What is a counterexample?

Similar documents
Logic and Artificial Intelligence Lecture 26

Iterated Belief Revision

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Bayesian Probability

Informalizing Formal Logic

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

A number of epistemologists have defended

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Constructing the World

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice Andrés Perea Excerpt More information

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Reasoning and Decision-Making under Uncertainty

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Learning is a Risky Business. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Course Webpage:

The New Paradigm and Mental Models

Orienting Social Epistemology 1 Francis Remedios, Independent Researcher, SERRC

What is Game Theoretical Negation?

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

SOME PROBLEMS IN REPRESENTATION OF KNOWLEDGE IN FORMAL LANGUAGES

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

The distinction between truth-functional and non-truth-functional logical and linguistic

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Stout s teleological theory of action

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Postulates for conditional belief revision

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Introduction. September 30, 2011

Frontloading and Fregean Sense: Reply to Neta, Schroeter, and Stanley

V.F. Hendricks. Mainstream and Formal Epistemology. Cambridge University Press, 2006, xii pp.

Bayesian Probability

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Pragmatic Presupposition

DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT?

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Aboutness and Justification

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Presupposition: An (un)common attitude?

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Comments on Seumas Miller s review of Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group agents in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (April 20, 2

CONCEPT FORMATION IN ETHICAL THEORIES: DEALING WITH POLAR PREDICATES

Keywords precise, imprecise, sharp, mushy, credence, subjective, probability, reflection, Bayesian, epistemology

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

Uncommon Priors Require Origin Disputes

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY (Michaelmas 2017) Dr Michael Biggs

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction

Knowledge, Safety, and Questions

by Blackwell Publishing, and is available at

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY Michaelmas 2018 Dr Michael Biggs

The Positive Argument for Constructive Empiricism and Inference to the Best

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

WHAT IF BIZET AND VERDI HAD BEEN COMPATRIOTS?

Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Philosophical Review.

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Coordination Problems

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

Varieties of Apriority

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

A dialogical, multi-agent account of the normativity of logic. Catarin Dutilh Novaes Faculty of Philosophy University of Groningen

Act individuation and basic acts

Evidence and the epistemic theory of causality

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture *

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Causation and Free Will

Chains of Inferences and the New Paradigm in. the Psychology of Reasoning

Contradictory Information Can Be Better than Nothing The Example of the Two Firemen

Realism and instrumentalism

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Transcription:

Lorentz Center 4 March 2013 What is a counterexample? Jan-Willem Romeijn, University of Groningen Joint work with Eric Pacuit, University of Maryland Paul Pedersen, Max Plank Institute Berlin

Co-authors Eric Pacuit and Paul Pedersen.

Formal philosophy There is a long tradition of formal analysis in philosophy, certainly insofar as it is concerned with matters epistemic. Logic provides a formal account correct inference. Confirmation theory formalizes the support relation between theory and evidence. Belief revision theory presents a formal structure for belief maintenance. Of course the list goes on...

The informal world The informal world of the epistemic is best described by models from the social sciences. By contrast, philosophical models... take a normative stance and hence motivate action, concern ideal agents rather than real people, and are often tested against intuitions rather than empirical facts. Despite the differences, there is a trend to bring social science and formal philosophy together.

Model vs world What to conclude if formal models do not square with our intuitions or with empirical fact? Are the models wrong, or applied incorrectly? This choice has implications for the role and status of formal philosophical models in the social sciences.

Contents 1 Normative and descriptive models 7 2 Iterated belief revision 12 3 Lexicographic Bayesian models 19 4 Discussion on counterexamples 21 5 Back to the informal world 26

1 Normative and descriptive models There are many interactions of formal models in philosophy and social science: Normative formal models are there for real people to aspire to. Social science can inform philosophers on how to tailor and communicate their models. Social science theories need conceptual tools and foundations. Philosophy can provide formal structures for unifying and interpreting empirical findings.

Experimental philosophy Empirical facts about people s reasoning and ethical considerations routinely informs modelling in philosophy. Examples: The psychology of reasoning has stimulated philosophical research into alternatives to the deductive consequence relation. The linguistics of conditional sentences impacts on the philosophical debate over the semantics of conditionals. The economics and psychology of decision making has put pressure on philosophical models of practical rationality.

Foundational input Conversely, normative philosophical models have often been used to perform a descriptive function in the sciences: Probabilistic degrees of belief have been employed descriptively in a wide range of disciplines. Epistemic logics have been used to describe strategic economic behavior. Formal philosophical ideas on causality have made their way into cognitive psychology of causal inference.

Model failure or misapplication For meaningful interactions we need to know in what sense the normative models can be wrong. If every failure can be put down to misapplication, the model cannot be falsified.

The role of the model The model is in that case not a substantive theory on norms or facts, but perhaps a good framework for theorizing. The model might serve as a universal tool to identify the presuppositions of real, or ideal, reasoning.

2 Iterated belief revision AGM belief revision is a theory on revising beliefs in the light of evidence: new evidence can be accommodated by expanding, contracting, or shifting the set of sentences currently entertained as true. K new K old The theory is diachronic and qualitative and thus fits well with the coarsegrained and dynamic nature of real reasoning.

Iteration The theory runs into unintuitive consequences when the rules for revision are applied iteratively. One source of problems is meta-information:... information about how I learn some of the things I learn, about the sources of my information, or about what I believe about what I believe and don t believe. If the story we tell in an example makes certain information about any of these things relevant, then it needs to be included in a proper model of the story, if it is to play the right role in the evaluation of the abstract principles of the model. Robert Stalnaker (2009), Iterated Belief Revision, Erkenntnis 70, pp. 189 209.

Problematic postulates The following postulates are often added to the basic AGM postulates that determine the revisions: I1 demands that if ϕ ψ is a theorem (with respect to the background theory), then first learning ψ followed by the more specific information ϕ is equivalent to directly learning the more specific information ϕ. I2 demands that first learning ϕ followed by learning a piece of information ψ incompatible with ϕ is the same as simply learning ψ outright, e.g., first learning ϕ and then ϕ should result in the same belief state as directly learning ϕ.

Counterexample to I1 There are three switches, yz. = y = z. The light U is on if = y, and W is on if Alice, Bob, and Carla report respectively that switch = 1, y = 0, and z = 1. Light U is observed to be on. Light W is observed to be on. After this series of reports, belief revision prescribes that we believe that yz are 111. But if we directly learn that light W is on, we may also hold 000 possible.

Counterexample to I2 Two fair coins are flipped and placed in two opaque boxes, 1 and 2. Independent and reliable observers deliver reports about their status, heads or tails up, H or T. Alice and Bob report that the coin in respectively box 1 and 2 are heads up, H 1 and H 2. Carla and Dora report that the coin in respectively box 1 and 2 are tails up, T 1 and T 2. Elmer reports that the coin in box 1 is heads up, H 1. After this series of reports, belief revision prescribes that we also believe that H 2.

Diagnosis of the latter The ideal agent comes to believe that the coins are correlated, but this meta-information is not explicit in the story. It is a side effect of learning first that both coins are heads and then that they are both tails.

Repairing belief revision After every learning experience we can retain the initial belief that the position of the coins are independent. What is the belief revision policy generating this sequence?

3 Lexicographic Bayesian models We accommodate the counterexamples in two steps: We provide a Bayesian model in which presuppositions on order and dependence can be made explicit. This model already satisfies the basic postulates of belief revision. The qualitative and diachronic character of belief revision can be replicated by an extension to lexicographic probability assignments. Apart from this we refined the event structure of reports and states.

Highly flexible models The Bayesian model enriches the range of doxastic attitudes that the ideal agent can have. In this way we can model all manner of meta-information. AGM belief revision can be made to fit counterexamples to both I1 and I2.

4 Discussion on counterexamples We can draw some general lessons about the balance between counterexamples and misapplications of formal models of belief dynamics, concerning... the generality of belief revision theory, its criteria for applicability, the use of including meta-information in the model, and the existence of genuine counterexamples.

Criteria for application Notice that AGM belief revision does not come equipped with its own user manual. The criteria for application are extra-theoretical. It is therefore hard to say how far the theory might stretch in general.

Don t be lazy The Bayesian resolutions illustrate that belief revision can accommodate particular kinds of meta-information, pertaining to the conceptual, causal, and epistemic relations among information items. Notably, the fact that we do not find a model, does not entail that there are none.

Coarse-grained modelling In some examples we can ignore the meta-information, which is often not specified in the description of an example. For Bayesian models, Halpern and Grünwald define the condition of coarsening at random, which holds when a more coarse space of reports yields the same belief dynamics.

Genuine counterexamples Conversely, genuine counterexamples to belief revision are cases in which no amount of refining events, reports, and doxastic attitudes will help. We think that Grünwald and Halpern lead the way to a systematic characterization of counterexamples.

5 Back to the informal world It is an open question whether current formal philosophical models have any genuine counterexamples in the above sense. But if they do not, the models may still offer great value to substantive social science.

Coordinate principles Geometry cannot by itself be falsified by measurements of physical space. To apply it to space, we need coordinative principles. The normative formal models may well have exactly that status in social science: they establish structure but we cannot prove them wrong.

Thank you The slides for this talk will be available at http://www.philos.rug.nl/ romeyn. For comments and questions, email j.w.romeijn@rug.nl.