Utilitarianism pp

Similar documents
Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

What is the nature of God? Does God make arbitrary rules just to see if we will obey? Does God make rules that He knows will lead to our happiness?

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

AS UTILITARIANISM EXAMPLE EXAM ANSWERS

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Utilitarianism JS Mill: Greatest Happiness Principle

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

Situation Ethics. Key Features. Strengths & Weaknesses

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Consequentialism. Mill s Theory of Utility

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Deontology. Immanuel Kant ( ) Founder of Deontology

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

Foundations of Bioethics

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

The Aristotelian Principle in Mill and Kant

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

Kant's Moral Philosophy

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

A primer of major ethical theories

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Lecture #3: Utilitarianism

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Challenges to Traditional Morality

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Strengths & Weaknesses of Utilitarianism

INSTITUTIONAL ISSUES INVOLVING ETHICS AND JUSTICE - Ethics Fundamentals and Approaches to Ethics - Chen Te

Phil 108, August 10, 2010 Punishment

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

LYING TEACHER S NOTES

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics Ethical Theories. Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

Normative Ethical Theories

Introduction to Ethics

Plato s Republic Book 3&4. Instructor: Jason Sheley

FINAL EXAM SHORT-ANSWER QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004

Chapter 12: Areas of knowledge Ethics (p. 363)

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

16RC1 Cahana. Medical professionalism: Where does it come from? A review of different moral theories. Alex Cahana. Introduction

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: WINTER 2009

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

Creative Genius and the Rights of the Individual: From Romanticism to Utilitarianism

In the Fall PEs many people who wrote about ethics as an Area of Knowledge indicated that ethical perspectives were always a matter of personal

A Categorical Imperative. An Introduction to Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

RS1/2 ETH: Introduction to Religion and Ethics (AS) by Gordon Reid

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

Ethical non-naturalism

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

CJR: Volume 1, Issue Book Reviews. Sam Harris, Lying. Edited by Annaka Harris Kindle Edition. 26 pages. $1.99.

Introduction to Philosophy

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

ADVANCED SUBSIDIARY (AS) General Certificate of Education Religious Studies Assessment Unit AS 6. assessing

Many Faces of Virtue. University of Toronto. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

MARCH 18, 2018 EXCLUSION-FREE LIFE

Born Free and Equal? On the ethical consistency of animal equality summary Stijn Bruers

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Desiring God in Your Life

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

A NOTE ON UTILITARIANISM & CONSEQUENTIALISM FOR PHILOSOPHY 13 Richard Arneson Fall, 2004

Transcription:

Utilitarianism pp. 430-445. Assuming that moral realism is true and that there are objectively true moral principles, what are they? What, for example, is the correct principle concerning lying? Three possibilities: i) Lying is impermissible in all circumstances. (To believe this is to be an absolutist about the wrongness of lying). ii) Lying is impermissible except when it s necessary to prevent a great evil on the order of a murder, in which case it s obligatory. iii) Lying is impermissible only when it produces worse consequences than being honest would (as it usually does). When lying would produce better consequences than honesty, it s obligatory. Consider two cases: a) The Nazis come knocking on my door asking if I know where any Jews are hiding. I do, but the only way to save my own life and that of the Jews is to lie to the Nazis and say that I don t. b) Joe is on his deathbed, but he is lucid during the last few moments of his life. He asks me how his adult daughter whom he loves dearly is doing. Instead of telling him the truth that she and her children were killed by a drunk driver last night I lie to him, telling him that she just won the lottery. I do this so that he can die happy. Principle i) forbids both lies; principle ii) requires the lie in a) but forbids the lie in b); principle iii) requires both lies. Another sort of case: telling a little, white lie to avoid hurting someone s feelings. Mary shows you her newborn baby and says Isn t he beautiful? and you answer, yes even though you think that he s one of the uglier babies you ve ever seen. (Of course in this case, unlike the Nazi case, you may be able to get away with artful evasion). Different moral theories take different views about what the correct moral principles are. The moral theory defended by Immanuel Kant holds that i) is the correct principle, while act utilitarianism ( AU ) says that iii) is. AU defined Out of all the acts that one could perform in a given situation, the morally right one is the one that would result in or produce the largest total amount of utility in the world. The morally right act is the one that will maximize utility. Utility means happiness, well-being, or welfare. Whose utility should I am at maximizing? Just my own, my family s, my nation s, or that of everyone in the whole world? AU says, everyone s.

AU is not the same as EE (Ethical Egoism, or the view that one ought to aim at maximizing one s own happiness, not the happiness of everyone). Suppose you could do A or B, and only three people would be affected, you, Jim, and Jane, in the following way (the numbers here indicate whether the act increases or decreases that person s happiness, and by how much): A B you +50 +20 Jim +1 +20 Jane -20 +20 total +31 +60 EE says that you ought to do A, whereas AU says that you have a duty to do B. What is happiness? What determines how well-off someone is, how a good a life they have? Here are 3 different answers (AU is compatible with all of them): i) Hedonism the only thing that has intrinsic value is pleasure, or what you re experiencing when you like or enjoy what you re doing. The activity that s giving you the pleasure is not valuable for its own sake, but only as a means to that pleasure. The only things that are intrinsically bad are unpleasant mental states (e.g. pain, fear, anxiety, boredom, feeling bothered or irritated, nausea, depression, etc.). -- Quantitative vs. qualitative hedonism. Bentham vs. Mill. (pp. 434-35). Quantitative hedonism (defended by Jeremy Bentham) says that how well off you are depends entirely on how much pleasure you have in your life (not just at present, but over the course of your entire life). Quantity of pleasure is a function of two variables: intensity and duration. J.S. Mill argues that this view is wrong, because quality of pleasure should matter too. Mill holds that if experts (i.e. people familiar with and capable of fully appreciating both) prefer one type of pleasure over another, even though the second type is quantitatively bigger, then the first type is of higher quality. In fact, quality is more important than quantity, for Mill. He thinks that you re better off with smaller, high quality pleasures than bigger, low quality ones. ( Better to be a Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied ). Mill claims that intellectual pleasures (e.g. the enjoyment people experience solving crossword puzzles, reading good books, etc.) are of higher quality than animal or carnal pleasures (food, drink, sex, back rubs, jucuzzis, etc.), because most people acquainted with both prefer them to the carnal ones. Some people have doubted that Mill s empirical generalization here is true. -- The experience machine (EM) objection to hedonism. (pp. 433-34) 1. If hedonism were true, then I m better off plugging into the EM for the rest of my life than living my life in the real world. (This is so because I would experience more pleasure in the EM than I could possibly get from living in the real world).

2. I m not better off plugging into the EM for the rest of my life. Doing that would be a kind of spiritual death. I d think I m doing wonderful things, but in reality I d be an indeterminate blob in a flotation tank. I don t want that. I want to really accomplish some fine things in my life, and I want to have beliefs about my situation that are true. 3. Therefore, hedonism is not true. ii) Preference or desire satisfaction. According to this view, how well-off you are depends on how well your strongest preferences about your life are satisfied. -- The deceived wife example to illustrate the difference between this view and the previous one. The key here is this: it s possible to feel great because you falsely believe that one of your preferences is satisfied, and it s possible to feel lousy because you falsely believe that one of your preferences has been thwarted. According to the preference satisfaction view, it s bad for you to have your preferences frustrated even if you never learn that they ve been frustrated. -- Question: How does an AU that tells us that right acts maximize society s total amount of preference satisfaction differ from majoritarianism, or the view that the right act is the one that the majority favors? Answer: AU takes strength of preference into account, while majoritarianism doesn t. Hence, suppose that 49% of all people strongly prefer policy A to policy B, while 51% of all people are almost indifferent but just barely prefer B to A. Then according to majority rule we should enact policy B, while according to utilitarianism we should enact policy A. This brings us to what Sober calls the apples and oranges problem (p. 436): how do you determine that one person has a stronger desire for something than another person does? iii) Perfectionist views, e.g. Aristotle. (Not mentioned by Sober in this chapter). Happiness consists in leading an objectively good life, one that realizes or perfects human nature and what it is capable of. The good life is one that develops and uses capacities that normal humans have but animals lack, such as our capacities for rational thought, moral deliberation and choice, artistic creativity, etc. -- The example of the blades of grass counter as support for this sort of view. Imagine someone who is blissfully happy spending all of his free time counting the blades of grass in his back yard. Suppose that if he were to spend that time socializing with other people, going on nature hikes, reading good books, solving crossword puzzles, doing woodworking, etc. he would derive just a tiny bit less pleasure and preference satisfaction than from counting blades of grass. According to i) and ii) he is better off spending his time counting blades of grass. According to iii) he is better off doing the finer, more worthwhile things. Three objections to AU. No matter which of the 3 accounts of happiness distinguished above AU uses, it seems vulnerable to the following objections: 1) It doesn t take rights of individuals seriously, because it tells us to violate rights whenever doing so would produce more total happiness than respecting them would.

Violating peoples rights is unjust, so AU (sometimes) supports unjust acts. This objection is illustrated by the following examples. Example of surgeon, 1 healthy, and 5 dying patients (not in the textbook) Example of lonesome stranger (pp. 437-38). Note the difference between AU and retributivism here. ( Retributivism is the view that in order for punishment to be just, it must be deserved, and only the guilty can deserve punishment. It also holds that the severity of punishment should be proportionate to the seriousness of the crime). Example of fanatical majorities (pp. 440-442). The utilitarian reply to the justice objection: replace AU with RU. RU is Rule Utilitarianism. It says that instead of performing whatever act will produce the most happiness, we should obey whatever moral rule will produce the most happiness. People who follow the rule always respect other people s rights produce more total happiness for society than people who go around violating rights, such as murderers, rapists, and robbers. So RU says that we should always respect others rights. But Sober points out that RU probably collapses into AU. After all, won t the people who follow the rule respect others rights, except when violating them will produce more total happiness for society produce even more happiness than people who follow the rule always respect others rights? So it looks like RU will tell us to violate rights in exactly the same cases as AU does. 2) Personal integrity/dirty hands (pp. 442-43). AU makes it impossible for people to retain their integrity, because it demands that they do evil, if that s the way to maximize utility in the long run. Example of person who must decide whether to work for the Nazis; if he doesn t, then someone else will, and that person will work more diligently for them, and thus, end up doing more evil. Most of us think that the right thing to do, in a case like this, is to maintain one s personal integrity, not get one s hands dirty, even if that means that there will be more evil in the world. But there are some examples that suggest that a preoccupation with one s own integrity, or not getting one s hands dirty is not so admirable. Example of soldier in a tyrannical country who is about to execute 20 citizens for publicly criticizing the tyrant and his policies. Joe, a tourist who happens to be visiting the country, arrives on the scene. The soldier says to Joe: we don t get many tourists around here. We re honored by your visit. To mark the occasion, I ll spare the 20 whom I was going to execute, but only if you punch one of them on the nose hard enough to cause a nosebleed. Joe happens to be an extreme pacifist, someone who believes that the use of violence against others is never justified. To remain true to his pacifist principles/faithful to his own conscience, Joe declines the soldier s offer. If Joe were to accept the offer, he would have dirty hands /compromise his integrity. We don t admire Joe. This second example shows that while there might well be a good objection to AU that appeals to the value of personal integrity, the objection is probably more complex than Sober suggests.

3) AU is incompatible with the value of loyalty to friends and close relatives, because it demands an extreme form of impartiality in one s dealings with all other people. (pp. 443-44) Example of passengers abandoning a sinking ship, I have a life vest, and I have to decide whom I should give it to my 18 year old son (who dropped out of high school, prefers stealing to work, abuses drugs and alcohol, is cruel to animals and children, etc.) or a 25 yr. old man who is not related to me, but whom I know is extremely talented, intelligent, and public spirited (i.e. devoted to helping his community). AU says I should give the life vest to the stranger. But don t I have a special responsibility to my children? A related objection to AU is that it is wrong because demands too much self-sacrifice. Go back to the example of the surgeon, the one healthy patient, and the five dying ones. Suppose that I am the healthy patient and the doctor asks me to sacrifice my life to save the five. If I say yes, others might well praise me for being heroic, saintly, etc. But isn t such a sacrifice above and beyond the call of moral duty? We don t think that I m doing anything wrong if I say no. And yet AU implies that I have a moral duty to say yes.