May 10, 2007 McGill University. Little or Nothing. Rajesh Bhatt. University of Massachusetts at Amherst

Similar documents
LINGUIST 601 Assigned on November 30, 2006 Due on December 12, Assignment 11

Exercises Introduction to morphosyntax

Neg-Raising. The Case of Persian. Zahra Mirrazi & Ali Darzi University of Massachusetts, Amherst University of Tehran. April 28, 2017.

Reconsidering Raising and Experiencers in English

Pronominal, temporal and descriptive anaphora

Factivity and Presuppositions David Schueler University of Minnesota, Twin Cities LSA Annual Meeting 2013

Solutions for Assignment 1

Brainstorming exercise

Exhaustification over Questions in Japanese

Reference Resolution. Regina Barzilay. February 23, 2004

Reference Resolution. Announcements. Last Time. 3/3 first part of the projects Example topics

Final Exam due on December 13, 2001

Houghton Mifflin English 2001 Houghton Mifflin Company Grade Three. correlated to. IOWA TESTS OF BASIC SKILLS Forms M Level 9

PASSIVES IN SOME SOUTH ASIAN LANGUAGES: A COMPARATIVE INVESTIGATION

A Typology of Clause Combining

NEGATED PERFECTS AND TEMPORAL IN-ADVERBIALS *

A Freezing Approach to the Ish-Construction in English

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

Introduction to Transformational Grammar, LINGUIST 601 December 3, Wh-Movement

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

CAS LX 523 Syntax II February 10, 2009 Prep for week 5: The fine structure of the left periphery

What is infinitival to?

Extra Syntax Exercises 5

Houghton Mifflin English 2001 Houghton Mifflin Company Grade Four. correlated to. IOWA TESTS OF BASIC SKILLS Forms M Level 10

If I hadn t studied as much as I did, I wouldn t have passed my exams.

Houghton Mifflin English 2004 Houghton Mifflin Company Level Four correlated to Tennessee Learning Expectations and Draft Performance Indicators

Some Anaphoric/Elliptical Constructions of English

ANAPHORIC REFERENCE IN JUSTIN BIEBER S ALBUM BELIEVE ACOUSTIC

ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang. Changchun University, Changchun, China

, and Imperfect Verbs

The Whys and How Comes of Presupposition and NPI Licensing in Questions

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

Introduction to Koiné Greek

Anaphora Resolution in Hindi Language

Long-distance anaphora: comparing Mandarin Chinese with Iron Range English 1

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Extraposition and Covert Movement

Question Formulation Made Simple. By Daniel M. Schweissing Community College of Aurora

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

3. Negations Not: contradicting content Contradictory propositions Overview Connectives

Abdul Hameed Adam - poems -

Lesson 7: Pain. In today's chapters Jonas receives painful memories from The Giver. How do you think he will respond to these memories?

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Cohen 2004: Existential Generics Shay Hucklebridge LING 720

Adverb Clause. 1. They checked their gear before they started the climb. (modifies verb checked)

Biased Questions. William A. Ladusaw. 28 May 2004

TURCOLOGICA. Herausgegeben von Lars Johanson. Band 98. Harrassowitz Verlag Wiesbaden

ESL 340: Noun Clauses. Week 5, Thur. 2/15/18 Todd Windisch, Spring 2018

THE FOURTH CREATIVE "DAY" of GENESIS

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes, Silver Level '2002 Correlated to: Oregon Language Arts Content Standards (Grade 8)

Prentice Hall Literature: Timeless Voices, Timeless Themes, Bronze Level '2002 Correlated to: Oregon Language Arts Content Standards (Grade 7)

Pragmatic Presupposition

LISTENING AND VIEWING: CA 5 Comprehending and Evaluating the Content and Artistic Aspects of Oral and Visual Presentations

By the Time Viewing relative progress or completion

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

That -clauses as existential quantifiers

Russell: On Denoting

Russell on Plurality

INTONATION PATTERNS. In the English Language

Correlation to Georgia Quality Core Curriculum

*HAPPY NEW YEAR* Soch rahe ho aaj kyon...? Ab tum DON ko sikhaaoge kab wish karna hai. DON ek din pehle wish kare ya 41 din pehle uski marzi.

StoryTown Reading/Language Arts Grade 2

Subject Index. Index

Category Mistakes in M&E

Epistemic Modals Seth Yalcin

Discourse Constraints on Anaphora Ling 614 / Phil 615 Sponsored by the Marshall M. Weinberg Fund for Graduate Seminars in Cognitive Science

The structure of this lecture. 1. Introduction (coordination vs. subordination) 2. Types of subordinate clauses 3. Functions of subordinate clauses

On the interaction of adjectival modifiers and relative clauses

GRAMMAR IV HIGH INTERMEDIATE

A Scopal Theory of Presupposition I

Logophors, variable binding and the interpretation of have. *

Four Proposals for German Clause Structure

Neg-raising and positive polarity: The view from modals

Affirmation-Negation: New Perspective

Lexical Alternatives as a Source of Pragmatic Presuppositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Table of Contents 1-30

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND CONDITIONAL ASSERTIONS

Romans Chapter Translation

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Arabic Immersion Advanced Level / SPLA025

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions

'ONLY' IN IMPERATIVES

Identity and Plurals

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

Houghton Mifflin English 2004 Houghton Mifflin Company Grade Six. correlated to. TerraNova, Second Edition Level 16

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

An alternative understanding of interpretations: Incompatibility Semantics

The backtracking conditional in this example has been singled out below:

Kai von Fintel (MIT)

7.1. Unit. Terms and Propositions. Nature of propositions. Types of proposition. Classification of propositions

Towards a Solution to the Proviso Problem

Logic: A Brief Introduction

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Transcription:

May 10, 2007 McGill University Little or Nothing 1 Different Kinds of Negation Rajesh Bhatt University of Massachusetts at Amherst bhatt@linguist.umass.edu In addition to the use of a dedicated negative marker such as not, the determiner no, noun phrases like nothing, and adverbs like nowhere, never, English has at least two other means for conveying negative meanings. The first involves the use of counterfactual morphology and the second, which will be our focus here, the use of expressions like few and little. (1) a. I wish I was tall. b. I read few Basque novels/ate little fried cheese during my stay in Spain. The properties of the dedicated negative marker and the fact that the South Asian languages only use the sentential negation strategy (nahĩ:, na:, mat in Hindi-Urdu) and lack altogether nominal negation has been well-documented (Bhatia (1978), Bhatia (1979), Kumar (2006) i.a.). The use of counterfactual morphology - the untensed habitual in Hindi-Urdu - to construct negative meanings has also been noted (Masica (1991)). (2) a. kaash mẽ amiir ho-taa: wish I rich be-hab.msg I wish I was rich. b. [tum amiir ho-te] to tumhẽ gairõ-ke-saamne haath nahĩ: phailaa-ne you rich be-hab.msg then you.dat others-gen-front hands Neg spread-inf.mpl paṛ-te have.to-hab.mpl If you were rich, you wouldn t have to spread your hands in front of others. In contrast the few/little strategy has not received much attention within the discussion of South Asian languages. In fact I am not aware that the existence of this strategy has even been documented. (3) provides an example of this strategy. (3) mẽ I kitaab phaaṛ-taa thoṛii. (sirf dhamkii de rahaa thaa) book tear-hab.msg LITTLE only threat give Prog.MSg be.pst.msg I wouldn t (actually) have torn the book. I was just threatening to do so. 1

2 Nominal Usage of thoṛaa The word thoṛaa few/little is ordinarily a adjective-like element that appears in the nominal domain. It can combine with the adverbial bahut very and with the element -saa like. Like other adjectives ending in -aa, it agrees with the head noun. The noun modified by tho daa can be mass or count but if the noun is a count noun, it has to be plural. The overall pattern can be summarized as follows: if thoṛaa displays plural agreement, it can be translated as few, otherwise as little. (4) a. count noun: (bahut) thoṛii(-sii) very little.f-like.f Very few books sold. b. mass noun: thoṛii(-sii) mirch/bewafaai little.f-like.f chillies/infidelity a little chillies/infidelity c. singular agreement: mass noun kitaabẽ bik-ĩ: book.fpl sold-pfv.fpl thoṛa(-saa) namak/*thoṛaa-(saa) baccaa little.msg-like.msg salt.m/*little.msg-like.msg by.msg a little salt/*few boy d. plural agreement: count noun thoṛe(-se) amruud/*namak little.msg-like.msg guava.m/salt.m a few guavas/*a few salt thoṛaa little does not behave as negation when it appears as a nominal modifier. In the nominal domain, it functions purely as a marker of low quantity. 1 In this it contrasts with the English few/little and patterns instead with a few/a little. (5) a. John reads few books, if any. (= (John reads many books); compatible with John having read none.) b. John read a few books, #if any. (= There is a small number of books s.t. John read them; incompatible with John having read none.) c. John did little preparation for the exam, if any. (= (John did much preparation); compatible with John having done no preparation.) d. John did a little preparation for the exam, #if any. (= There is a small amount of preparation that John did for this exam; incompatible with John having done no preparation at all.) 1 There is also a marker of high quantity zyaadaa lot. 2

a few/a little has existential import, which is not the case with few/little. And the nominal usage of thoṛaa has a similar existential import. Thus (6) would not be true in a circumstance where no book sold at all. (6) thoṛii(-hi:) kitaabẽ few.f-only book.fpl (Only) a few books sold. bik-ĩ: sold-pfv.fpl That we do not get the negative meaning in the nominal domain can be seen as part of the general absence of the nominal expression of negation in the South Asian languages, which has been noted above. 3 Adverbial thoṛii as Negation: Parallels with nahĩ: To get the negative meaning, we have to go to the adverbial/sentential domain. We have already seen one example in (3). Further examples are provided in (7). The adverbial counterpart is always thoṛii, never thoṛe/aa. (7) a. Mahesh-ko kisi-ne invite thoṛii kiyaa thaa Mahesh-KO someone-erg invite LITTLE do.pfv be.pst No one had invited Mahesh. b. Timur Manu-ko ḍã:ṭ-taa thoṛii thaa Timur Manu-KO scold-hab LITTLE be.pst Timur didn t used to scold Manu. c. yeh saamaan bik-egaa thoṛii this stuff sell-fut.msg LITTLE The stuff won t well. (7a-c) are well-formed even without the thoṛii, though of course the polarity is flipped. The meanings of (7a-c) are close to the corresponding sentences with thoṛii replaced by the negative marker nahĩ:. 3.1 Indeclinability One difference between adverbial thoṛii and its nominal counterpart is that the former is indeclinable. The adverbial counterpart does not agree with any nominal element and is always thoṛii, never thoṛaa. It is possible that thoṛii is a contraction of thoṛe plus the focus marker -hii. This is suggested by the fact that some speakers pronounce this element as thoṛe-hii. thoṛe is the oblique form of thoṛaa little. 2 2 For me, the thoṛe-hii form is dispreferred. I wonder if the speakers who can use thoṛe-hii can optionally drop the -hii and just use thoṛe also. 3

Such a decomposition of thoṛii is attractive in that we have an additional parallel with nahĩ:, which has also been claimed to consist of naa plus the focus marker -hii. We also are able to explain the otherwise puzzling feminine inflection on thoṛii. One does not expect the default/indeclinable form to be the feminine form. But it should be noted that the interchangeability between thoṛe-hii and thoṛii is only limited to the adverbial/negation environments. In its nominal usage thoṛe plus -hii is not interchangeable with thoṛii: (8) thoṛe-hii/*thoṛii akhbaar bik-e little.mpl-foc/little newspaper.m sell-pfv.mpl Only a few newspapers sold. 3.2 Constituent Negation Another parallel with the negative marker is that just as nahĩ: can be used as a marker of constituent negation, so can thoṛii. Constituent negation in Hindi-Urdu right adjoins to any XPs it modifies. This is also the case with thoṛii. As a result, thoṛii can appear in practically any position other than sentence-initial. In general, its acceptability in a position parallels the acceptability of nahĩ: in that position. (9) (*thoṛii) Mona-ne LITTLE Mona-Erg Mona hadn t scolded Ghizala. (thoṛii) Ghizala-ko (thoṛii) ḍã:ṭ-aa (thoṛii) thaa (*thoṛii) LITTLE Ghizala-ko LITTLE scold-pfv LITTLE be.pst LITTLE (The exact meaning depends upon the placement of thoṛii. If it follows Mona, it would mean It wasn t Mona who had scolded Ghizala ) But the parallel between constituent negation by nahĩ: and constituent negation by thoṛii is not complete. Constituent negation by nahĩ: seems to require a counterpart of the negated constituent. (10) a. without counterpart: degradation #Mira-ne Tushar-ko Mira-Erg Tushar-Dat nahĩ: kitaab dii thii Neg book.f give.pfv.f be.pst.f #Mira had given the book not to Tushar. b. with counterpart: good Mira-ne Tushar-ko nahĩ: Madhukar-ko kitaab dii thii Mira-Erg Tushar-Dat Neg Madhukar-Dat book.f give.pfv.f be.pst.f Mira had given the book not to Tushar but to Madhukar. The judgements with thoṛii seem to be reversed. Here the counterpart-less cases are perfect but the cases with a counterpart seem slightly degraded. 4

(11) a. without counterpart: good Mira-ne Tushar-ko thoṛii kitaab dii thii Mira-Erg Tushar-Dat LITTLE book.f give.pfv.f be.pst.f #Mira had given the book not to Tushar. b. with counterpart: midly degraded??mira-ne Tushar-ko Mira-Erg Tushar-Dat thoṛii Madhukar-ko kitaab dii thii LITTLE Madhukar-Dat book.f give.pfv.f be.pst.f Mira had given the book not to Tushar but to Madhukar. 3.3 A constraint against Double Negation Hindi-Urdu does not allow for two instances of negation to appear within a minimal finite clause. This restriction seems to hold even if the two instances of negation are not of the same kind syntactically i.e. if one is a sentential negation and the other is a constituent negation. (12) a. two(?) sentential negations: *Deepesh-ne kitaab Deepesh-Erg book.f nahĩ: Neg nahĩ: Neg paṛh-ii read-pfv.f intended meaning: Deepesh didn t not read the book. b. one sentential negation and one constituent negation:???deepesh-ne nahĩ: Mona-ne Deepesh-Erg Neg Mona-Erg kitaab nahĩ: book.f Neg paṛh-ii read-pfv.f intended meaning: It was Mona, not Deepesh, who didn t read the book. Any combination of nahĩ: and thoṛii leads to ungrammaticality, or at least oddness. (13) two(?) sentential negations: a. *Deepesh-ne kitaab nahĩ: thoṛii paṛh-ii Deepesh-Erg book.f Neg LITTLE read-pfv.f intended meaning: Deepesh didn t not read the book. b. *Deepesh-ne kitaab thoṛii nahĩ: paṛh-ii Deepesh-Erg book.f LITTLE Neg read-pfv.f intended meaning: Deepesh didn t not read the book. c. *Deepesh-ne kitaab thoṛii thoṛii paṛh-ii Deepesh-Erg book.f LITTLE LITTLE read-pfv.f intended meaning: Deepesh didn t not read the book. (14) one sentential negation and one constituent negation: a.???deepesh-ne nahĩ: Mona-ne Deepesh-Erg Neg Mona-Erg kitaab thoṛii paṛh-ii book.f LITTLE read-pfv.f intended meaning: It was Mona, not Deepesh, who didn t read the book. 5

b.???deepesh-ne thoṛii kitaab thoṛii paṛh-ii Deepesh-Erg Neg book.f LITTLE read-pfv.f intended meaning: It wasn t Deepesh who didn t read the book. Curiously the following where the thoṛii contributes the constituent negation and the nahĩ: the sentential negation seems a bit better: (15)?(?)Deepesh-ne thoṛii Deepesh-Erg LITTLE kitaab nahĩ: book.f Neg paṛh-ii read-pfv.f intended meaning: It wasn t Deepesh who didn t read the book. 4 Adverbial thoṛii as Negation: Divergences from nahĩ: But nahĩ: and thoṛii are not fully parallel. The negative meaning contributed by thoṛii always has an emphatic element. It would be odd out of the blue. Consider again (3, repeated below as 16) - this is felt to respond to a situation where the hearer thinks that the speaker is about to tear the book. (16) mẽ I kitaab phaaṛ-taa thoṛii. (sirf dhamkii de rahaa thaa) book tear-hab.msg LITTLE only threat give Prog.MSg be.pst.msg I wouldn t (actually) have torn the book. I was just threatening to do so. Likewise in (7a-c, repeated below as 17a-c), there is a background proposition which is assumed or at least being entertained. In (17c), the hearer might think that the things will sell and the speaker is disabusing the hearer of this notion. (17) a. Mahesh-ko kisi-ne invite thoṛii kiyaa thaa Mahesh-KO someone-erg invite LITTLE do.pfv be.pst No one had invited Mahesh. b. Timur Manu-ko ḍã:ṭ-taa thoṛii thaa Timur Manu-KO scold-hab LITTLE be.pst Timur didn t used to scold Manu. c. yeh saamaan bik-egaa thoṛii this stuff sell-fut.msg LITTLE The stuff won t well. 4.1 The Presuppositional Nature of thoṛii The intuition is that the proposition negated by thoṛii needs to be in the immediately preceding discourse. A structure with thoṛii can only indicate disagreement with the polarity of the relevant proposition. It cannot actually introduce the proposition itself. This is shown clearly by the following contrast between nahĩ: and thoṛii: 6

(18) I say to my friend: Tell me something about your friend Yashesh. He replies: a. ok response: Yashesh-ko aalsii log pasand nahĩ: hẽ Yashesh-Dat lazy people like Neg be.prs.pl Yashesh doesn t like lazy people. b. bizarre response: #Yashesh-ko Yashesh-Dat aalsii log pasand thoṛii hẽ lazy people like Neg be.prs.pl Yashesh doesn t like lazy people. Intuition: The negation contributed by thoṛii can only deny propositions that have already been asserted in the discourse. We could formalize this in the following manner: (19) thoṛii (p) a. Presupposition: p has been asserted in the preceding discourse b. Assertion: p is false A consequence that follows from this formalization: the negation contributed by thoṛii takes scope over everything else in the clause. 4.2 Scope with PPIs and NPIs This intuition is supported by the fact that positive polarity items like kuchh some.pl, which escape the scope of nahĩ:, are unable to escape the scope of thoṛii leading to ungrammaticality. (20) a. kucch laṛkõ-ne mujhe tohfe nahĩ: diye some.pl boys-erg me.dat presents.m Neg give.pfv.mpl Some boys did not give me a present. b. #kucch laṛkõ-ne mujhe tohfe thoṛii diye some.pl boys-erg me.dat presents.m LITTLE give.pfv.mpl (21) a. Yashesh-ne kuch kitaabẽ nahĩ: paṛh-ĩ: Yashesh-ne some.pl books.fpl Neg read-pfv.fpl There were some books such that Yashesh did not read them. b. #Yashesh-ne kuch Yashesh-ne some.pl kitaabẽ thoṛii paṛh-ĩ: books.fpl Neg read-pfv.fpl There were some books such that Yashesh did not read them. (22) NPI-Licensing 7

a. ek-bhii laṛke-ne Mona-se baat nahĩ: kii one-psi boy-erg Mona-Instr talk.f Neg do.pfv.f Not even one buy talked to Mona. b. ek-bhii laṛke-ne Mona-se baat thoṛii kii one-psi boy-erg Mona-Instr talk.f Neg do.pfv.f Not even one buy talked to Mona. (23) Anti-licensing of Positive Polarity Compound Verbs a. Mina-ne phal khaa (#nahĩ:) liyaa Mina-Erg fruit.msg eat Neg TAKE.Pfv.MSg Mina ate the apple. b. Mina-ne phal khaa (#thoṛii) liyaa Mina-Erg fruit.msg eat Neg TAKE.Pfv.MSg Mina ate the apple. 4.3 Licensing of Auxiliary Deletion The nahĩ: negation allows for optionality of the present tense auxiliary in the habitual and the progressive. (24) a. negation of present habitual: Ramesh doodh nahĩ: pii-taa Ramesh.M milk Neg drink-hab.msg Ramesh doesn t drink milk. b. negation of counterfactual: agar if tum us-se kah-te to-bhii Ramesh doodh nahĩ: you him-instr say-hab.mpl then-also Ramesh.M milk Neg Even if you had told him to do so, Ramesh wouldn t have drunk milk. c. negation of counterfactual: (consequent) Ramesh doodh thoṛii pii-taa Ramesh.M milk LITTLE drink-hab.msg Ramesh wouldn t have drunk milk. d. negation of counterfactual: Ramesh doodh pii-taa thoṛii Ramesh.M milk drink-hab.msg LITTLE Ramesh wouldn t have drunk the milk. e. negation of present/past habitual: Ramesh doodh pii-taa thoṛii hai/thaa Ramesh.M milk drink-hab.msg LITTLE be.prs.sg/be.pst.sg It s not the case that Ramesh drinks/used to drink milk. pii-taa drink-hab.msg - it is not in the right syntactic environment to license auxiliary deletion. Cases like (24d) do not actually involve auxiliary deletion - only a counterfactual which always lacks an auxiliary. 8

- does not license deletion of auxiliary with the progressive rahaa (25) context: sister compaining about her brother to their mother: a. nahĩ: licenses auxiliary deletion with the progressive: Mahesh doodh nahĩ: pii rahaa Mahesh.m milk Neg drink Prog.MSg Mahesh is not drinking milk. (he is refusing to drink milk.) b. thoṛii does not: *Mahesh doodh thoṛii pii rahaa Mahesh.m milk Neg drink Prog.MSg Mahesh is not drinking milk. (he is refusing to drink milk.) c. control example: Mahesh doodh thoṛii pii rahaa hai/thaa Mahesh.m milk Neg drink Prog.MSg be.prs.sg/be.pst.sg Mahesh is not drinking milk. (exact meaning depends upon intonation and placement of thoṛii, no refusing-to-drink meaning) 5 Distribution of Little 5.1 Embeddability The presuppositional requirements of thoṛii which require that the proposition negated by thoṛii be asserted in the preceding context and that only matrix propositions can be asserted impose strict restrictions on the possibility of thoṛii in embedded environments. because clauses: (26) a. nahĩ: can be embedded in a because clause: Nirupama-ne Shirish-se mil-naa band kar diyaa kyõ-ki Shirish Nirupama-Erg Shirsh-Instr meet-inf stop do GIVE.Pfv because Shirish.m us-ke daddy-ko pasand nahĩ: aa-yaa Dem.Obl-Gen.Obl daddy-dat like Neg come-pfv.msg Nirupama stopped talking to Shirish because her father did not like him. b. thoṛii cannot: *Nirupama-ne Shirish-se mil-naa band kar diyaa kyõ-ki Shirish Nirupama-Erg Shirsh-Instr meet-inf stop do GIVE.Pfv because Shirish.m us-ke daddy-ko pasand thoṛii aa-yaa Dem.Obl-Gen.Obl daddy-dat like LITTLE come-pfv.msg Nirupama stopped talking to Shirish because her father did not like him. 9

counterfactuals: (27) a. kaash [mẽ wish I.MSg I wish I was not poor. b. #kaash [mẽ wish I.MSg I wish I was not poor. (28) a. [agar Prakhar-ne is Prakhar-Erg gariib na: ho-taa] poor Neg be-hab.msg gariib thoṛii ho-taa] poor LITTLE be-hab.msg chori: nahĩ: ki: ho-ti:] [to vo aaj yahã ho-taa] theft.f Neg do.pfv.f be-hab.fsg then he today here be-hab If Prakhar hadn t stolen, he would have been here today. b. [agar Prakhar-ne is Prakhar-Erg chori: (#thoṛii) ki: ho-ti:] [to vo aaj yahã ho-taa] theft.f LITTLE do.pfv.f be-hab.fsg then he today here be-hab If Prakhar had stolen, he would have been here today. embedded complement clauses: (29) a. mujhe pataa hai ki Prakhar beimaan nahĩ: hai: me.dat known be.prs.sg that Prakhar.M dishonest Neg be.prs.sg I know that Prakhar is not dishonest. b.??mujhe pataa me.dat known hai ki Prakhar beimaan thoṛii hai: be.prs.sg that Prakhar.M dishonest LITTLE be.prs.sg I know that Prakhar is not dishonest. expletive negation in until clauses: (30) a. (for some speakers but not all nahĩ: is optional here.) [jab-tak train nahĩ: aa-ii] [tab-tak Saimaa platform-par baiṭhii rah-ii] when-till train.f Neg arrive-pfv.f then-till Saimaa.f platform-on seated.f stay-pfv.f Saimaa stayed at the station until the train arrive. b. #[jab-tak train thoṛii aa-ii] [tab-tak Saimaa platform-par baiṭhii rah-ii] when-till train.f Neg arrive-pfv.f then-till Saimaa.f platform-on seated.f stay-pfv.f Saimaa stayed at the station until the train arrive. 10

5.2 Interactions with Questions Negation is possible in both Y/N questions and wh-questions. (31) a. Y/N question + Neg: kyaa Mohit-ne Q Mohit-Erg Sita-se baat nahĩ: Sita-Instr talk.f Neg Did Mohit not talk to Sita? b. wh- question + Neg: kii? do.pfv.f Mohit-ne kis-se baat nahĩ: kii? Mohit-Erg who-instr talk.f Neg do.pfv.f Who did Mohit not talk to? But thoṛii is not compatible with either kind of question. (32) a. Y/N question + thoṛii: * *kyaa Mohit-ne Q Mohit-Erg Did Mohit not talk to Sita? b. wh- question + thoṛii: * *Mohit-ne kis-se Mohit-Erg who-instr Who did Mohit not talk to? Sita-se baat thoṛii kii? Sita-Instr talk.f LITTLE do.pfv.f baat thoṛii kii? talk.f LITTLE do.pfv.f This is reminiscent of a similar restriction noted in Kidwai (2000) for the topic marker -to: (33) a. Y/N question + -to: * *kyaa Mohit-ne-to Q Mohit-Erg-Top Did Mohit talk to Sita? b. wh- question + -to: * Sita-se baat kii? Sita-Instr talk.f do.pfv.f *Mohit-ne-to kis-se baat kii? Mohit-Erg-Top who-instr talk.f do.pfv.f Who did Mohit talk to? This restriction follows from the presupposition of thoṛii - it needs to negate an asserted proposition. This leads to a pragmatic confound. 11

References Bhatia, T. K. (1978) A syntactic and semantic description of negation in south asian languages, Doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois-Urbana, Urbana-Champaign, Illinois. Bhatia, T. K. (1979) Negation in South Asian Languages, in B. Kachru, H. H. Hock, and Y. Kachru, eds., South Asian Languages Analysis Vol. 1, Dept. of Linguistics, University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign, 1 12. Kidwai, A. (2000) XP-adjunction in universal grammar: scrambling and binding in Hindi-Urdu, Oxford studies in comparative syntax, Oxford University Press, New York, NY. Kumar, R. (2006) The Syntax of Negation and the Licensing of Negative Polarity Items in Hindi, Outstanding Dissertations in Linguistics, Routledge, London. Masica, C. (1991) The Indo-Aryan Languages, Cambridge Language Surveys, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England. 12