Critique of Cosmological Argument

Similar documents
Philosophy of Religion: Hume on Natural Religion. Phil 255 Dr Christian Coseru Wednesday, April 12

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

The problem of God s cognoscibility in David Hume

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

David Hume on the cosmological argument and the argument from design in the Dialogues

The midterm will be held in class two weeks from today, on Thursday, October 9. It will be worth 20% of your grade.

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

The Cosmological Argument

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Reid Against Skepticism

The British Empiricism

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Treatise of Human Nature, Book 1

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

1. An inquiry into the understanding, pleasant and useful. Since it is the understanding that sets

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

From Natural Theology, William Paley, Archdeacon of Carlisle, 1800 CHAPTER I. STATE OF THE ARGUMENT.

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

The Critique of Berkeley and Hume. Sunday, April 19, 2015

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Of the Nature of the Human Mind

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza

An Answer to Anselm by Gaunilo

Idealism from A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part I by George Berkeley (1720)

David Hume ( )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Kant and his Successors

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Thomas Reid on personal identity

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Free will & divine foreknowledge

The Ethics. Part I and II. Benedictus de Spinoza ************* Introduction

THE LEIBNIZ CLARKE DEBATES

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Selection from David Hume s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Parts II and V.

Necessary and Contingent Truths [c. 1686)

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

The CopernicanRevolution

JAMES CAIN. wants a cause. I answer, that the uniting. or several distinct members into one body, is performed merely by

On The Existence of God

Entirely decisive? Hume and the Ontological Argument

The cosmological argument (continued)

Monday, September 26, The Cosmological Argument

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

1/5. The Critique of Theology

SCHOOL ^\t. MENTAL CURE. Metaphysical Science, ;aphysical Text Book 749 TREMONT STREET, FOR STUDENT'S I.C6 BOSTON, MASS. Copy 1 BF 1272 BOSTON: AND

DIALOGUES CONCERNING NATURAL RELIGION (SELECTION)

EXTRACTS from LEIBNIZ-CLARKE CORRESPONDENCE. G. W. Leibniz ( ); Samuel Clarke ( )

Summer Preparation Work

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

What does it say about humanity s search for answers? What are the cause and effects mentioned in the Psalm?


CHAPTER THREE ON SEEING GOD THROUGH HIS IMAGE IMPRINTED IN OUR NATURAL POWERS

NOT CLASSICAL, COVENANTAL

It is not at all wise to draw a watertight

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

Baruch Spinoza. Demonstrated in Geometric Order AND. III. Of the Origin and Nature of the Affects. IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Power of the Affects.

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

The Riddle of Epicurus

The Rejection of Skepticism

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Introduction to Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Of Probability; and of the Idea of Cause and Effect. by David Hume ( )

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Free will and foreknowledge

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

John Locke August 1, 2005 The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

Transcription:

David Hume: Critique of Cosmological Argument Critique of Cosmological Argument DAVID HUME (1711-1776) David Hume is one of the most important philosophers in the history of philosophy. Born in Edinburgh, Scotland, Hume attended Edinburgh University. He enjoyed great popularity during his lifetime. His six-volume History of England established his reputation as an historian and man of letters. Hume also made many enemies with his skeptical doubts about religion and his attacks on the metaphysical doctrines of his Continental and British predecessors. One of his most influential works, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (1779), which our present reading is from, was published after his death. His friends, like Adam Smith, persuaded him that the work was too controversial and might permanently damage his reputation. David Hume s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion is one of the most celebrated contributions to philosophical theology in Western thought. In this dialogue, a cast of three characters each represents a common attitude about God. Demea is a metaphysical theist whose arguments stand or fall on certain a priori notions about evidence. Cleanthes is an anthropomorphic theist who argues from the fact of the world to the necessity of a divine source. Philo is clearly Hume as the skeptic. In the sections that follow, both Cleanthes and Philo attack the rationalism of Demea. Cleanthes argues that matters of fact cannot be demonstrated by the introduction of a priori assertions. Philo argues that while Demea has assumed that rationality necessarily entails a divine mind, an equally acceptable explanation could be the absolute natural character of the universe. 69

Part II. The Philosophy of Religion Vocabulary: Adhere: Sublime: Infallible: Ascertained: Efficacy: Annihilation: stick to noble incapable of error determined power to produce effects or desired results complete destruction Concepts: A posteriori: Infinity: Necessary existence: Chance: Contradiction: Infinite Regression Contingency: Matters of Fact: Questions: 1. Explain Hume s argument regarding matters of fact. 2. Explain Hume s argument regarding contingency. 3. Explain Hume s argument regarding infinite regression. 4. Do you feel that Hume correctly expresses the Teleological Argument? 5. Do you agree with Hume? Why or why not? 70

David Hume: Critique of Cosmological Argument Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion But if so many difficulties attend the argument a posteriori, said Demea, had we not better adhere to that simple and sublime argument a priori, which by offering to us infallible demonstration, cuts off at once all doubt and difficulty? By this argument, too, we may prove the infinity of the Divine attributes, which, I am afraid, can never be ascertained with certainty from any other topic. For how can an effect, which either is finite, or, for aught we know, may be so; how can such an effect, I say, prove an infinite cause? The unity, too, of Divine Nature, it is very difficult, if not absolutely impossible, to deduce merely from contemplating the works of nature; nor will the uniformity alone of the plan, even were it allowed, give us any assurance of the attribute. You seem to reason, Demea, said Cleanthes, as if those advantages and conveniences in the abstract argument were full proofs of its solidity. But it is first proper, in my opinion, to determine what argument of nature you choose to insist on; and we shall afterwards, from itself, better than from its useful consequences, endeavor to determine what value we ought to put upon it. The argument, replied Demea, which I would insist on, is the common one. Whatever exists must have a cause or reason of its existence; it being absolutely impossible for anything to produce itself, or be the cause of its own existence. In mounting up, therefore, from effects to causes, we must either go on in tracing an infinite regression, without any ultimate cause at all; or must at last have recourse to some ultimate cause, that is necessarily existent. Now, that the first supposition is absurd, may be thus proved. In the infinite chain or succession of causes and effects, each single effect is determined to exist by the power and efficacy of that cause which immediately preceded; but the whole external chain or succession, taken together, is not yet determined or caused by anything; and yet it is evident that it requires a cause or reason, as much as any particular object which begins to exist in time. The question is still reasonable, why this particular succession of causes existed from eternity, and not any other succession, or no succession at all. If there be no necessarily existent being, any supposition which can be formed is equally possible; nor is there any more absurdity in nothing s having existed from eternity, than there is in that succession of causes which constitutes the universe. What was it, then, which determined something to exist rather than nothing, and bestowed being on a particular possibility, exclusive 71

Part II. The Philosophy of Religion of the rest? External causes, there are supposed to be none. Chance is a word without meaning. Was it nothing? But that can never produce anything. We must, therefore, have recourse to a necessarily existent being, who carries the reason of his existence in himself, and who cannot be supposed not to exist, without an expressed contradiction. There is, consequently, such a being; that is, there is a Deity. I shall not leave it to Philo, said Cleanthes, though I know that starting objections is his chief delight, to point out the weakness of this metaphysical reasoning. It seems to me obviously ill-grounded and at the same time of so little consequence to the cause of true piety and religion, that I shall myself venture to show the fallacy of it. I shall begin with observing, that there is an evident absurdity in pretending to demonstrate a matter of fact, or to prove it by any argument a priori. Nothing is demonstrable, unless the contrary implies a contradiction. Nothing, that is distinctly conceivable, implies a contradiction. Whatever we conceive as existent, we can also conceive as nonexistent. There is no being, therefore, whose non-existence implies a contradiction. Consequently, there is no being, whose existence is demonstrable. I propose this argument as entirely decisive, and am willing to rest the whole controversy upon it. It is pretended that the Deity is a necessarily existent being; and this necessity of his existence is attempted to be explained by asserting that, if we knew his whole essence or nature, we should perceive it to be as impossible for him not to exist as for twice two not to be four. But it is evident, that this can never happen, while our faculties remain the same as at present. It will still be possible for us, at any time, to conceive the non-existence of what we formerly conceived to exist; nor can the mind ever lie under a necessity of supposing any object to remain always in being; in the same manner as we lie under a necessity of always conceiving twice two to be four. The words, therefore, necessary existence, have no meaning; or, which is the same thing, none that is consistent. But further; why may not the material universe be the necessarily existent being, according to this pretended explication of necessity? We dare not affirm that we know all the qualities of matter; and for aught we can determine, it may contain some qualities, which, were they known, would make its non-existence appear as great a contradiction as that twice two is five. I find only one 72

David Hume: Critique of Cosmological Argument argument employed to prove, that the material world is not the necessarily existent being; and this argument is derived from the contingency both of the matter and form of the world. Any particle of matter, it is said, may be conceived to be annihilated; and any form may be conceived to be altered. Such an annihilation or alteration, therefore, is not impossible. But it seems a great partiality not to perceive, that the same argument extends equally to the Deity, so far as we have any conception of him; and that the mind can at least imagine him to be non-existent, or his attributes to be altered. It must be some unknown, inconceivable qualities, which can make his non-existence appear impossible, or his attributes unalterable: And no reason can be assigned, why these qualities may not belong to matter. As they are altogether unknown and inconceivable, they can never be proved incompatible with it. Add to this, that in tracing an eternal succession of objects, it seems absurd to inquire for a general cause or first author. How can anything that exists from eternity, have a cause, since that relation implies a priority in time, and a beginning of existence? In such a chain, too, or succession of objects, each part is caused by that which preceded it, and causes that which succeeds it. Where then is the difficulty? But the whole, you say, wants a cause. I answer, that the uniting of these parts into a whole, like the uniting of several distinct countries into one kingdom, or several members into one body, is performed merely by an arbitrary act of the mind, and has no influence on the nature of things. Did I show you the particular causes of each individual in a collection of twenty particles of matter? I should think it very unreasonable, should you afterwards ask me, what was the cause of the whole twenty? This is sufficiently explained in explaining the cause of the parts. Though the reasoning which you have urged, Cleanthes, may well excuse me, said Philo, from starting any further difficulties, yet I cannot forbear insisting still upon another topic. It is observed by arithmeticians that the products of 9, compose always either 9, or some lesser product of 9, if you add together all the characters of which any of the former products are composed. Thus, of 18, 27, 36, which are products of 9, you make 9 by adding 1 to 8, 2 to 7, 3 to 6. To a superficial observer, so wonderful a regularity may be admired as the effect of chance or design. But a skillful algebraist immediately concludes it to be the work of necessity, and demonstrates, 73

Part II. The Philosophy of Religion that it must forever result from the nature of these numbers. Is it not probable, I ask, that the whole economy of the universe is conducted by a like necessity, though no human algebra can furnish a key which solves the difficulty? And instead of admiring the order of natural beings, may it not happen, that, could we penetrate into the intimate nature of bodies, we should clearly see why it was absolutely impossible they could never admit of any other disposition? So dangerous is it to introduce this idea of necessity into the present question and so naturally does it afford an inference directly opposite to the religious hypothesis! From David Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, 1779. 74