First of all, I will describe what I mean when I use the terms regularity (R) and law of

Similar documents
Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

Can a behaviourist admit that we have feelings or thoughts that we keep hidden?

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Is the Identity of Indiscernibles refuted by Max Black's thought experiment? What is the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles (PII)?

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Realism and instrumentalism

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

A note on science and essentialism

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Small Group Assignment 8: Science Replaces Scholasticism

Philosophy and Methods of the Social Sciences

SCIENCE CAN A SCIENTIST BELIEVE IN GOD? Peter M. Budd Professor of Polymer Chemistry University of Manchester

Ch01. Knowledge. What does it mean to know something? and how can science help us know things? version 1.5

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

I Causation. II Explanation

Marcel Sarot Utrecht University Utrecht, The Netherlands NL-3508 TC. Introduction

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

MITOCW watch?v=ppqrukmvnas

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

The tribulations of Rationality in Philosophy, Economics and Biology by Alex Kacelnik University of Oxford

The British Empiricism

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

Aquinas, The Divine Nature

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Unit. Science and Hypothesis. Downloaded from Downloaded from Why Hypothesis? What is a Hypothesis?

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Dennett's Reduction of Brentano's Intentionality

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

Universal Consciousness & the Void

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Introduction to Philosophy P1000 Lecture 1

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

The Ontological Argument. An A Priori Route to God s Existence?

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

Many Minds are No Worse than One

5 A Modal Version of the

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Naturalism Primer. (often equated with materialism )

Proof as a cluster concept in mathematical practice. Keith Weber Rutgers University

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

Kant and his Successors

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy. Hume on Causation. I. Recap of Hume on impressions/ideas

PHIL-176: DEATH. Lecture 15 - The Nature of Death (cont.); Believing You Will Die [March 6, 2007]

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

GOD, Scientists & the Void

Chapter 2: Two Types of Reasoning

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Scanlon on Double Effect

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Philosophical Arguments

Adapted from The Academic Essay: A Brief Anatomy, for the Writing Center at Harvard University by Gordon Harvey. Counter-Argument

This is a repository copy of Does = 5? : In Defense of a Near Absurdity.

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Acting without reasons

The Existence of Material Substance. A Response to George Berkeley s Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. Philosophy 104

145 Philosophy of Science

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

Wolterstorff on Divine Commands (part 1)

Orthodox truthmaker theory cannot be defended by cost/benefit analysis

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Discussion Notes for Bayesian Reasoning

EVOLUTION, EMPIRICISM, AND PURPOSENESS.

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Wisdom and the Quest for Meaning. What s it all about?

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Correcting the Creationist

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability


Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Transcription:

1 Are laws of nature mere regularities? Introduction First of all, I will describe what I mean when I use the terms regularity (R) and law of nature (L). Having done this, I will explore the question, which can be seen as asking whether Ls and Rs are identical, or whether all Ls are a subset of Rs. Regularities I define a regularity as describing something which is repeated over a set of separate observations. I will distinguish between two types of such regularity: firstly (R1), those which involve a single phenomenon (such as the fact that whenever I visit the river, I observe flowing water), and secondly (R2), those which involve multiple phenomena (whenever I stroke my cat, he purrs; when I fill a kettle with water and switch it on, it boils). Obviously, these examples may be over-simplistic, and in reality we may find that they are somehow qualified: my car purs when I stroke him and he's awake; the water in the kettle boils if the kettle is plugged in, etc.. It might also be pointed out that in the case of R1, the observer is part of the regularity, but I will skate over that for now. Of notable significance is the fact that this definition of regularities rules out anything which is necessarily true and can be known a priori; e.g. while it is true that whenever I add 2 and 2 I regularly end up with 4, this doesn't count as a regularity as I am defining it:

2 regularities describe the universe as we find it, not as it necessarily must be. On this definition, Humeans might argue that it is not rationally defensible to expect past regularities to be any guarantee of the future behaviour of the world. Nonetheless, humans are constituted to behave in this way, and so regularities are useful since we successfully use them to make predictions about the future based on our past experience. This usefulness applies to both R1 and R2 type regularities: having previously observed flowing water in the river on a regular basis, I may decide to go there if I want something to drink; I know that in order to boil t he kettle, I have to make sure it's filled with water and switched on. The fact that we have observed a regularity in the past doesn't necessarily result in our assuming that it will recur in the future. For example, if the first three National Lottery draws had been won by someone with blonde hair, it wouldn't be surprising should the fourth draw be won by a brunette. And in some cases, while we take past regularities to act as a guide to future events, we are not altogether surprised to see our expectations upset: the water may fail to boil if the kettle is broken, for example. While we may learn of regularities by observed specific instances, we can form assumptions about future phenomena that do not involve the same specific objects and events which were previously involved. For example, on encountering an unfamiliar cat, I would expect it to purr when stroked (Aristotle uses the term nous to refer to that part of

3 our mind which is capable of generalising in this way). From this, the key points about regularities are that: 1. they are observed (we learn about them empirically) 2. they may or may not have a causal component 3. it is possible to form generalisations based on them 4. in some, but not all, cases, we use them as a guide to future events Laws of Nature Conceivably, the only reason we have seen regularities in the past is the result of nothing more than chance and coincidence: we are doing no more than recognizing pictures in the clouds. But another explanation is that there is some underlying structure to the universe which is realised, or manifested, in the regularities that we observe and use to guide our behaviour. Such underlying structures are what are referred to as laws of nature, and they can be used to explain the regularities that we see. Should these laws exist, we would not be able to observe them directly, but intuitively it seems that the more evidence we accumulate, we ought to be able to get closer to an approximation of their essence. Should such laws exist, then they would be more powerful as predictors than mere regularities : they would apply to entities of which we have no direct experience: we may use it to make predictions what stars might be like in galaxies that our beyond our limits of observation, or about the behaviour of an as yet undiscovered element which occupies an

4 empty spot in the periodic table. But there are limitations too: we can only do this when we have experience of similar, or related entities. We cannot be confident about the laws of nature that govern the what happened at the time of the Big Bang. Another possibility is that while such a structure of universal laws does exist, the picture we have of it is completely wrong: it may be that there are various different combinations of laws which would result in the universe behaving in the ways that we have so far observed; perhaps we have found one of those sets which is consistent with our observations, and self-coherent, but nevertheless untrue. Kuhn argued that science undergoes paradigm shifts where a whole set of previously held beliefs has to be replaced; however, it may be that despite these shifts, which we see as moving us nearer to an ultimate truth, it may be that the reality underlying our evolving set of beliefs is completely different to anything we will ever describe. Perhaps the ultimate truth is not something we would be able to understand in any case ( I don't understand it. Nobody does - Richard Feynman The Strange Theory of Light and Matter ). On this reading then, a law of nature is a fundamental truth about our universe which we deduce based on a series of empirical observations (i.e., it's not a necessary truth which we could know a priori). It's also generally true: while we see specific instances of events which obey a law of nature, we regard such laws as being applicable throughout space and time. Are Laws of Nature mere Regularities? From the definitions above, there are clearly common aspects between regularities and laws

5 of nature. In both cases they are a feature of the way the world is, rather than the way it has to be; they cause us to form associations and make predictions about future events. But unlike regularities, laws of nature attempt to describe something more general, consistent and fundamental. A regularity might be observed which is accidental (every time I go to the beach it rains), but a law of nature should hold in all cases. According to this account, laws of nature are not identical to regularities: they differ in the following ways: 1. we don't observe laws of nature directly 2. we make more extravagant claims for the ubiquity of laws of nature 3. we don't expect predictions based on laws of nature to be disproved 4. we regard laws of nature as having explanatory power The last point is the one that most significantly distinguishes laws of nature from regularities. If I say the kettle boils whenever I switch it on, this may be true, but doesn't get to the root explanation of what happened. On the other hand, if we postulate a law of gravity, then we can use it to explain why the apple falls from a tree, and we don't have to go any further; the law is axiomatic and does not need to be explained (except, perhaps in terms of other natural laws). However, it is not clear what the justification is for investing laws with this explanatory power. Laws then, are undeniably useful, but is it reasonable to say that they are any more than simplifications, or generalisations, of past observed regularities? In other words, are they no more than the result of aggregating sets of regularities, removing any accidental ones, and stripping them of their particulars? The chief fact which might argue against laws of nature being anything special is that we

6 have seen occasions in the past where laws of nature have turned out not to be so. For example, while Newton's laws of motion were for some time taken to be natural laws, science has since shown that they do not seem to apply on very large or small scales. As new observations are made which conflict with our understanding of a law of nature, the law needs to be discarded, or qualified in some way. This doesn't seem different, except in scale, from the way that my expectations are upset by the failure of my kettle to boil a cup of water; it seems that a law of nature is only safe so long as we haven't yet performed observations in a way that invalidates it. Conclusion In conclusion, I think that while there may be laws of nature, in the sense that there may be some kind of governing set of structures which dictate how the universe behaves, we have no way to be sure that they do exist, and no way to be sure of what they are: those laws of nature that we use are no more than generalisations made based on observed regularities, and may or may not resemble any true laws of nature. It may be useful for us to behave as if we do have valid laws of nature, but this behaviour is not in itself any guide to the existence of such laws. Nick Hudson 2005 nick@nickoh.com

7 Bibliography Okasha, S (2002) Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. Oxford Psillos, S (2002) Causation and Explanation. Acumen. Chesham Swartz, N (1995) A Neo-Humean Perspective: Laws as Regularities [WWW Document Retrieved 01 September, 2005 from World Wide Web: http://www.sfu.ca/philosophy/physical-law/regularity_theory.htm