On the Incompatibility of Reasons Internalism and the Practical Rationality of Moral Action

Similar documents
CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective. Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

PH 329: Seminar in Kant Fall 2010 L.M. Jorgensen

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Scanlon on Double Effect

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

(P420-1) Practical Reason in Ancient Greek and Contemporary Philosophy. Spring 2018

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism. Derek Parfit s two volume work On What Matters is, as many philosophers

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Is Morality Rational?

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

Action in Special Contexts

Ethics (ETHC) JHU-CTY Course Syllabus

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

In his paper Internal Reasons, Michael Smith argues that the internalism

Julius & Aleks 03/27/2014

A primer of major ethical theories

5 A Modal Version of the

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Practical reasons and rationality. A critique of the desire-based reasons model

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Hard Determinism, Humeanism, and Virtue Ethics

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

REASONS AND REFLECTIVE ENDORSMENT IN CHRISTINE KORSGAARD S THE SOURCES OF NORMATIVITY ERIC C. BROWN. (Under the direction of Melissa Seymour-Fahmy)

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

To link to this article:

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

A Categorical Imperative. An Introduction to Deontological Ethics

Agency and Responsibility. According to Christine Korsgaard, Kantian hypothetical and categorical imperative

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Internal to what? A critique of the distinction between internal and external reasons for action (*)

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Smith s Incoherence Argument for Moral Rationalism

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Skepticism and Internalism

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Natural Motives and the Motive of Duty: Hume and Kant on Our Duties to Others

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have


How Problematic for Morality Is Internalism about Reasons? Simon Robertson

Metaethics and Theories of Motivation

Reply to Robert Koons

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

Modern Deontological Theory: Rawlsian Deontology

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

Kantian Ethics, Animals, and the Law

Reasons as Premises of Good Reasoning. Jonathan Way. University of Southampton. Forthcoming in Pacific Philosophical Quarterly

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

The Exeter College Summer Programme at Exeter College in the University of Oxford. Good Life or Moral Life?

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

BERNARD WILLIAMS S INTERNALISM: A NEW INTERPRETATION. Micah J Baize

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality

Reasons: A Puzzling Duality?

Reason Papers Vol. 36, no. 1

Transcription:

1 On the Incompatibility of Reasons Internalism and the Practical Rationality of Moral Action Lane DesAutels Abstract: In what follows, I explore the relationship between two widely held theses in moral and practical philosophy: reasons internalism and the practical rationality of moral action. The goal of this paper is to show the impossibility of holding a (certain sort of) internalist view of reasons while at the same time maintaining that moral acts are always necessitated by practical rationality. 1. Introduction The goal of this paper is to explore the relationship between two attractive and commonly held theses in practical philosophy. They are: And 1. Reasons internalism (RI): reasons always bear some relation to an agent s motivations (or desires). 2. The practical rationality of moral action thesis (PRMA): that an act is morally right (or wrong) necessarily gives all agents to which morality applies a preemptive or decisive reason to so act (or not to act) such that refraining from so acting would be irrational. My aim is to argue for the following: Incompatibility Thesis: (1) and (2) are incompatible; they cannot both be upheld without saying something absurd about morality. Here is my plan: In 2 and 3, I distinguish between some of the varieties of reasons internalism as well as the practical force of morality thesis briefly noting some historical and contemporary defenders of each. In 4, I give a novel argument, which I call the Argument from Justice, for why reasons internalism and the practical force of morality thesis cannot both be upheld. 2. Reasons Internalisms Reasons internalism comes in a myriad of forms. A complete taxonomy of the varieties of reasons internalism and its various associated theses is beyond the purview of this paper. Instead, I focus on (what I take to be) certain of the primary distinguishing features between kinds of reasons internalism. Reasons internalists agree that every reason for action must bear some relation to the agent s desires or motivations. Internalists disagree, however, as to whether what is required of a consideration for it to count as a reason for an agent is some fact about an agent s actual

2 motivations or some other psychological state (e.g., desire) which merely plays a role in motivation. Following Finlay and Schroeder (2008), I Call the former: motivation-based reasons internalism and the latter: state-based reasons internalism. To see the difference, it is instructive to note instances where the two could conceivably come apart. Suppose I desire a cookie but lack the motivation to get up and walk to the cookie jar. Do I have a reason get a cookie? If your answer is yes, then you are a state-based reasons internalist; my desire for a cookie (despite lack of motivation to take the steps into the kitchen to retrieve one) is sufficient to give me a reason. Suppose I am motivated to make a healthy dinner of kale and beans but have no desire to do so. Do I have a reason to cook kale and beans? If you think so, you are a motivation-based reasons internalist; my motivation to eat healthfully (despite my lack of desire to do so) is sufficient to instill me with a reason to so act. Reasons internalists also disagree as to what sort of relation there must be between an agent s reasons for action and her desires or motivations. On the one hand, an internalist might require that for an agent to have a reason to φ, she must actually be motivated (or have a desire) to φ. On the other hand, an internalist might merely require that for an agent to have a reason to φ, it must be true that she would be motivated (or have some desire) to φ given some further kinds of circumstances. Call the former sort of position actualist reasons internalism, and the latter: counterfactualist reasons internalism. To complicate things further, Counterfactualists differ as to what sorts of conditions they consider to be the relevant counterfactual circumstances for a consideration to count as a reason for an agent. A counterfactualist might think, for example, a consideration is a reason for an agent to φ just in case (i) she has all the relevant information (and no relevant false beliefs) (Smith 1994, Joyce 2001), or (ii) she has reached a state of Rawlsian reflective equilibrium (Brandt 1979), or (iii) she has deliberated without fault from her occurant motivations (Williams 1979) or (iv) she is practically rational (Korsgaard 1986), or (v) she was raised properly to be an ideal phronimos (McDowell 1995). 1 Due to considerations that will become clear in the following sections, the sort of reasons internalism I focus my discussion on is an actualist, state-based reasons internalism. The archetypical example of such an account is the view commonly attributed to Hume 2 henceforth the Humean Theory of Reasons (HTR). HTR states: if an agent has a reason to φ, then she must 1 Credit for the compilation of this list goes to Finlay & Schroeder 2008. 2 A Treatise of Human Nature, Book II, Part II, Section III

3 have some actual desire that gets served by φ-ing. 3 From here on out, HTR is the position I refer to by reasons internalism (RI). 3. The Practical Rationality of Moral Action It would be nice if what we morally ought to do were to always coincide perfectly with what it makes most sense to do: with what we have the best reasons to do. If this were the case, there would never be any tricky conflicts between choosing between the moral act and the otherwise rational act. On the face of it, however, examples seem to abound of clear instances where morally virtuous acts come at a cost to our own well-being and would, thereby, seem to be irrational for us to undertake. For example, I would be financially better off if I did not donate a percentage of my income to charity. I would have more time to myself if I were not obligated to look after my children. I could further my professional goals more quickly by lying to or taking advantage of others. Each of these is a prima facie instance where the morally virtuous act (acting charitably, benevolently, honestly, etc) appears to conflict with what would make life go best for me. Many moral philosophers have gone to great lengths to construct moral systems to overcome (or otherwise make go away) this apparent conflict between the moral and the otherwise practically rational actions we might choose to undertake. The moral philosophy of Immanuel Kant is a classic example. On Kant s view, there is a single principle from which all specific moral duties are derived: the categorical imperative (CI). Kant formulates the CI in a few different ways, but argues (somewhat dubiously) that all formulations are derivable from the formulation of the universal law: Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law. (G 4:421). For Kant, the CI is the supreme principle of practical reason. Even our hypothetical imperatives are subordinate to the CI. 4 Furthermore, Kant argues that since morality is in the realm of metaphysics, and all reasoning about metaphysics is a priori, the CI must be derivable using pure, a priori reasoning alone. What is important about Kant for our present inquiry is this: on Kant s view, there is no separating the moral act from the practically rational one. The two simply do not (and cannot) come apart. 3 It is worth noting, however, that my arguments may also apply to various versions of the counterfactualist account. 4 See Korsgaard (1997) for a detailed discussion of this.

4 A contemporary (non-kantian) example of a moral philosopher who is committed to a version of the practical rationality of moral action is Alan Gibbard. Unlike Kant, however, Gibbard is firmly rooted in the contemporary metaethical expressivism movement. Expressivism about moral language is the view, roughly, that moral statements are mere evincings of noncognitive attitudes rather than any sort of truth-evaluable claims. In his 2003 book, Thinking How to Live, Gibbard writes, Thinking what I ought to do is thinking what to do (x), and later: ought questions and reason questions are by their very nature questions of what to do. Understanding this is the way to understand what ought assertions mean. I the chooser don t face two clear, distinct questions, the question what to do and the question what I ought to do. (9-10). On Gibbard s account, there is no difference between thinking about what we ought (morally) to do and the question of what to do (in general). Ought statements do not have a special property. They are simply a species of the general question of what we have to most reason to plan to do. Derek Parfit is another recent defender of a version of (PRMA). In his 2011 book On What Matters, Parfit s argues that, if morality is to matter at all, we must always have the most reason to act morally. He, like Gibbard, distinguishes between two questions: Q1: What do I have the most reason to do? And Q2: What ought I morally to do? He then writes, Of these questions, it is the question about reasons that is wider, and more fundamental. And if these questions often had conflicting answers, because we often had decisive reasons to act wrongly, that would undermine morality. For morality to matter, we must have reasons to care about morality, and to avoid acting wrongly. (147) He then goes on to defend the following position (which he labels Q ); When some act would be [morally] wrong, this fact always gives us decisive 5 reason not to do it (173). By virtue of the fact that Parfit s Q only holds that the wrongness of an act gives us decisive reason not to do it, it might be thought of as a weaker version of (PMRA) than those formulations which claim that we always have decisive reason to act rightly. After all, unless one accepts the controversial Platonic doctrine of the unity of the virtues, there seem to be plenty of cases where different moral virtues would call for disparate courses of action. If we restrict ourselves to a version of (PRMA) like Parfit s, on the other hand, we need not deal with having decisive reasons for acting in 5 Parfit defines decisive reasons: When our reasons to do something are stronger than our reasons to do any other act, these reasons are decisive, and this act is what we have most reason to do; it is what we should, ought to, or must do (33).

5 accordance with countervailing virtues like (courage and wisdom) because we only have decisive reasons not to act wrongly. For this reason, Q seems more easily defensible. I shall, therefore, take (PRMA) to refer to Parfit s Q for the remainder of the paper. 4. An Argument for why (RI) and (PRMA) cannot both be upheld. The general point I wish to make in this section is this: (RI) and (PRMA), in their refined versions outlined above, cannot both be upheld without running into trouble. To do this, I take the subset of moral duties stemming from justice as a starting point. Why focus on justice? I focus on justice because, as we shall see, it is the virtue that most straight-forwardly seems to require us to act in ways contrary to our actual desires. As such, I call the following argument: the Argument from Justice. In schematic form, it goes like this: (1) If (RI) holds, we only have reasons to act when such reasons connect to our actual desires. (2) If (PRMA) holds, all agents (to which morality applies) have decisive reason not to act unjustly such that acting unjustly would be irrational. (3) There are plausible cases where avoiding acting unjustly requires of an agent to act contrary to anything in her desire set. (4) Given (1) and (3), if (RI) is true we do not always have a reason to refrain from acting unjustly. (5) But given (2), if (PRMA) is true we do always have a reason to refrain from acting unjustly. (6) Contradiction! (7) Therefore, (IR) and (PRMA) cannot both be upheld. Premises (1) and (2) are just the respective definitions of (RI) and (PRMA) that we stipulated in 2 and 3. Premises (3)-(6), on the other hand, require some further explanation and justification. Before offering support for the forgoing argument from justice, however, we first need to get straight as to what (precisely) justice is. Plato conceived of justice in the Republic as the overarching virtue of individuals and societies. 6 As such, justice for Plato encompassed much (if not all) of what we now think of as morality. In today s society, however, usage of the word 6 Plato, Republic, translated and with intro by R.E. Allen, New Haven: Yale University Press, 2006.

6 justice has come to take a more limited meaning; it refers to only a subset of morality. As Michael Slote puts it in his 2010 essay Justice as a Virtue, What individual justice most naturally refers to are moral issues having to do with goods or property. It is, we say, unjust for someone to steal from people or not to give them what he owes them, and it is also unjust if someone called upon to distribute something good (or bad or both) among members of a group uses an arbitrary or unjustified basis for making the distribution (this last aspect of individual justice obviously has reference to social or at least group justice). (1) By way of defending premise (3) of my argument from justice (that there are plausible cases where justice requires an agent to act contrary to anything in her desire set) I take three examples from the above quotation from Slote of paradigmatic actions prohibited by justice and show why it is easy to conceive of an agent with no desire to so act. Having done so, I will have shown that a defender of both (RI) and (PRMA) is forced into a pernicious contradiction. (i) Stealing: A college student desperately wants to impress her friends with the latest fashion in blue jeans, but for her, designer jeans are entirely unaffordable. She remembers having been told many times by her mother and father that stealing is wrong, but she finds herself utterly devoid of any desire to abide by the advice of her parents. The student furtively places the blue jeans in her bag and carries them out of the store unnoticed. (ii) Not giving people what is owed to them: Imagine, for instance, that a mega-rich family member gives you a small loan so that you could make a down-payment on that new condo you, your wife, and your young children have long wanted. But further suppose that this bourgeois family member, being a bit older and busy with his retired life of golf and contract bridge, forgets all about the loan. You know that the just act would be to repay him by the time you both agreed upon, but you never liked the guy anyway and feel zero desire to comply. He won t even notice anyway. (iii) Non-arbitrary distribution of goods: Consider a local politician who comes to discover an error in the state budget such that there is now a surplus of funding for the coming fiscal year. This politician knows that the virtue of justice would demand him to allocate this surplus money to road maintenance, new computers for local schools, more library books, or some other public good. However he finds himself with no desire to do so, and instead decides to keep the whole thing under wraps quietly allocating the money to wealthy special interest groups whose support will greatly improve his chances for reelection. What are these examples meant to show? How are they meant to support the mutual exclusivity of (RI) and (PRMA)? The point of these examples is to show plausible instances where justice requires an agent not to act in a certain way but the agent in question has no desire to refrain from so acting. In short, these examples are supposed to show that sometimes

7 agents have no desire to do what justice requires. Once it is established that cases of the sort described above are easy to imagine, the rest of the argument from justice follows. Since (RI) requires of an agent s reasons that they be connected to her desires, a reasons internalist must conclude that these imaginary agents do not have reason to refrain from acting unjustly. But (PRMA) claims that we always have decisive reason not to act wrongly. And since unjust acts are certainly a species of wrong acts, we always have decisive reason not to act unjustly. In short, a defender of (RI) says these agents do not have reasons to refrain from acting unjustly; and a defender of (PRMA) says of these agents that they must have such reasons. Thus, these are plausible examples that show the incompatibility of (RI) and (PRMA). The upshot of my argument from justice is this: anyone who wishes to be a reasons internalist and support the practical rationality of moral action runs into a problem. Namely, such a person must say of these plausible cases that the agents in the examples described above necessarily do and do not have reasons to act justly. In other words, any defender of both (RI) and (PRMA) faces a vicious contradiction. If my argument from justice is sound, therefore, it shows that reasons internalism (of the Humean sort) and the practical rationality of moral action (of the Parfitian sort) cannot both be upheld. 5. Conclusion In this paper, I have defended the incompatibility of (a certain sort of) reasons internalism and the view that moral acts are always necessitated by practical rationality. To do this, I first defined and distinguished between types of reasons internalism and the practical rationality of moral action theses. I then offered an argument from justice to show that there are plausible cases which lead defenders of both (RI) and (PRMA) to reach contradictory conclusions. I conclude, therefore, that (RI) and (PRMA) cannot both be upheld and a choice between the two positions must be made.

8 References: Brandt, R. (1979) A Theory of the Good and the Right. New York: Clarendon Press. Finlay, S. & Schroeder, M (2008) Reasons for Action: Internal vs. External http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasons-internal-external/ Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking How to Live, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Hume, D. (1739), A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by L. Selby-Bigge, 2nd revised edition by P. H. Nidditch, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975. Joyce, R. (2001) The Myth of Morality, Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1785) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, translated by T. Abbott, revised and edited by L. Denis, Peterborough: Broadview Press, 2005. Kant, I. (2002) Theoretical Philosophy after 1781, translated/edited by H. Allison, M. Friedman, G. Hatfield and P. Heath, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Korsgaard, C. (1986) Skepticism about Practical Reason. Journal of Philosophy, 83: 5-25. Korsgaard, C. (1997) The Normativity of Instrumental Reason, in Ethics and Practical Reason, G.Cullity & B.Gaut (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 215 254. McDowell, J. (1995) Might There Be External Reasons? In J.E.J. Altham & R. Harrison (eds.), World, Mind and Ethics: Essays on the Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 68-85. O Neill, O. (1989) Constructions of Reason, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Parfit, D. (2011) On What Matters. Oxford University Press. Plato, Republic, translated and with intro by R.E. Allen, New Haven: Yale University Press, 2006. Raz, J. (ed.), (1990) Authority, New York: New York University Press. Raz, J. (1975) Practical Reason and Norms, Oxford University Press. Slote, M. (2010) Justice as a Virtue http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-virtue/ Smith, M. (1994) The Moral Problem. Blackwell. Williams, B. (1979) Internal and External Reasons. Reprinted in Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981: 101-13.