Emotivism and its critics

Similar documents
THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Emotivism. Meta-ethical approaches

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

BRITISH PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION AQA PHILOSOPHY UNIT 3: MORAL PHILOSOPHY

Ethical non-naturalism

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Norm-Expressivism and the Frege-Geach Problem

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

Our topic today is the reality of value. There are different sorts of value but we will focus on the reality of moral value.

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Mackie s Error Theory of Moral Judgments

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

New Chapter: Ethics and Morality

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Coordination Problems

Comments on Lasersohn

[name] [course] [teaching assistant s name] [discussion day and time] [question being answered] [date turned in]

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Stout s teleological theory of action

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Thomas Reid on personal identity

Value Theory. Contemporary approaches to metaethics

Lecture notes, Phil 4830, spr 03. Anti-Realism

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Bayesian Probability

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Divine command theory

Ryle on Systematically Misleading Expresssions

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

A problem for expressivism

Simplicity made difficult

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY AND ST. THOMAS. The debate about the naturalistic fallacy, or about whether value judgments and ought

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Reply to Robert Koons

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

One's. Character Change

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Problems in Philosophy Final Review. Some methodological points

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts. Indrek Reiland. Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have recently developed similar views of propositional attitudes

Transcription:

Emotivism and its critics PHIL 83104 September 19, 2011 1. The project of analyzing ethical terms... 1 2. Interest theories of goodness... 2 3. Stevenson s emotivist analysis of good... 2 3.1. Dynamic and descriptive uses, and emotive meaning 3.2. Stevenson s analysis of good 3.3. Stevenson s analysis and the arguments against interest theories 4. Objections to Stevenson s emotivism... 4 4.1. Geach s critique of ascriptivism 4.2. Problems understanding dynamic meaning 4.3. Doubts about internalism 4.4. The fact/value distinction 1. THE PROJECT OF ANALYZING ETHICAL TERMS Much of 20th century moral philosophy was concerned with the analysis of ethical terms. Why pursue an analysis of terms like good? Stevenson: Ethical questions arise first in the form Is so and so good?... These questions are dicult partly because we don t quite know what we are seeking. We are asking, Is there a needle in that haystack? without even knowing just what a needle is. So the first thing we must do is examine the questions themselves (289). As Stevenson recognizes, there s an intuitive problem with this project of analysis. On the one hand, it does not seem that we can require that everyone who understands good wil be able to rcognize a correct analysis, for this would make informative analyses impossible. On the other hand, we need some way to check whether our analysis is correct. (This is one version of the paradox of analysis. ) Stevenson s solution: the analysis must be relevant, in the sense that any legitimate question or claim which can be made with the old term should be possible with its analysis. This is reasonable as far as it goes even if it leaves unanswered the central question of how we are supposed to tell when we are able to ask or claim all of the things we were able to ask and claim with the term to be analyzed.

2. INTEREST THEORIES OF GOODNESS Good has often been analyzed in terms of approval and similar attitudes. (15) According to Stevenson, Hobbes claims good means desired by me, whereas Hume claimed that good means desired by most people. Set aside the question of whether these are the right interpretations of Hobbes and Hume. Stevenson thinks that these proposed analyses of good are certainly partially relevant. But, Stevenson claims, three arguments show that interest theories like these cannot be the whole story. 1. Ethical disagreement. It seems possible for people to disagree about what is good. But, as Stevenson says, this possibility seems to rule out Hobbes s version of the interest theory: For consider the following argument: This is good. That isn t so; it s not good. As translated by Hobbes, this becomes: I desire this. That isn t so, for I don t. The speakers are not contradicting one another, and think they are, only because of an elementary confusion in the use of pronouns. (16) Stevenson notes that disagreement between members of different communities seems to rule out Hume s version in just the same way. 2. Motivational force of judgements about the good. As Stevenson says, a person who recognizes X to be good must ipso facto acquire a stronger tendency to act in its favor than he otherwise would have. (16) (This is one thing that is meant by internalism about ethical judgements.) 3. Unverifiability. Stevenson claims that the goodness of anything must not be verifiable solely by use of the scientific method. (16) Relationship to the open question argument. Stevenson goes on to give his own analysis of good at this point, after refuting interest theories. This indicates that he takes interest theories to be the main alternative to the theory that he presents. But there are also a host of traditional analyses of good : in terms of divine will, a moral law, maximization of pleasure... One question to ask about Stevenson s article: does he take his three arguments against interest theories to also rule out these traditional views? Do they rule out these traditional views? 3. STEVENSON S EMOTIVIST ANALYSIS OF GOOD 3.1. Dynamic and descriptive uses, and emotive meaning Stevenson held that these problems were fatal for interest theories as they had been traditionally developed. But he claimed that a new kind of interest theory could meet these three objections to interest-based analyses of good. He claimed: 2

I believe that the three requirements, given above, are perfectly sensible; that there is some one sense of good which satisfies all three requirements; and that no traditional interest theory satisfies them all. But this does not imply that good must be explained in terms of a Platonic Idea, or of a Categorical Imperative, or of an unique, unanalyzable property. On the contrary, the three requirements can be met by a kind of interest theory. But we must give up a presupposition which all the traditional interest theories have made. Traditional interest theories hold that ethical statements are descriptive of the existing state of interests that they simply give information about interests....it is this emphasis on description, on information, which leads to their incomplete relevance. Doubtless there is always some element of description in ethical judgements, but this is by no means all. Their major use is not to indicate facts, but to create an influence. Instead of merely describing people s interests, they change or intensify them. They recommend an interest in an object, rather than state that the interest already exists. (18-19) The key here is Stevenson s distinction between descriptive and dynamic uses of language as a function of the purposes of the speaker. (21) This is part of Stevenson s psychological/causal view of meaning: the meaning of an expression is defined in terms of which effects uses of it tend to bring about. This leads to a definition of emotive meaning: The emotive meaning of a word is a tendency of a word, arising through the history of its usage, to produce...affective responses in people. It is the immediate aura of feeling which hovers about a word. (23) 3.2. Stevenson s analysis of good By now it should be clear that Stevenson thinks that good and right and other such terms have an emotive meaning. But what, exactly, is this meaning? He says: As a preliminary definition, let us take an inaccurate approxima- tion. It may be more misleading than helpful, but will do to begin with. Roughly, then, the sentence X is good means We like X. (24) Why does Stevenson say that this analysis may be misleading? Immediately after giving it, he considers an objection: if someone says to me X is good then, if Stevenson s analysis were correct, it would be appropriate for me to respond by saying: But I don t like it. What led you to believe that I did? But this is clearly not appropriate. (Note that this is a version of the first argument above that Stevenson gave against interest theories.) 3

Stevenson replies that this objection rests on a misunderstanding of his theory. He is not, like previous interest theorists, saying that the meanings of ethical claims are descriptive of our likes, interests, and desires; rather, he is suggesting that X is good means something like what We like X means, when the latter is used dynamically. We ll return later to the question of what, exactly, this means. But the basic idea is that in uttering X is good we are not trying to describe the world as being a certain way, but rather trying to bring about a certain change in the world. 3.3. Stevenson s analysis and the arguments against interest theories Response to argument 1: Why one might think that an emoitivist theory like Stevenson s has, like interest theories, trouble making sense of cases of moral disagreement. Stevenson s reply: the distinction between disagreement in belief and disagreement in interest. The emotivist might also press this point further, and say that emotivism is not only consistent with the existence of ethical disagreement, but also provides a very neat explanation of one salient feature of ethical disagreement: its intractability. If ethical disagreements are not disagreements about any matter of fact, wouldn t this explain the persistence of ethical disagremeents between subjects who agree on all relevant matters of fact? Response to argument 2: since part of Stevenson s theory is that someone who judges X is good expresses interest in or approval of X, this accounts for the magnetism of the good. This is often taken to be one of the main strengths of emotivist theories: they make sense of internalist theses without positing any strange magnetic properties of things. Response to argument 3: why the empirical method is not sufficient to give us agreement in interest; this is just a special case of the fact that agreement in belief is not sufficient for agreement in interest. 4. OBJECTIONS TO STEVENSON S EMOTIVISM 4.1. Geach s critique of ascriptivism Geach characterizes ascriptivism as follows: Ascriptivists hold that to say that an action x was voluntary on the part of an agent A is not to de scribe the act in any way, but to a scribe it to A, to hold A responsible for it. (221) 4

Given this characterization, it is fair to say that Stevenson holds a version of ascriptivism applied to ethics. Geach gives the following parody of ascriptivism about action claims (and emotivism about ethical claims): I said that ascriptivism naturally thrives in the present climate of opinion... It is really quite easy to construct theories on this pattern; here is a new one that has occcurred to me. To call a man happy is not to characterize or describe his condition; macarizing a man (that is, calling him happy: the words macarize and macarism are in the O.E.D.) is a special non-descriptive use of language. If we consider such typical examples of macarism as the Beatitudes, or again such proverbial expressions as happy is the bride that the sun shines on; happy are the dead that the rain rains on, we can surely say that these sentences are not used to convey propositions.... to speak of people s happiness is to macarize them, not to describe their state....there you are; I make a free gift of the idea to anyone who likes it. Geach s worry is, in part, that emotivism can only seem plausible because of an idiosyncratic choice of examples. Geach quotes Wittgenstein approvingly: when put on an unbalanced diet of examples philosophy suffers from deficiency diseases. Geach s example of a use which is not explained by Stevenson s theory is a conditional: If gambling is bad, inviting people to gamble is bad. Here bad is predicated of gambling; but the speaker does not assert that gambling is bad, nor does he condemn gambling. So how can the emotivist make sense of this sort of use of ethical terms? Geach does not just offer counterexamples to this sort of theory; he also offers an explanation of why these counterexamples arise. Geach thinks that emotivism ignores the distinction between predication and assertion. This, as you may recall, is Frege s distinction, emphasized in Thought, between the thought expressed by a sentence and the act of asserting it. As Geach says in Assertion, A thought may have just the same content whether you assent to its truth or not; a proposition may occur in discourse now asserted, now unasserted, and yet be recognizably the same proposition.... I shall call this point about assertion the Frege point... The magnitude and variety of philosophical errors that result from not seeing the Frege point justifes a missionary zeal in the matter. In these terms, Geach s criticism is that emotivism ignores the Frege point. 5

4.2. Problems understanding dynamic meaning Another of the worries Geach has in mind is a worry about understanding exactly what interpretation the emotivist is giving to ethical claims. We might say that to say X is bad it to condemn something; but what does this mean? One might, after all, naturally think that to condemn something is just to make a certain descriptive claim. Here two possibilities naturally present themselves. One is that when we say X is bad we are adopting a primitive emotive attitude toward X must like when we say Boo! at a sports game. The other which Stevenson has in mind when he talks about the quasiimperative meaning of ethical terms is that X is bad is an imperative, much like Don t do X! But either way we go here, if we keep the Frege point in mind, we get absurd results. Consider claims about the past. If I say The 19th century slave trade was a great evil. could I really be saying Boo! 19th century slave traders. or 19th century people: don t deal in slavery! Or consider again Geach s example of the conditional, If gambling is bad, inviting people to gamble is bad. It does not seem that this is adequately rendered by either of If Boo! gambling, then Boo! inviting people to gamble. If don t gamble, then don t invite people to gamble. Neither of these is even an intelligible sentence. Many contemporary ethicists have views which are descendants of emotivism though usually these views are called non-cognitivist rather than emotivist. These ethicists have tried to develop response to Geach s criticism and variants thereof; it s still an open question whether these responses are satisfactory. But it is pretty much universally agreed that this is one of the main challenges facing views to the effect that ethical sentences and the like are non-fact-stating. 6

4.3. Doubts about internalism One might also question the internalist theses which are among the principal motivations for emotivism. The example of the amoralist and doubts about whether it is really impossible for someone to claim X is good. while having no inclination at all to pursue X. 4.4. The fact/value distinction Emotivism about ethical claims relies on a distinction between two sorts of sentences: descriptive sentences, on the one hand, and evaluative or normative sentences on the other. (This is one thing that goes under the heading, the fact/value distinction. ) But one might question whether this background picture, which involves there being a clean break between factual and evaluative claims, can be sustained. An example: claims about epistemic rationality. Can these be understood in emotivist terms? 7