so that experience can be the way in which a system of knowledge responds to the world? Again, the point of confirmation holism is not a story about how experience causally induces changes to the systems of beliefs of persons. The point is how experience can be a reason for changes to a system of knowledge that is shared by a community. The point thus is how there can be a rational relation between experience and knowledge. Confirmation holism faces the following dilemma: If experience is conceived as a mere sensual happening, it is not intelligible how it can be a reason for changes to a system of knowledge. If, however, experience is conceived as being conceptual itself and thus as consisting in observation statements, it is itself part of the system of knowledge. How can it then exercise a check on a system of knowledge? 2.2 Holism about justification Holism about justification can be seen as one answer to the last question. The claim is that (a) only other statements or beliefs can justify a statement or a belief and that (b) a statement or a belief is justified if and only if it coheres with other statements or beliefs. Holism of justification therefore is a coherence theory of justification. According to this position, insofar as experience is relevant to knowledge, it is itself conceptual and consists in observation statements. These statements are acquired without making any inferences. But they are not immune to revision, because they are part and parcel of our system of knowledge. They exercise a check on knowledge in the sense of general statements from within the system. The view thus is that our knowledge as a whole is one coherent system that relates to the world by including observation statements. There are two ways of conceptualizing holism about justification: One can say that coherence is in the first place a property of a system of knowledge as a whole. If the justification of a statement that is called into question consists in showing that this statement is integrated into a coherent system of statements, then one can maintain that justification is, like coherence, a property which is, strictly speaking, a property only of a whole system of statements. Nonetheless, the property of justification of the whole indicates the way in which its parts that is, single statements are related with each other as regards justification. This property of the whole indicates in how far its parts cohere with one another, although the property of justification does not apply to single statements. Such an account of justification thus moves from the coherence of the overall system to the justification of that system and from there to the justification of particular statements by virtue of their membership in the system. However, one can also conceptualize holism about justification in such a way that coherence is not a property of a whole system in the first place, but the way in which

single statements fit together with other statements in a system of statements. In this case, justification is a property of single statements in the first place, albeit a relational one, consisting in relations to other statements within a system of statements. The system as a whole is justified, because its parts have the property of being justified by cohering with one another. - - - Bibliography TO ACCESS ALL THE 18 PAGES OF THIS CHAPTER, Visit: http://www.eolss.net/eolss-sampleallchapter.aspx Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology. In: P. A. French, T. E. J. Uehling and H. K. Wettstein (eds.): Studies in the Philosophy of Mind. Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Volume 10. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 615 678. [Inferential role semantics as semantic holism] Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making It Explicit. Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment, Cambridge (Massachusetts): Harvard University Press. [Social, inferential role semantics as semantic and social holism] Esfeld, M. (1998). Holism and Analytic Philosophy. Mind 107, 365 380. [General characterization of holism.] Gadamer, H.-G. (1960). Truth and Method. Revised translation by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald Marshall, New York: Crossroad. [German original: Wahrheit und Methode, Tübingen: Mohr 1960] [Most important source of hermeneutics in contemporary philosophy.] Hegel, G. W. F. (1951). Science of Logic. 2 Volumes. Translated by W. H. Johnston, London: Allen and Unwin [Objective idealism as ontological holism.] Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two Dogmas of Empiricism. Philosophical Review 60, 20 43. [Reprinted in Quine, From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge (Massachusetts): Harvard University Press 1953 and 1980]. [Most important source of confirmation holism and semantic holism] Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. With an Introduction by Richard Rorty and a Study Guide by Robert Brandom, Cambridge (Massachusetts): Harvard University Press. [Important source of semantic holism.] Simons, P. M. (1987). Parts. A Study in Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Chapter 8 on ontological dependence.] Spinoza, B. de: Ethics. English translation in Curley, E. M. (1985). The Collected Works of Spinoza. Vol. 1, Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Important source of ontological holism in modern philosophy.] Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Blackwell. [Important source of semantic and social holism.] Biographical Sketch Michael Esfeld, born 1966, is Private-docent in Philosophy at the University of Konstanz and Heisenberg Fellow of the German Research Council. His main areas of research are epistemology, the

philosophy of science, in particular physics, and the philosophy of mind. His main publications include a book on Holism in Philosophy of Mind and Philosophy of Physics, Dordrecht: Kluwer 2001, Synthese Library No. 298 (Habilitation Thesis), a book in German on Mechanismus und Subjektivitaet in der Philosophie von Thomas Hobbes, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog 1995 (Ph.D. Thesis) as well as several papers on holism and other subjects in epistemology and the philosophy of science, among them "Holism and Analytic Philosophy" in Mind 107 (1998), pp. 365-380, and "Physicalism and Ontological Holism" in Metaphilosophy 30 (1999), pp. 319-337.