POLEMICS & DEBATES / POLEMIKI I DYSKUSJE

Similar documents
Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Augustine s famous story about his own theft of pears is perplexing to him at

Natural Rights, Morality, and the Law

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Aristotle s Virtue Ethics

THEORY AND ANTI-THEORY IN ETHICS. A Two-Day Workshop on Philosophy and the Nature of Morality

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

What Part of the Soul Does Justice Perfect? Shane Drefcinski Department of Humanities/Philosophy University of Wisconsin Platteville

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Nicomachean Ethics, Book II

TOPIC 27: MORALITY OF HUMAN ACTS

Nichomachean Ethics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Happiness and Moral Virtue Aristotle

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Out of tragedy comes self knowledge. Do you find this to be true in King Lear and Oedipus the King?

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Nicomachean Ethics, Book II By Aristotle Written 350 B.C.E Translated by W. D. Ross

For a brilliant introductory lecture on the meaning of practical wisdom in virtue ethics by Professor Schwartz of the University of Colorado go to:

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

Nicomachean Ethics. Aristotle ( BCE) Reading 8.3 BOOK ONE. 1. The Good as the End of All Action. 2. The Search for a Supreme Good

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Zdenko Kodelja HOW TO UNDERSTAND EQUITY IN HIGHER EDUCATION? (Draft)

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

Misfortune: Creating Opportunity, or Impeding Happiness? in accordance with some virtue, good fortune dictates whether we will experience

Reading the Nichomachean Ethics

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

A Very Short Primer on St. Thomas Aquinas Account of the Various Virtues

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

Letter Figures Words PHILOSOPHY. Written examination. Friday 15 November 2013

Immortality Cynicism

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

Sophists vs. Aristotle in Sophocles's Antigone

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

THE EMOTIONAL AND INTELLECTUAL VIRTUE OF FAITH

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

Urging Righteousness and Virtue: Socrates, Gorgias and the Nature of Moral Argument

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

F. Rachel Magdalene Universität Leipzig Leipzig, Germany

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Many Faces of Virtue. University of Toronto. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Virtue Ethics. I.Virtue Ethics was first developed by Aristotle in his work Nichomachean Ethics

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Nietzsche and Aristotle in contemporary virtue ethics

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Does God exist? The argument from evil

Saint Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae Selections III Good and Evil Actions. ST I-II, Question 18, Article 1

This is a repository copy of The Expressive Function of Blame. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper:

VIRTUE RULES AND UNIVERSALIZABLE RULES. Lee Vincent, The Evergreen State College

Dirty Hands or Political Virtue?

Nicomachean Ethics by Aristotle (ca 330 BC) (Selections from Books I, II & X)

Antigone. Teaching Unit. Advanced Placement in English Literature and Composition. Individual Learning Packet. by Sophocles

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

On Courage [Laches] Plato

Action in Special Contexts

Ancient & Medieval Virtue Ethics

Nicomachean Ethics. by Aristotle ( B.C.)

A primer of major ethical theories

Agency Implies Weakness of Will

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Augustine, On Free Choice of the Will,

Meanings from the Oxford English Dictionary

LODGE VEGAS # 32 ON EDUCATION

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Utilitarianism pp

4. Faces a horrible truth (catastrophe) 5. Reversal of fortune (paripateia) 6. The fall and the revelation. 3 rd Period

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder.

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

SCIENCE AND THEOLOGY: BATTLE BY PROXY. John Alexander. Introduction. The World Book Dictionary defines proxy as an agent; deputy; substitute.

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

THE CAMBRIDGE SOLUTION TO THE TIME OF A KILLING LAWRENCE B. LOMBARD

Excerpts from Aristotle

Going beyond good and evil

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Does Theism Imply Determinism? Questions about Hard Determinism. Objections to Hard Determinism, I. Objections to Hard Determinism, II

Hence, you and your choices are a product of God's creation Psychological State. Stephen E. Schmid

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Transcription:

ARGUMENT Vol. 4 (1/2014) pp. 155 160 POLEMICS & DEBATES / POLEMIKI I DYSKUSJE Moral tragedy Peter DRUM ABSTRACT In this paper it is argued, contrary to certain moralists, that resolutely good people can be assured of a contentment of the soul. KEYWORDS Aristotle; Raimond Gaita; Alasdair MacIntyre; moral conflict Lecturer in philosophy at School of Philosophy, Australian Catholic University, Melbourne, Australia. E-mail: peter.drum@acu.edu.au. www.argument-journal.eu Published online: 27.10.2014

156 Peter DRUM INTRODUCTION In Nichomachean Ethics Aristotle maintains that: to fear some things is right and noble, and it is base not to fear them e.g., disgrace; he who fears this is good and modest, and he who does not is shameless ; and that poverty and disease we p e r h a p s ought not to fear, nor in general the things that do not proceed from vice and are not due to a man himself (Aristotle, 1952a: I, 6; emphasis added). His point is that what is fearful or, at least, what we should be m o s t a f r a i d o f is wickedness. Yet, this is avoidable. So, if we are resolved to be good, we do not have to live in fear of t h i s. Hence, although the happiness and well-being which all men manifestly desire, some have the power of attaining, but to others, from some accident or defect of nature, the attainment of them is not granted, he claims in Politics (Aristotle, 1952b: VII, 13); even then nobility shines through, when a man bears with resignation many great misfortunes, not through insensibility to pain but through nobility and greatness of soul (Aristotle, 1952a: I, 10). Therefore, despite the fact that those who say that the victim on the rack or the man who falls into great misfortunes is happy if he is good are, whether they mean it or not, talking nonsense (Aristotle, 1952a: VII, 13) for Aristotle such a person is not unhappy either, u n l e s s their soul is rent by faction (Aristotle, 1952a: IX, 4). Yet, it is sometimes argued that there are tragic situations where even good people cannot but suffer morally. They are, then, d o o m e d to be morally fearful, and can only hope to be morally l u c k y enough not to become involved in such events. The aim of this paper is show that this depressing thesis is unwarranted. CONFLICTS OF DUTY? In reference to the hanging of Billy Budd, Peter Winch says that although Captain Vere considered it right for him to do so, he considers it to be wrong; and they both could be right: I am holding that if A says «X is the right thing for me to do» and if B, in a situation not relevantly different, says «X is the wrong thing for me to do», it can be that both are correct (Winch, 1972: 164 165). Raimond Gaita agrees: there is no difference in their descriptions of the character of that innocence and of its importance to their judgements, no difference, that is, which explains why Vere acted one way and Winch thought it impossible for him to act that way (Gaita, 1991: 110). He contends that moral deliberation is irreducibly personal [ ] [so] this should no longer be surprising or puzzling, or a sign of irrationalism (Gaita, 1991: 110). Yet, reasonable agent A who cannot agree with reasonable agent B, will n e c e s s a r i l y be morally fraught if he must actively o p p o s e him; as he knows that he is in conflict with somebody whose cause is for his adversary a c t u a l l y right. But, this is absurd. Moral

Moral tragedy 157 deliberation involves the weighing up harms and benefits attached to cases, and these are publically accessible. What needs to be decided, then, is whether or not upholding the rules of the sea requires the hanging. Vere is quite convinced that they do; so, he can be consoled in the fact that Billy is in the wrong, despite his m o r a l innocence. If he is correct, Winch s finding it impossible for h i m to give the execution order, is simply a matter of weakness. CONFLICTS OF VALUE? Nevertheless, Alasdair MacIntyre maintains that there can be rival allegiances to incompatible goods [ ]. It seems that there can be rival conceptions of the virtues, rival accounts of what a virtue is [ ]. Could one virtue be temporarily at least at war with another? [ ]. Can the exercise of the virtue of doing what is required of a sister (Antigone) [ ] be at odds with [ ] justice (Creon)? [O]ur situation is tragic in that we have to recognize the authority of both claims (MacIntyre, 1990: 142 143). His contention is that it is wrong to think the tragic form of narrative is enacted when and only when we have a hero with a flaw, a flaw in practical intelligence which springs from inadequate possession or exercise of some virtue (MacIntyre, 1990: 163). This is because there is a multiplicity of human practices such as raising a family and forging a career which can create for us irresolvable moral conflicts. Hence, there may be tensions between the claims of family life and those of the arts the problem that Gauguin solved or failed to solve by fleeing to Polynesia (MacIntyre, 1990: 210). The point is that even if he is not a bad man, w h a t e v e r Gauguin does he is in a fix, because for the tragic protagonist, ought does not imply can (MacIntyre, 1990: 224). Yet, this does not make sense. That someone should do something can only mean that he should do it i f he can. But, as noted by Aquinas in his Summa Theologica, when discussing people wanting to enter the religious life, husbands c o u l d n o t desert their wives without i n j u s t i c e. Therefore when he [ Jesus] met Peter, who was married, he did not separate him from his wife, although he kept John from marriage when he wished to wed (Aquinas, 2006: 2a, 2ae., 186, 4; emphasis added). So, since doing injustice is the g r e a t e s t of evils, states the author of Gorgias (Plato, 1960, 469b; emphasis added), if Gauguin should go to Polynesia, this can o n l y be on the basis of f i r s t taking care of his family. Consequently, e i t h e r Polyneices body belongs to Antigone to bury; or it belongs to Creon to let rot; or it belongs equally to both of them, so either course of action is valid.

158 Peter DRUM BLAMELESS WRONGDOING? However, some moralists think that there can be acts of dirty hands acts that are justified, even obligatory, but none the less w r o n g a n d s h a m e f u l (Stocker, 1992: 9; emphasis added). Hence, Gaita: in what follows, one of the ten who might be saved by the shooting of an innocent person calls that shooting evil. I do not think it follows that he must say [ ] that therefore it must not or ought not be done. Do I intend his speech as an argument that the killing would be evil? Only in this manner and to this degree: it is meant to foreclose one way of talking about the killing and its relation to the ten, to the effect that though, of course, it is terrible it is the right thing to do, and so not evil. If he kills one to save ten, even because he believes that he must, that he must does not mean that he should not plead for the forgiveness, not only of the one he kills and those related to him, but of those he saves as well (Gaita, 1991: 69). Gaita believes that people can do evil yet not be blameable for it [ ]. [But:] It would be wrong to infer that they are not morally responsible for what they did, meaning, that they should not feel remorse for what they did (Gaita, 1991: 43 44). If this is correct, then of course the culpability factor is unnecessary for a moral tragedy; but is it? Remorse is defined as bitter repentance for [a] wrong committed (Fowler & Fowler, 1974: 1050), and people a r e blameable for committing wrongs. He says that: there are many who would say that if he [Oedipus] acted in non-culpable ignorance, then remorse is rationally inappropriate. But if we ask why that should be so, I know of no answer which does not, in the end, beg the question about the connection between responsibility and blame (Gaita, 1991: 345). Yet, there is no question-begging here: remorse comes from wrong-doing, and doing wrong accrues blame. Therefore wrong-doers are right to feel bad about the harm they have done, and they are right to apologise and ask for forgiveness, since what happened was their own fault. The point is that e i t h e r what is proposed i s evil and should not be done; o r circumstantially it i s not, and so it can be done. For, to think that there could be a d u t y to do the w r o n g thing is a contradiction in terms. Stocker makes the extraordinary claim that Aristotle h i m s e l f accepts the morality of dirty-hands ; because he says that if a tyrant were to order one to do something base, having one s parents and children in his power, and if one did the action they were to be saved, but otherwise would be put to death (Aristotle, 1952a: III, 1), a wrong can rightfully be committed. Yet, Aristotle repudiates baseness. Using matricide as an example, he says that there are some acts, perhaps, we cannot be forced to do, but ought rather to face death after

Moral tragedy 159 the most fearful sufferings [ ] for what we are forced to do is base (Aristotle, 1952a: III, 1). Moreover, he also says that not every action nor passion admits a mean; for some have names that already imply badness, e.g., spite, shamelessness, envy, and in the case of actions adultery, theft, murder [ ]. It is not possible, then, ever to be right with regard to them: one must always be wrong (Aristotle, 1952a: II, 6). The only time, then, that doing something a p p a r e n t l y wrong such as throwing goods overboard (Aristotle, 1952a: III, 1) is justified, is when t h e baseness of the action is annulled by the weight of the circumstances. For, on condition of securing the safety of himself and his crew any sensible man does so (Aristotle, 1952a: III, 1). CONCLUSION Aristotle maintains that despite the vicissitudes of life, resolutely good people can at least be assured of p e a c e o f s o u l, and to this extent they are not unhappy. Hence, in reference to some very brave men who opposed the Nazis, Philippa Foot remarks: one may think that there was a sense in which [ ] [they] did, but also a sense in which they did not, sacrifice their happiness in refusing to go along with the Nazis. In the abstract what they so longed for to get back to their families was of course wholly good. But as they were placed it was impossible to pursue this end by just and honourable means. And this, I suggest, explains the sense in which they did not see as their happiness what they could have got by giving in. Happiness in life, they might have said, was not something possible for them (Foot, 2001: 95). That this idea that in a v i t a l sense a good person cannot be harmed i s w r o n g would be tragic. This paper has sought to reassure us that it is not. BIBLIOGRAPHY Aquinas, St Thomas (2006). Summa Theologica (Ed. Th. Gilby). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Aristotle (1952a). Nicomachean ethics (Ed. R. M. Hutchins). Chicago: Great Books of the Western World, William Benton. Aristotle (1952b): Politics (Ed. R. M. Hutchins). Chicago: Great Books of the Western World, William Benton. Foot, Ph. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Fowler, H. W. & Fowler, F. G. (1974). The concise Oxford dictionary. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

160 Peter DRUM Gaita, R. (1991). Good and evil: an absolute conception. London: MacMillan. MacIntyre, A. (1990). After virtue. London: Duckworth. Plato (1960). Gorgias (Trans. W. Hamilton). Harmondsworth: Penguin. Stocker, M. (1992). Plural and conflicting values. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Winch, P. (1972). Ethics and action. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.