Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Similar documents
Constructing the World

Constructing the World

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Varieties of Apriority

Constructing the World

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Minds and Machines spring The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited spring 03

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Comments on Lasersohn

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Ethical non-naturalism

APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Informational Models in Deontic Logic: A Comment on Ifs and Oughts by Kolodny and MacFarlane

Constructing the World

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Skepticism and Internalism

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Conceivability, Possibility and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Epistemic Modals and Correct Disagreement

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Is God Good By Definition?

Higher-Order Epistemic Attitudes and Intellectual Humility. Allan Hazlett. Forthcoming in Episteme

Two-dimensional semantics and the nesting problem

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Ethics is subjective.

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Glossary (for Constructing the World)

Matthew Parrott. In order for me become aware of another person's psychological states, I must observe her

The unity of the normative

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

THE ROLE OF DISAGREEMENT IN SEMANTIC THEORY

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Paradox of Deniability

TWO CONCEPTIONS OF THE SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. Marian David Notre Dame University

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

Semantic Values? Alex Byrne, MIT

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Analyticity and reference determiners

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

Modal disagreements. Justin Khoo. Forthcoming in Inquiry

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries

Frontloading and Fregean Sense: Reply to Neta, Schroeter, and Stanley

Intuition as Philosophical Evidence

Seeing Through The Veil of Perception *

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Aboutness and Justification

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Chalmers s Frontloading Argument for A Priori Scrutability

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Simplicity made difficult

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

A-LEVEL PHILOSOPHY 7172/1

Three easy points on relative truth

Moral Argument. Jonathan Bennett. from: Mind 69 (1960), pp

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI

Theories of propositions

In (1975), Peter Unger argued that knowledge

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

Transcription:

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers

An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (3) There are moral truths.

First Premise (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths I.e. there is some conjunction of basic truths F such that for all truths T, F T is a priori. E.g. F = physical/phenomenal/indexical/that s-all truths Or a broader set -- but not including moral truths. [See Chalmers and Jackson, Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation.]

Second Premise (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths Strictly: no nontrivial moral truths Grounded in two related theses/intuitions Failure of convergence Genuineness of moral disagreement

Failure of Convergence Convergence Thesis: Ideally rational agents, fully informed about fundamental truths, will agree in their moral judgments. Intuition 1: Convergence is false. Fully informed agents with sufficiently different values might diverge in their moral judgments, even though neither is guilty of irrationality from the God s eye point of view. If convergence is false, then empirical truths plus ideal a priori reasoning do not yield determinate moral truths.

Genuine Moral Disagreement Intuition 2: Apparent moral disagreement is genuine disagreement (not merely verbal disagreement), even between subjects/ communities with very different views. Presuming that the apparent moral terms play relevantly similar practical roles in guiding action, and so on. If so, one can t protect convergence by diagnosing apparent cases of divergence as involving different concepts Instead there are shared concepts, e.g. good and right.

Third Premise Premise 1 and 2 entail: There are no (nontrivial) moral truths. Noncognitivism, error theory? But there are still both intuitive and technical reasons to hold premise 3: there are moral truths Murder is wrong Murder is wrong is true. Q: Can one reconcile premise 3 with something like premises 1 and 2? Or at least, something that respects the intuitions and arguments behind them?

Moral Relativism Moral relativism (cf. Egan, Macfarlane, et al): Moral utterances (e.g. murder is wrong ) are true not just relative to a circumstance of evaluation, but also relative to a standard of assessment Likewise, the propositions expressed by moral utterances are not true or false absolutely, but true or false relative to standards of assessment. Relative to standard 1, murder is wrong is true. Relative to standard 2, murder is wrong is false.

Standards of Assessment What is a standard of assessment? Many possibilities: but we can think of it as a set of values, grounded in the most fundamental commitments of a subject or a community. E.g. grounded in some subset of a subject s pro-attitudes (something in the vicinity of approval, desire, utility) Perhaps idealized to yield values that the subject would have on ideal reflection. Any given subject will be associated with a standard of assessment Different subjects will have different standards of assessment (even on idealization, given failure of convergence).

Moral Disagreement Say you and I have different standards: I say Murder is wrong You say Murder is not wrong. Murder is wrong expresses the same proposition for both of us (one that is true relative to my standard, false relative to yours). So we assert and deny the same proposition -- we are really disagreeing. I am not asserting the proposition Murder is wrong according to my standard -- then we wouldn t be disagreeing (cf. contextualism).

Relativism About Truth Fixed point: Murder is wrong iff murder is wrong is true. So murder is wrong is true can be true relative to one standard, false relative to another. So relativism about good leads immediately to relativism about true N.B. this need be only a limited relativism, involving truth of moral sentences When I say S is true, I am not saying S is true according to my standards But my assertions are governed by my standards.

Moral Truth Revisited Premise 3: There are moral truths. Murder is wrong Murder is wrong is true There are moral truths. Of course these truths are true relative to a standard (mine) -- but this is the operative standard.

Truth and Absolute Truth We can define an operator absolutely, such that Absolutely S is true (relative to any standard) iff S is true relative to all standards. Then Absolutely murder is wrong is false (or indeterminate). (Unless we go relativist about truth relative to a standard -- but no need to do this.) Define a predicate Wrong so that x is Wrong is true (relative to any standard) iff x is wrong is true relative to all standards, I.e. iff Absolutely x is wrong is true Likewise, a predicate True such that S is True is true (relative to any standard) iff S is true is true relative to all standards, I.e. if Absolutely (S is true) is true. Then murder is wrong, but murder is not Wrong. Murder is wrong is true, but it is not True. There are nontrivial moral truths, but no nontrivial moral Truths. According to the relativist, wrong and true in ordinary English express the relativistic concept (wrong, true) not the absolute concept (Wrong, True).

Truth and Apriority What about the link between truth and apriority? (Premises 1 and 2) Are moral truths a priori entailed by fundamental truths? It s natural to hold: the most fundamental and universal moral truths are (I) knowable, (ii) such that one can be justified in believing them, and (iii) such that this knowledge/justification can be a priori Relativism about morality doesn t entail that one can t know or be justified in believing these truths, or that the knowledge/justification is a posteriori. What about the (false) fundamental moral beliefs of others with different standards? Either (I) these are justified (and justified a priori), although false. Or (ii) they are not justified. (ii) preserves the link between justification (especially a priori justification) and truth. But leads naturally to relativism about justification.

Relativism about Justification Claims such as S is justified in believing P are themselves true or false relative to standards. So: X is justified in believing that murder is wrong may be false by my standards, true by X s standards. N.B. The standards here may be the standards as before, merely involving differences in values, and affecting only moral beliefs. Likewise for related epistemic notions such as a priori, rational, etc Then the relativist can allow that all moral truths (but not moral falsehoods) are a priori entailed by fundamental truths. When M is true, F M is knowable (and justifiable) a priori. When M is false, F M is not knowable or justifiable a priori.

Whither Convergence? What about premise 2: No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths. This now appears to be false. Likewise, the convergence claim: All ideally rational and fully informed beings will converge in the moral judgments appears to be true. The relevant moral beliefs in beings with different standards will not be justified, and these beings will not be ideally rational (by my standards). However, this view can arguably save the intuitions behind the denial of convergence.

The Intuition Behind Divergence The intuition behind the denial of convergence was: Fully informed agents with sufficiently different values might diverge in their moral judgments, even though neither is guilty of irrationality from the God s eye point of view. We might reconstruct this as: fully informed agents who are not Irrational might diverge in their moral judgments Where an agent is Irrational if it is irrational relative to all standards. If an agent is not Irrational, let us say it is Rational* (N.B. not Rational). Then the relativist can allow: fully informed, ideally Rational* agents can diverge in their moral judgments. Likewise: moral truths are not A priori entailed by all truths.

Three Inconsistent Triads (R1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (R2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (R3) There are moral truths. (I1) All truths are A priori entailed by fundamental truths (I2) No moral truths are A priori entailed by fundamental truths (I3) There are moral truths. (A1) All Truths are A priori entailed by fundamental truths (A2) No moral Truths are A priori entailed by fundamental truths (A3) There are moral Truths. Diagnosis: (R2), (I1), and (A3) are false.

A Consistent Triad (C1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (C2) No moral truths are A priori entailed by fundamental truths (C3) There are moral truths. [Also a version with (C1*): All Truths are A Priori entailed by fundamental truths.] Arguably these readings capture most of the force of the original case for the three premises.

Moral Rationalism Rationalist Thesis: If X is rational and well-informed, and phi-ing is right, then X ought (rationally) to judge that phi-ing is right. Given relativism about morality without relativism about rationality, the Rationalist Thesis is plausibly not true (and is certainly not True). Given relativism about morality and rationality, the Rationalist Thesis is plausibly true (and indeed True).

Internalism and Externalism Judgment internalism: If S judges that it would be right for them to phi, S will have some motivation to phi. Moral relativism can explain this, insofar as moral judgments reflect prima facie values, and prima facie values reflect motivating proattitudes. Existence internalism: If it would be right for S to phi, then if S is rational and well-informed, S will have some motivation to phi. Moral relativism plus relativism about rationality can explain this (e.g. via judgment internalism plus the rationalist thesis). Moral relativism without relativism about rationality cannot.

Multiple Concepts Arguably: there are two concepts in the vicinity of each of good, rational, and so on: good (relativistic) and Good (absolute) rational (relativistic) and Rational (Absolute) Some elements of our usage may better fit the absolute concept, while some elements may better fit the relativistic concept. It s an empirical question which best fits our overall use of these term. Perhaps no determinate fact of the matter about which is the real content. It could be that e.g. the relativistic concept is a somewhat better fit for good than for rational E.g. X is rational iff X is absolutely rational is closer to being a conceptual truth than X is good iff X is absolutely good. This might also help to explain the pull of denying convergence.

Conclusion Moral relativism has a chance of reconciling the existence of nontrivial moral truths with the intuitions of divergence and of disagreement, and with the link between truth and apriority. But moral relativism may well bring epistemic relativism in its wake.