Assertion and Inference

Similar documents
Keeping track of individuals

Brandom on Facts, Claims, and Deflationism about Truth

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Politicizing Brandom s Pragmatism: Normativity and the Agonal Character of

MAKING NORMATIVITY EXPLICIT

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

From the Second to the Third Person and Back Again: Habermas and Brandom on Discursive Practice. Steven Hendley

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Brandom s Pragmatist Inferentialism and the Problem of Objectivity Ulrich Reichard University of Durham

Conversation with Robert Brandom

I. In the ongoing debate on the meaning of logical connectives 1, two families of

Anaphoric Deflationism: Truth and Reference

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

Combining Pricean and Peircean Pragmatism. Henrik Rydenfelt

Pragmatism and Inferentialism

Horwich and the Liar

My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Brandom on the Normativity of Meaning

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Normativity and Concepts. Hannah Ginsborg, U.C. Berkeley. June 2016

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Is Logic Demarcated by its Expressive Role?

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Critical Scientific Realism

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Indexicality, Opacity, and Perspectivality

THESES SIS/LIBRARY TELEPHONE:

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

Aboutness and Justification

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

Brandom, Wittgenstein and Intersubjectivity 1

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Putnam and the Contextually A Priori Gary Ebbs University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Brandom s Account of Defeasible Reasoning: Problems and Solutions

Learning and the Necessity of Non-Conceptual Content in Sellars Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind *

Coordination Problems

ANAPHORIC REFERENCE IN JUSTIN BIEBER S ALBUM BELIEVE ACOUSTIC

Florida Philosophical Review Volume XIV, Issue 1, Winter Ryan Simonelli, New College of Florida

Review Article Blueprint for a Science of Mind:

Brandom s five-step program for modal health

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

NORTON ANTHOLOGY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY: AFTER KANT TABLE OF CONTENTS. Volume 2: The Analytic Tradition. Preface Acknowledgments GENERAL INTRODUCTION

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Is There Immediate Justification?

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Varieties of Apriority

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Kant and his Successors

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Philosophy Courses-1

WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

deduction to a chain. The chain has many links: we survey the links one after the

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

PRESTON STOVALL PH.D. CANDIDATE ACLS FELLOW DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

semantic-extensional interpretation that happens to satisfy all the axioms.

Philosophy Courses-1

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Teleology, Intentionality and Acting for Reasons In this paper I would like to contrast two radically different approaches to the evident linkage

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Part I Semantic Pragmatism

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

TWO CONCEPTIONS OF THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. Marian David Notre Dame University

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

A Comparison of Davidson s and McDowell s Accounts of Perceptual Beliefs

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres

MAKING "REASONS" EXPLICIT HOW NORMATIVE IS BRANDOM'S INFERENTIALISM? Daniel Laurier

Transcription:

Assertion and Inference Carlo Penco 1 1 Università degli studi di Genova via Balbi 4 16126 Genova (Italy) www.dif.unige.it/epi/hp/penco penco@unige.it Abstract. In this introduction to the tutorials I will give a brief sketch of the place of Brandom's ideas in the network of "classical" authors, focusing on some of the central tenets introduced by Making it Explicit (MIE), which antecedes the ideas developed in Between Saying and Doing (BSD). I give here a schematic presentation with some references to pages in MIE and BSD.. 1 Classic Authors: Background Differently from many contemporary analytic authors, Brandom makes often references to classical philosophical traditions, from rationalism to pragmatism, and rerences to classical authors are easy to find in his books. Among these authors I think it useful to quote what I think are some of the main contributions in Brandom's work: Kant contributes as the typical representative of rationalism and for his conception of normativity: to be rational is to be bound by rules (both in theoretical judgements and in practical actions); the authority of rules derives by our endorsing them, by our acting according to our conceptions of the rules (MIE 50-52; see 30-36) Frege is taken first of all as the author who claims the priority of judgment over concepts - recovering a Kantian idea which has dismissed by Kant's successors - and his consequent idea of the sense of a sentence as its inferential potential. The other main aspect of Frege is the distinction between conceptual content and force, a distinction basic for any pragmatic account (MIE 79-81; 107-116). Dewey and Peirce are taken to reinterpret what is meant with "pragmatism", insisting on what one is doing when one takes something as true. To understand the use of "true" we need to clarify what we are doing when we make a claim, when we make an assertion (MIE 286-288). Wittgenstein is taken first of all as the author of rule following considerations. Brandom claims that the Wittgensteinian point is to make sense of the idea of norms implicit in practice, which can avoid the reduction of understanding to interpretation on the one hand or to natural reactions on the other. The point is that norms belong to a custom, a practice or institution (MIE 29; see also McDowell 1984). Sellars, who is said to have introduced Kant into Analytic Philosophy, is taken as an example of the reaction against the myth of the given (see introd. to Sellars 1997)

and as the proponent of the basic idea of what he calls "socratic method", that is "a way of bringing our practices under rational control, by expressing them explicitly in a form in which they can be confronted with objections and alternatives." (MIE 106) 2 Basic Ideas: Background Beside these general ideas there are more specific points which Brandom takes from different authors although expressing doubts and reservations. Brandom's work is entangled with a complex networks of concepts and topics (from material inferences, to conservativeness, from preception to substitution ) which cannot be easily summarized I will speake therefore of some of the concepts Brandom partially takes from other authors. to give at least a hint on some influences on his thought. This will be useful to find at least a thread to follow: his treatment of assertion. Ludwig Wittgenstein's influence is linked to his treatment of rule following and language games; however Brandom puts some doubt on Wittgenstein's conception of language games, as they included just "vocal" practice which do not deserve to be called language games (Brandom is referring to the language game of the builders in Wittgenstein 1953, 2; see MIE 172 and BSD 42). Here Brandom's stance is that to have a proper language game you need to have the practice of assertion. Wilfrid Sellars: Brandom refers strictly to Sellar's notion of "game of giving and asking for reasons". It is a notion of language game where assertions are the basic case: we ask for the grounds of an assertion and are ready to give reasons for what we assert. An assertion is something which stands in need of a reason and it is also something that can be offered as a reason. (MIE 167) Michael Dummett's theory of meaning as use has received much attention in Brandom's work, taking Dummett's idea that we need to generalize Gentzen's model of introduction and elimination rules for logic to a general theory o meaning (MIE 116-118): learning to use a statement involve the mastery of the conditions under which we can justify the statement and the the consequences of accepting it. Against Dummet's idea to restrict a systematic theory of meaning only to the justification (or assertibility) conditions, Brandom insists on treating also the consequences, giving a prominent role to the commitment of accepting the consequences of our assertions (the reason is that assertions with the same assertibility conditions may have different consequences MIE 121-122). David Lewis 1974 suggests the fundamental idea of scorekeeping; he suggests to treat our normal rule governed conversation as a game which evolves according to scorekeeping like it happens in baseball; the element of the conversational score are things like presuppositions, boudaries between permissible and impermissible actions, and so on. Scorekeeping in conversation is perspectival: playing a conversational game means, among other things, that different people keep track of the commitments and entitlements of the other participants, attributing them commitments and entitlements. Richard Rorty was a teacher of Brandom and his main influence is to be found in the attempt to build a philosophy where "representation" is not the first step. Fighting

against the idea that philosophy must be the "mirror of nature" (Rorty 1980), Brandom tries to recover objectivity through inference and social practice. Charles Chastain 1975 suggested a unusual way of thinking of Kripke's treatment proper names. While Kripke said that the reference of a proper name is fixed through a causal chain, Chastain begun to think to the actual ways we keep a chain of reference going: anaphora, that is the use of picking what antecedes in a discourse with pronouns and other indexicals (John had a daughter; she was very nice "). Causal chains become in this perspective a disguised way to speak of anaphoric chains. Discussing the basic role of indexicals and demostratives (deixis) in the structuring of our context dependent utterances,brandom reaches a strong conclusion: deixis presupposes anaphora, given that no use of demostratives can be properly set out unless in a chain of anaphoric links; to use a demonstrative is first of all to put an anaphoric initiator (MIE 307-310). Donald Davidson is another main source of inspiration for Brandom, from the theory of triangulation to the treatment of indirect speec; here I want to point to one of the main tenet of Davidons's philosophy, that is meaning holism. The mastery of the meaning, or the use of an expression involve mastery of the uses of many expressions. Meaning holism has been accused of making communication impossible; an aswer is to pass from the idea of communication in terms of sharing or grasping a common meaning to an idea of communication as cooperating in a joint activity (MIE 479). 3 Assertion and Inference One of the central point of Brandom's original inferentialism is the definition of the meaning of a sentence in terms of its inferential power, as a development of what Frege had said in his Begriffsschrift ( 3). To understand a sentence is to understand its consequences, given certain collateral assumptions, and to understand the grounds for asserting it (grounds which may be logical but also perceptual: apparently to see something red is a ground to assert that something is red). Brandom develops his particular way of an inferential semantics, where the definition of conceptual content is specified (grossly) as a point in a network of inferences. Apparently one need not to know the impossible task to know all the inferences connected to a concept; one will count as mastering the concept if he is able to make enough of the right inferences in the context in which the concept is used. Inferential semantics alone would take a lot of space to be summarized; here I want to point to the way in which inferential semantics is embedded inside a normative pragmatics. Normative status and material incompatibility of commitments We might see the attempt to connect inferential semantics to normative pragmatics as a way fo specifying - in Austin terminology - felicity conditions of assertions. Going back to Sellars terminology we may say that to make an assertion implies to be able to play the game of giving and asking for reasons. Standard felicity conditions for an assertion say that the speaker should sincerely believe what he assert and also have justifications for the content of the assertions. Brandom, as we have seen, insists also on the necessity to give space to the recognition of the consequences of an asser-

tion. He gives us therefore two normative dimensions which form what we might call the felicity condition of a correct assertion: 1 entitlements: a speaker must have justification for what she asserts, she must be entitled by some objectively recognizable grounds (either logical or emprical) 2 commitments: a speaker must commit herself to the consequences of what she asserts, given her mastery of the conditional relation. Commitments and entitlements are normative statuses needed for a speaker to perform a correct speech act of asserting. These "normative" statuses correspond to the traditional primitives of permission and obligation. In this distinction Brandom places a central tenet of his theory: the notion of material negation or incompatibility: "two notions are incompatible with each other if commitments to one precludesentitlement to the other" (MIE 160). Apparently the significance of making a claim - whose content is expressed by the use of a particular sentence - depends on other collateral commitments other people may have. Therefore there may be different consequences derived by different sets of beliefs that are held by different persons. This makes a systematic theory of meaning almost impossible: how can we define the meaning of a sentence in terms of its possible consequences when they depend on collateral assumptions and commitments? How communication become possible? This question is a traditional one against holism - made by Dummett 1973: if meaning is defined holistically, if it depends on the different perspectives of different speakers, what you mean with an expression will be different by what I mean with the same expression; therefore agreement or disagreement will become impossible and communication will become a mistery nobody can really explain. Here the move made by Brandom as we shall wee now - is another pragmatic move. Normative attitudes and the answer to the problem of holism We are not only driven by linguistic exchange to have entitlements and commitments to what we claim; we also report what other people say. Reported speech is a long debated topic since Frege, and its main problem is the substitution salva veritate of coreferring expressions. Brandom realizes that we have different kinds of reported speechs, which depend on the attitudes we have towards what other people say. We may simply report what another person has said, without being committed to the content of what is said, but attributing commitments the the speaker. On the other hand we may acknowledge what a person claims and undertake what she claims. Attributing and Undertaking are two different (normative) attitudes towards what other people claim. When we make an assertion we undertake a certain kind of commitment, and we make it manifest in the way we accept or reject substitutions, for instance, in reported speech. If I say that Mary does not believe of Benjamin Frankling that is the inventor of the lightning rod I do not undertake what she says, but I attribute her that belief; on the other hand, if I say that John believes that Benjamin Franklin is the inventor of the lightning rod, I undertake John's assertion, and in so doing i accept to substitute "BF" with "the inventor of the lightning rod".

We have so far distinguished two levels of norms: (i) commitments and entitlements, which are the basic status of our treating the sentences we assert; (ii) attributing and undertaking, which are the basic attitudes we have towards the contents of other people assertions. This should be enough 1 to face the above mentione problem of defining communication in a holistic vision: communication does not require the previous sharing of common contents, but it is a process in which speakaers converge towards the same concepts in the activity of attributing and undertaking commitments to certain inferences and substitutions. Asserting and infererring are threfore internally related practices. Assertion becomes the basic tool in inferential semantics and pragmatics; in fact verbal practices like orders acquire their inferential meaning only in a language where we already have assertions. A case it made by Brandom also relatively to promises, which become understandable only on the background of assertions, and the entitlements and commitments which are defining the act of asserting (MIE 163-165). In the new terminology of Between Saying and Doing assertion becomes "the minimal kind of doing which counts as saying" (BSD 42). Put in semantic terms we may say that only what can stand in inferential relations can count as the content of an assertion (BSD 43). References Brandom R. B. 2008 Between Saying and Doing, Towards and Analytic Pragmatism, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Brandom, R. B. 1994. Making It Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press Chastain, C. 1975. Reference and context. In K. Gunderson (ed), Language, Mind and Knowledge. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 194 269. Dummett, M. 1973. Frege: Philosophy of Language. London: Duckworth. McDowell J. 1984 "Wittgensten on following a rule", Synthese 58 (325-363) Lewis D., 1974 "Scorekeeping in a Language Game", in Journal of Philosophical Logic (reprint in D. Lewis, Philosophical Papers, ch. 13) Sellars W. 1997 Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, Introd R. Rorty, comment by R. Brandom, Harvard U.P., Cambridge (Mass.) [first. edition 1956] 1 Actually Brandom suggest that we need a third step, which permits us to do for deontic attitudes what those attitudes do for deontic statuses (MIE 637); but some simplification is needed is such a short introduction.