Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Similar documents
From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Animals in the Kingdom of Ends

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Kantian Ethics, Animals, and the Law

Skepticism and Internalism

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

Reason Papers Vol. 36, no. 1

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Kantian Constructivism, the Issue of Scope, and Perfectionism: O Neill on Ethical Standing

The Origin of the Good and Our Animal Nature. Christine M. Korsgaard. Harvard University

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Animal Rights. and. Animal Welfare

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Does Fish Welfare Matter? On the Moral Relevance of Agency

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

Finding Obligations Within Second-Personal Engagement: A Critique of Christine. Korsgaard's Normative Theory. A thesis presented to.

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

Teleology, Intentionality and Acting for Reasons In this paper I would like to contrast two radically different approaches to the evident linkage

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

Natural Goodness, Rightness, and the Intersubjectivity of Reason: A Reply to Arroyo, Cummisky, Molan, and Bird-Pollan

Unified Teleology: Paul Taylor s Biocentric Egalitarianism Through Aristotle

Edinburgh Research Explorer

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

The Challenge of God. Julia Grubich

The authority of reflection

Agency and Responsibility. According to Christine Korsgaard, Kantian hypothetical and categorical imperative

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism. Derek Parfit s two volume work On What Matters is, as many philosophers

Additive Theories of Rationality: A Critique

Curriculum Vitae Contact Harvard University Department of Philosophy 25 Quincy Street Cambridge, MA

The Philosophical Value of Reflective Endorsement

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

Action in Special Contexts

Topic III: Sexual Morality

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

CONTENT NORMATIVITY AND THE INTERDEPENDENCY OF BELIEF AND DESIRE. Seyed Ali Kalantari Lecturer of philosophy at the University of Isfahan, Iran

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

Desert-Adjusted Utilitarianism, People, and Animals Jean-Paul Vessel New Mexico State University Eastern APA 2017

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

It seems evident from experience that there are different cultures, different cultural moral codes,

Dignity, Contractualism and Consequentialism

My project in this paper is to reconsider the Kantian conception of practical reason. Some

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

ETHICS AND RELIGION. Prof. Dr. John Edmund Hare

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

acting on principle onora o neill has written extensively on ethics and political philosophy

Ethical non-naturalism

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Philosophical Review.

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

The Subjectivity of Values By J.L. Mackie (1977)

Responsibility and the Value of Choice

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

WhaT does it mean To Be an animal? about 600 million years ago, CerTain

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Animal Selves and the Good 1. Christine M. Korsgaard Harvard University

O Neill and Korsgaard on the Construction of Normativity

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Kant and his Successors

REASONS AND REFLECTIVE ENDORSMENT IN CHRISTINE KORSGAARD S THE SOURCES OF NORMATIVITY ERIC C. BROWN. (Under the direction of Melissa Seymour-Fahmy)

The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective. Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Transcription:

74 Between the Species Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT Christine Korsgaard argues for the moral status of animals and our obligations to them. She grounds this obligation on the notion that we share a common identity, our animal nature, with them and that animal pain represents a public reason that binds us; nevertheless, her distinctive attempt to enlist Kantian arguments to account for our obligations to animals has a startling implication that she fails to adequately consider: that we have direct duties to plants as well. Gregory L. Bock Walters State Community College greg.bock@ws.edu Volume 17, Issue 1 Jun 2014

75 In The Sources of Normativity, Christine Korsgaard argues for the moral status of animals and our obligations to them. She grounds this obligation on the notion that we share a common identity, our animal nature, with them and that animal pain represents a public reason that binds us; nevertheless, her distinctive attempt to enlist Kantian arguments to account for our obligations to animals has a startling implication that she fails to adequately consider: that we have direct duties to plants as well. In the first part of this paper, I will revisit Korsgaard s attempt to justify our obligations to animals; then in part two, I will examine her account of our indirect duties to plants. Next, I will show that her argument for our having direct duties to animals actually justifies similar obligations to plants as well, not just in regards to them, and finally I will consider and rebut her objection to my argument. Obligations to Animals According to Korsgaard, animals value themselves; this is just what it means to be a living thing. She says, A living thing is an entity whose nature it is to preserve and maintain its physical identity. It is a law to itself. When something it is doing is a threat to that identity and perception reveals that fact, the animal finds that it must reject what it is doing and do something else instead. In that case, it is in pain (1996, 150). She argues that pain is the unreflective rejection of a threat to your identity. So pain is the perception of a reason, and that is why it seems normative (1996, 150). When we see an animal in pain, we are also perceiving a reason that the animal has to change its condition, and this reason is public, something that has normative import for us as reflective rational beings. She argues that the animal s cry of pain obligates you just as someone calling out to you in your language can obligate you to listen: You can no more hear the cries of an animal as mere noise than you

76 can the words of a person (1996, 153). Pain, in this sense, is a public language that we share with animals, a sign that points to reasons that we both are able to perceive. Korsgaard argues that we must respond compassionately to the cries of an animal because we must act consistently (in a Kantian sense), valuing sentient nature wherever we find it. In The Sources of Normativity, she puts it this way: I first point out to you that your animal nature is a fundamental form of identity on which the normativity of your human identity, your moral identity, depends. It is not just as human but considered as sensible, considered as an animal, that you value yourself and are your own end. And this further stretch of reflection requires a further stretch of endorsement. If you don t value your animal nature, you can value nothing. So you must endorse its value. And the reasons and obligations to which your animal identity gives rise are not private reasons. However you bind yourself by those reasons, you can bind and be bound by others as well. So the reasons of other animals are also reasons for you (1996, 152-153). Thus the reasons we have to value our sentient identities are public in nature; that which is a reason for you is also a reason for me hence my obligation to you. Like Kant s Formula of Humanity, just as you can recognize your own humanity in other rational beings, wherever you also find animal nature, you will find a common identity, something someone shares with you and something that can obligate you.

77 In her article, Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and our Duties to Animals, she describes our common animal nature as an end in itself: In taking ourselves to be ends-in-ourselves we legislate that the natural good of a creature who matters to itself is the source of normative claims. Animal nature is an end-initself, because our own legislation makes it so. And this is why we have duties to the other animals (2004, 103). Indirect Duties to Plants On the face of it, Korsgaard s account of obligations to animals seems plausible, but what does she have to say about other forms of life, specifically plants? According to Korsgaard, plants do not share the same status as rational and nonrational animals: Since a plant is not conscious, being a plant is not a way of being someone, so it is not a way of being someone that we share with them (1996, 156). She thinks that a plant s lack of awareness, its lack of mattering to itself, disqualifies it from obligating us. On the other hand, Korgaard does recognize that we have duties in regards to plants; she asks, Is it crazy to say that there is something amiss with someone who destroys plant life wantonly, or who can see a plant drooping but still alive without wanting to give it a drink? Such a person shows a lack of reverence of life which is the basis of all value (1996, 156). However, she claims that this is not an obligation to plants directly. This is Kant s view, as Allen Wood describes it, of our duties to both animals and plants: Kant argues that our duty to cherish and promote what is beautiful in nonrational nature irrespective of its usefulness, and to behave with kindness and gratitude toward animals, are really duties to promote our own

78 moral perfection by behaving in ways that encourage a morally good disposition in ourselves. Kant claims that appreciation for the beauty of nature, by awakening in us the disposition to value something apart from its usefulness for our ends, prepares the way for a genuinely moral disposition in our behavior toward rational beings (1998, 194). This means, regarding plants, that Kant s duty not to harm plants is an indirect duty, not a direct duty to value plant life for its own sake, but to value it for our sake because it makes us better people. Kant s view does not permit unbridled exploitation of nonrational life for our own pleasures, but it also does not consider plant life as intrinsically valuable. Korsgaard agrees with Kant that our duties to plants are indirect, but she disagrees with him regarding our duties to animals. However, she may be overlooking an aspect of her argument that would support the view that our duties to plants and animals are the same, that we have direct duties to both. Direct Duties to Plants Korsgaard s argument for our direct duties to animals depends on two things: our shared identity and the reasons it gives rise to, but this justification would also work for plants as well. First, we share a common identity with plants our biological nature; second, our biological nature gives rise to reasons too. Regarding our common identity, we are not only a part of the animal kingdom, but we also share biological characteristics in common with plant life. This could be called (following Aquinas) a vegetative, (or following Aristotle) nutritive, or reproductive nature. Without this principle of life the aspect that is concerned with nutrition, growth, and reproduction

79 there would be no animals or rational human beings who could concern themselves with higher principles such as appetite, action, or reason. In fact, there would be no Kantian basis for duty at all since obligation is self-legislating through rational autonomy, and this is dependent (at least empirically) on there being human biological organisms. Therefore, if animal nature is necessary for rational human nature, then so is biological nature in general. A living thing, under Korsgaard s conception, is an entity whose nature it is to preserve and maintain its physical identity (1996, 150). While describing animals, she invokes Aristotle: Aristotle thought that a living thing is a thing with a special kind of form. A living thing is so designed as to maintain and reproduce itself. It has what we might call a self-maintaining form. So it is its own end; its job is just to keep on being what it is. Its business in life is to preserve its own identity. And its organs and activities are arranged to that end (1996, 149). When an animal experiences pain, it perceives a reason to act to preserve its identity. For example, when an animal feels hungry, it perceives a reason to eat, being that if it does not eat, it will die. The animal does not know this reason, but it does perceive it, nonetheless. Korsgaard applies a similar description to plant life: Plants, although not sensible, are in a way organized to be their own end. Like animals they have a self-maintaining form. And it is also true that we find it natural to use the language of reason and action about plants. We say that a plant needs water, that it turns towards the light, even that it is not happy in that window and must be moved to another (1996, 156). Here and elsewhere, Korsgaard describes living things in the language of final causes, as having ends. Although some of this language clearly crosses over into metaphor (plant emotions for example) Korsgaard evidently thinks that a common prin-

80 ciple of life can be ascribed to both animals and plants, since both are organized to their own ends and have natures that aim at preserving their own identity. Plants are not conscious, so any sense that can be made of the claim that plants have reasons must not include the notion of awareness. Nevertheless, it seems as though Korsgaard is consistently applying the Aristotelian conception of living things here. Although plants do not share perceptual capacities with animals, it is not inconceivable to think that they are organized on the basis of final causes; for example, Thomas Aquinas, commenting on Aristotle, agrees that a rational mind is not necessary to act for an end. Everything in nature, by its action or movement, tends to an end (Summa Theologica, I-II, 1,2). As Korsgaard writes, We do not think of plants as perceiving and pursuing their good, and yet like animals they are essentially self-maintaining beings and in that sense are oriented toward their own good. And they exhibit a certain responsiveness to the environment, to light and moisture (2004, 106). Plants spread their roots and photosynthesize on the basis of this end, and if they do not do this, they will die. Since the function of a plant is to maintain itself, it is the plant s own needs, not our needs, that are affected by things that enable or interfere with its functioning. A plant therefore has a good in a slightly deeper sense than a [human artifact] does, since what is good for it is more authentically good for itself (2004, 102). Thus, plants have identities, just not in a conscious sense, which does not seem to be a difficulty for Korsgaard s model. If conscious self-awareness were necessary for having an identity, then it is not clear that even animals would have the status that Korsgaard needs for her argument to go through. Granted animals are more conscious than plants, they are not self-aware in the same way as human beings are. Nevertheless, Korsgaard can

81 extend direct duties to animals because, I claim, it is not awareness that is fundamental to her model, it is having reasons based on a metaphysical identity, or the having of an esse. Attributing reasons to plants in this way depends on a strongly teleological conception of life. Nevertheless, this appears to be Korsgaard s actual view toward living things in general and why her model, in my view, entails direct duties to plants. J. Skidmore interprets her model in a similar fashion: Korsgaard s discussion seems to lay great emphasis on a teleological conception of life, suggesting that living things are, by their very nature, oriented toward certain goals or ends, such as self-preservation (2001, 548). If we grant her this controversial conception of life, then we seem to be faced with the fact that being one s own end is not limited to human or animal life, but would even extend to plant life. But does having ends mean having reasons in the needed sense? Skidmore, at least, is skeptical: Does it follow that plants have reasons to pursue such ends? It is hard to imagine what this could mean. Plants simply are not the kinds of things that can have reasons to do anything at all (2001, 548). Under our modern conception of having a reason, it seems implausible to ascribe reason to anything incapable of acting for reasons in a deliberative sense. Nevertheless, in the rich teleological conception of life present in Korsgaard s writing, it makes sense to conflate having ends with having reasons. This is apparent in Korsgaard s discussion of animal reason: Suppose for instance that [this] animal needs nourishment. It perceives that by getting hungry. It finds this unpleasant and is moved to get something to eat. Don t be confused here: it is not that the pain is an unpleasant sensation which gives the animal a reason to eat. The animal has a reason to eat, which is that it will die if it

82 does not (1996, 150). Thus, for Korsgaard, having a reason is quite independent from being capable of rational deliberation and from even being basically aware of it. In this example, the animal has a reason to eat apart from the pain, which is the perception of that reason. It will die if it does not eat, and this is what is relevant to obligation. Plants, equally, have reasons entailed in their principle of life. Assuming the case has been made that plants have reasons and identities, then our direct duty to plants works like this: your biological nature is a fundamental form of your identity. You do not simply value your human nature, but also you value that nature on which your distinctly rational faculties depend: animal nature and more basically biological nature. Since you value the basic principle of life that you find within, then you are obligated to value the same principle in others as well, whether you find it in other humans, animals, or plants. To disvalue the principle of life in others would be to deny your own nature, to lose your self-identity. This shows that plants do not have value simply as being instrumental to our good, but they are valuable as having their own ends, and this is how Korsgaard s model entails obligations to plants. Korsgaard s Response Korsgaard would immediately reject this alleged implication of her argument because she says plants are not conscious and thus not capable of perceiving threats to their identities. She says, Being a plant is not a way of being someone, so it is not a way of being someone that we share with them (1996, 156). And this would mean that our perceiving a threat to a plant would not obligate us to the plant, to change its condition in any way, because the plant itself does not perceive a reason; it does not matter to itself in a self-conscious way.

83 That a plant does not matter to itself in a self-conscious way is an incontestable fact, but as Korsgaard says, plants matter to themselves in an unconscious teleological sense, and this having a reason, not the perception of a reason, seems to be the basis of obligation. For something to obligate us, it need only have a reason that we can also attribute to ourselves, which is to identify with it, and this is clearly what she has in mind when she speaks of plants having ends, which I have shown above. Being a conscious someone might be necessary for holding obligations yourself, but not a necessary condition for being able to obligate others. Under Korsgaard s model, plants obligate us because we are capable of reflecting on reasons that they have to maintain themselves, as having their own needs. We do not need to be called upon by an expression of pain to recognize these needs, we simply infer these needs as reasons by seeing the same principle of life active in ourselves, and this is how we are obligated to plants, not just in regards to them. Conclusion I have attempted to show that Korsgaard s theory of direct duties to animals entails direct duties to plants as well. The only way for Korsgaard to avoid this entailment is to abandon the teleological conception of life, but it is not clear that she can do this without ultimately undermining her case for obligations to animals. Another solution might be to give a more careful defense of why mattering to yourself or being conscious of reasons is necessary to obligate others in your case, or she could simply embrace our having direct duties to plants, but then face the daunting task of answering other questions such as what we are to eat. I think all of these solutions are potentially viable. Some might take my argument as a reductio ad absur-

84 dum against Korsgaard (some think it is absurd to say that we have direct obligations to non-sentient life), but this is not my aim. I am partial to teleological conceptions of life and hopeful that her project can help explain the moral intuition that nonsentient life is intrinsically valuable; however, making the full case for direct obligations to plants will require more work, and I hope that Korsgaard or someone else continues this project. References Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Korsgaard, Christine. 2005. Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 25/26. Salt Lake City: Utah University Press. O Neill, Onora. 1998. Kant on Duties Regarding Nonrational Nature, II. Supplement, Aristotelian Society 72: 211-228. Skidmore, J. 2001. Duties to Animals: The Failure of Kant s Moral Theory. The Journal of Value Inquiry 35: 541-559. Wood, Allen W. 1998. Kant on Duties Regarding Nonrational Nature, I. Supplement, Aristotelian Society 72: 189-210.