= (value of LEAVE if rain x chance of rain) + (value of LEAVE if dry x chance of dry) = -20 x x.5 = -9

Similar documents
Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Decision Making: expected utility decisions. possible conditions. it rains 8. it doesn t rain -5. it rains -12. it doesn t rain 7

Blaise Pascal

175 Chapter CHAPTER 23: Probability

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

Introductory Matters

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 5d God

The St. Petersburg paradox & the two envelope paradox

232 Infinite movement, the point which fills everything, the moment of rest; infinite without quantity, indivisible and infinite.

MITOCW Lec 2 MIT 6.042J Mathematics for Computer Science, Fall 2010

The significance of faith proven by decision theory Pascal s wager game is correct and refutes atheism completely

Part 9: Pascal s Wager

A Reply to New Zeno. appeared in Analysis v.60, #2 (April 2000) S. Yablo

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

The following content is provided under a Creative Commons license. Your support

What is Atheism? How is Atheism Defined?: Who Are Atheists? What Do Atheists Believe?:

On Breaking the Spell of Irrationality (with treatment of Pascal s Wager) Selmer Bringsjord Are Humans Rational? 11/27/17 version 2 RPI

MITOCW watch?v=ogo1gpxsuzu

MITOCW MITRES18_006F10_26_0703_300k-mp4

Consider... Ethical Egoism. Rachels. Consider... Theories about Human Motivations

Video 1: Worldviews: Introduction. [Keith]

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

Bayesian Probability

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Cosmological Arguments

Bradley on Chance, Admissibility & the Mind of God

OCR YEAR 11 MOCK EXAMS REVISION BOOKLET

The following content is provided under a Creative Commons license. Your support

6.080 / Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring 2008

Following Jesus. Peter, Andrew, James, and John had to choose between being fishermen or fishers of men (Matthew 4:19).

The following content is provided under a Creative Commons license. Your support

MITOCW ocw f99-lec18_300k

The free will defense

REPUGNANT ACCURACY. Brian Talbot. Accuracy-first epistemology is an approach to formal epistemology which takes

MATH 1000 PROJECT IDEAS

MITOCW watch?v=6pxncdxixne

Step 1 Pick an unwanted emotion. Step 2 Identify the thoughts behind your unwanted emotion

some of the questions that Blaise Pascal and John Locke seek to address. The two great

Chapter 20 Testing Hypotheses for Proportions

THE FOUR CALLS MIKE MAZZALONGO

Swinburne. General Problem

PROBLEM PASSAGES FOR SECURITY

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

>> Marian Small: I was talking to a grade one teacher yesterday, and she was telling me

Trade Defence and China: Taking a Careful Decision

When is Faith Rational? 1. What is Faith?

William Clifford and William James on sufficient evidence for belief

24.09 Minds and Machines Fall 11 HASS-D CI

Boxes and envelopes. 1. If the older child is a girl. What is the probability that both children are girls?

Construing faith as action won t save Pascal s wager

(Run through table of possibilities, and since the other three are pretty bad, you might as well be Christian)

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

The Cosmological Argument

Betting on God: Pascal, Probability Theory and Theology. nevertheless made surprising contributions to the field of religious philosophy.

A Better Version of Pascal s Wager. Forthcoming in American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. Michael Rota

CAN TWO ENVELOPES SHAKE THE FOUNDATIONS OF DECISION- THEORY?

HOMILY Questions on the Final Exam

The Hard Work of Life Together September 13, Oxford Christian Church James 3:17-18; 1 Corinthians 13:1-7

Fan or Follower. Peter, Andrew, James, and John had to choose between being fishermen or fishers of men (Matthew 4:19).

Is it rational to have faith? Looking for new evidence, Good s Theorem, and Risk Aversion. Lara Buchak UC Berkeley

FAITH. And HEARING JESUS. Robert Lyte Holy Spirit Teachings

HELL YES OR HELL NO WEEK 2. Jeff Toner & Scott Blore

Wholehearted Coaching: Week Three Self-Love & Worthiness

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

think that people are generally moral relativists. I will argue that people really do believe in moral

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction

A DEFINITION OF BELIEVING. R. G. Cronin

MITOCW ocw f99-lec19_300k

100 SATANIC QUESTIONS

Today we begin our discussion of the existence of God.

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Abstract. Coping with Difficult, Unanswered, and Unanswerable Questions

Birthday Puja CONTENTS. Date : 21st March 2000 Place : Delhi Type : Puja Speech : English & Hindi Language. Transcript.

Predestination: Fated By Our Genes?

Hypocrisy. Introduction: Titus 1:16 NEW SERIES

Owning Your Worldview Considers. The Case for Faith. A Journalist Investigates the Toughest Objections to Christianity.

Descartes Meditations

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

En Pos de la Verdad 1 Eight Bible Studies for understanding God s redemptive plan

COPLESTON: Quite so, but I regard the metaphysical argument as probative, but there we differ.

Engaging Moderns & Postmoderns. Engaging Moderns. The Fine-Tuning Argument. The Fine-Tuning Argument. The Fine-Tuning Argument

First Christian Church The Way of Kings 2 Samuel 11:1-15

Fear and Trembling: The knight of faith and movement. (Lecture 3 accompanying notes for reading of the Preamble from the heart )

THE IMMUTABILITY OF GOD

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

2017 Parochial Report. Workbook. Page 2. Membership, Attendance and Services. File online at: With. Line-by-Line Instructions

Car Goat Goat. And no doubt there are other arguments as well. car goat goat 1

Many Minds are No Worse than One

Safety Psalm 139 Sermon by Associate Pastor Joe Davis Union Baptist Church November 8 th, 2015

UNITY IN BIBLICAL UNDERSTANDING

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Not The Same God: Is The Qur'anic Allah The Lord God Of The Bible? By Atif Debs, Sam Solomon READ ONLINE

Materialism Pascal s Wager exposes unbelief as illogical

Reading the Rainbow. Genesis 9:13. Rely on God, He doesn t lie. KEY VERSE STICKY STATEMENT

know needs a u-turn in some aspect of life, or even if you just need a sign more like one of these, then you're in the right place.

PHIL Philosophy of Religion

Theology Notes Class One Student Notes Why Studying Theology is so important

Transcription:

3. PASCAL S WAGER Suppose you are facing a decision under conditions of uncertainty : say, whether to take an umbrella or not, on a day when the chance of rain is one half. e value of taking as opposed to leaving the umbrella depends on whether it rains, so we should list all the possible scenarios taking and rain, taking and dry, leaving and rain, and leaving and dry and note how well things work out in each of them. e rational choice is the one likely to produce the best outcome. Practical Rationality Principle One should choose the action A with the highest expected value = Df the sum of the values of A's possible outcomes, weighted according to their probabilities. RAIN (.5) DRY (.5) EV TAKE 10-4 3 LEAVE -20 2-9 EV(TAKE) = (value of TAKE if rain x chance of rain) + (value of TAKE if dry x chance of dry) = 10 x.5 + -4 x.5 = 3 EV(LEAVE) = (value of LEAVE if rain x chance of rain) + (value of LEAVE if dry x chance of dry) = -20 x.5 + 2 x.5 = -9 So you should take the umbrella. If the probabilities change, or the values you assign to the possible outcomes change, you may reach a different result. Say the probability of rain is 10%: EV(TAKE) = 1 + -3.6 = -2.6 EV(LEAVE) = -2 + 1.8 = -.2 Now apply this reasoning to the issue of whether to "take" God or leave him. Say the probability of God's existence is 50%. If God exists, believers are rewarded with eternal bliss; that's infinitely valuable (it literally couldn t be better: unity joined to infinity adds nothing to it ) so the first box gets filled like this:. Disbelievers, let s say, are rewarded with eternal damnation so the second box gets filled like this: -1,000,000 (Note: Pascal doesn t seem to think that it is infinitely bad: Justice to the outcast is less

bad vast than mercy to the elect. But you can make the disutility of hell as large as you like, so long as it is finite.) Now what if God does not exist? en the believer suffers some inconvenience on account of his/her observant lifestyle; and the nonbeliever, let s say, enjoys an equal amount of pleasure. is gives GOD (.5) NO GOD (.5) EV BELIEVE -20 REJECT -1,000,000 20-499,990 EV (BELIEVE) = (value of BELIEVE if God x prob. God) + (value of BELIEVE if no God x prob. no God) = x.5 + -20 x.5 = EV(REJECT) = (value of REJECT if God x prob. God) + (value of REJECT if no God x prob. no God) = -1,000,000 x.5 + 20 x.5 = -499,990 More generally, so long as the probability of God existing is finite (however small), the reward of heaven is infinite, and the rewards from other options are finite, we get: GOD (f n ) NO GOD (1- f n ) EV BELIEVE f 1 REJECT f 2 f 3 f 4 So EV(BELIEVE) > EV(REJECT) 1. e practically rational thing to do is the thing with the highest expected value. [A] 2. e expected value of believing in God is higher than that of not accepting God. [A] 3. Believing in God and rejecting God are the only options. [A] 4. erefore, I should believe in God. [1,2,3]

IS BELIEF UNDER OUR CONTROL? ere s a worry though: belief isn t under our direct control. ( I ll give you $10 if you can believe that Elvis is still alive ) It is only practically rational to do a thing if we can do that thing. Pascal s response: we can make it much more likely that we come to believe in God by behaving like a believer. So we get a new argument: 1. e practically rational thing to do is the thing with the highest expected value. [A] 2. Behaving like a believer makes one more likely to believe in God. [A] 3. e expected value of believing in God is higher than that of not. [A] 4. erefore, the expected value of of behaving like a believer is higher than that of not [2,3] 5. Behaving like a believer and not behaving like a believer are the only options [A] 6. erefore, I should behave like a believer. [1,4,5] FIRST OBJECTIONS i. e Wager is cynical and God would not reward a theist whose belief is based on it. (Deny 3) ii. e probability of God is 0. (Deny 3) iii. One s life will be based on a lie if one behaves like a believer and God doesn't exist. (Deny 1) MANY GODS So far we have assumed a very specific sort of God, call him or her the God of Abraham. What about the gods of Hinduism or the Shinto faith or etc? What about possible gods not worshipped by any religion? e trouble is that as far as Pascal s actual reasoning goes, it would seem that we have just as good an argument for believing in some of these other gods as we do for believing in the God of Abraham. Yet to believe in all of them at once makes no sense. Some of these gods contradict each other; you can't have more than one all-powerful god for what if they disagree? Even consistent gods may require inconsistent behavior. How is one to choose which god to believe in? WEIRD GODS Why not an AntiGod who is just like the God of Abraham except in being absolutely evil? Or a Jealous God who will reward you for believing in him but has a horrible fate in store for you if you even think of believing in the God of Abraham? Or a Shy God who gives you everlasting life provided you don t believe in him, etc. Once these are thrown into the hopper, the earlier calculation needs to be revised. Is it clear that if you believe, and God doesn't exist, then you lose only a finite reward? Not if an Anti- Abrahamic Jealous God exists, and puts you through infinite hell if you believe in the God of Abraham.

GOD (.5) JEALOUS-GOD (.1) NO GOD (.4) EV ACCEPT - f 1? f 5 REJECT f 2 f 3 f 4 f 6 e immediate problem is that mathematically there is no well-defined way to calculate the result; infinite numbers can be added but there's no well-defined way to subtract them. But suppose we bracket that concern, and assume that the two infinities cancel out. e calculation favors, if anything, rejecting God, since you don t have to pay the cost of (say) abstinence. e advantage of accepting God over rejecting God has disappeared. IS THE EXPECTED VALUE OF ACTING LIKE A BELIEVER HIGHER? (I.E. DOES 4 FOLLOW FROM 2 & 3?) First: imagine that instead of behaving like a believer, one decided to flip a coin: if it comes up head, you do, if tails, you don t. e expected utility is still infinite. Or suppose you roll a die, with the plan to act like a believer if and only if it comes up 6. Expected utility is still infinity. And so on for any chance you take for acting like a believer, however small, so long as it is finite. is involves rejecting premise 5. But even if we accept premise 5 (make any outcome that has a finite probability of behaving like a believer count as behaving like a believer), 4 doesn t follow from 2, 3 & 5. Don t we accord a finite probability to the possibility that, having decided not to behave like a believer, you will still end up believing in God? (Perhaps your action will backfire.) In which case, the expected utility of not behaving like a believer is still infinite. So there is no advantage in behaving like a believer.

MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.00 Problems in Philosophy Fall 2010 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms.