KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Similar documents
PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

What is an Argument? Validity vs. Soundess of Arguments

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Humanities 4: Lectures Kant s Ethics

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

CMSI Handout 3 Courtesy of Marcello Antosh

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

(naturalistic fallacy)

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Ethical non-naturalism

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Transcendental Knowledge

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Kant's Moral Philosophy

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Varieties of Apriority

Immanuel Kant. Retirado de: (25/01/2018)

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

Introduction to Philosophy

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Philosophy Courses Fall 2016

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Minds and Machines spring The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited spring 03

Transition: From A priori To Anselm

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

IT is frequently taken for granted, both by people discussing logical

NOTE ON KANT'S GROUNDWORK, PP PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 Dick Arneson

Immanuel Kant. Great German philosophers whose influence was and continues to be immense; born in Konigsberg East Prussia, in 1724, died there in 1804

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

PHILOSOPHY (413) Chairperson: David Braden-Johnson, Ph.D.

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY

Epistemology Naturalized

Moral Psychology

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL 56. Research Integrity. 1 Unit

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

PHILOSOPHY. Chair: Karánn Durland (Fall 2018) and Mark Hébert (Spring 2019) Emeritus: Roderick Stewart

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

NOTES ON A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE 10/6/03

Peter Bornedal, General Lecture, 203. Copyright (C) by P. Bornedal

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

Kant and his Successors

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

24.09 Minds and Machines spring 2007

Transcription:

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism Metaphysics of morals Formal inquiry Pure practical reason a priori justification synthetic truth Necessary truth Moral law Moral duty A good will Kantian respect of rational creatures (whether human or otherwise). Kant s goal in the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Kant seeks to demonstrate that there are moral laws that govern our conduct in virtue of there being a foundational or first principle of morality. As he says, The present groundwork is nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality (AK 4:392). (Notice that this reveals Kant s commitment to ethical foundationalism.) What is more, Kant tells us that the focus of the Groundwork is to show that the supreme principle of morality is a necessary, synthetic a priori principle. (He calls that principle The Categorical Imperative [hereafter CI]). As we will see, Kant argues that CI is a necessary, synthetic a priori principle since it governs the actions Why does Kant think this about CI? He contends that since CI is a moral principle that legitimately binds all rational creatures (not merely creatures with specific biology), any inquiry into CI is really an investigation into the metaphysics of morals, and not, as others argue (e.g., Mill), an inquiry into practical anthropology. To make sense of this, let us consider the taxonomy of the sciences that he adopts from the ancient Greek thinkers. 1 The ancient threefold division of philosophy Physics: the study of the laws that govern the behavior of physical systems. Logic: the study of the laws that govern the thought of rational creatures. Ethics: the study of the laws that govern the action of rational creatures. Five important distinctions for understanding Kant To make the above threefold taxonomy clear and direct our attention to the relevant moral investigation, there are a number of important distinctions we need to make in order to understand Kant. An inquiry distinction: the formal material inquiry distinction Kant distinguishes two kinds of scientific inquiries: formal inquiries and material inquiries. What is the difference? A formal inquiry is an inquiry of the form of the laws that govern some entities e. A material inquiry is an inquiry of the entities the values of the variable e that are governed by the laws. 1 Notice that Kant describes the disciplines of logic and ethics as kinds of science. He does so because the term science historically (at least until the mid to late nineteenth-century) referred to any discipline that aims at developing a comprehensive theoretical understanding of one or more features of reality.

A helpful example is to consider the form content distinction from formal logic and mathematics. Consider the following example. The argument All whales are mammals All mammals are animals All whales are animals has both a form and a content (i.e., a material). Its form is the pattern of reasoning; the content is what the argument is about. The same is true of the statement if 5>4 and 4>3, then 5>3 : it s form is the schema if x > y and y > z, then x > z whereas its content (i.e., its material) are the numbers 5, 4 and 3. A reason distinction: pure vs. impure reason Pure reason: reason totally devoid of any a posteriori content. Impure reason: reason that involves some a posteriori content. An epistemological distinction: a priori vs. a posteriori (epistemic) justification Epistemology is that field of philosophical inquiry that is concerned with the nature and scope of human knowledge. As such, epistemologists seek to answer such questions as Is (human) knowledge possible? and If that knowledge is possible, what is required to have that knowledge and what kinds of things can be known? To answer such questions, we must inquire into the necessary conditions for a human being to have knowledge. One such condition is the epistemic justification condition (where a belief b is epistemically justified if there is some condition c, such that b satisfies c). What is the requisite epistemic justification condition? Although philosophers disagree about the details of that condition, they agree that condition recognizes two broad types of epistemic justification: a priori epistemic justification and a posteriori epistemic justification. But first A priori epistemic justification: a person S is epistemically justified a priori in believing that a proposition p is true only if (i) S has some justifier j for believing that p is true, and (ii) S s having j does not require that S be able to appeal to a particular sensory experience e. Putative examples of propositions that a person might be epistemically justified a priori to believe: that all red apples are red, that all Euclidean right triangles satisfy the Pythagorean Theorem (i.e., a 2 + b 2 = c 2 ), etc. A posteriori epistemic justification: a person S is epistemically justified a posteriori in believing that a proposition p is true only if (i) S has some justifier j for believing that p is true, and (ii) S s having j does require that S be able to appeal to a particular sensory experience e. Putative examples of propositions that a person might be epistemically justified a posteriori to believe: that there are more than two people in the room, that the atomic number of gold is 79, that water is H 2O, etc. A linguistic distinction: analytic vs. synthetic truth-values This is a distinction regarding what makes a sentence true, the truth-maker as it were. To be sure, the straightforward answer is that facts are the truth-makers. However, there are different kinds of facts. For simplicity, let us distinguish between linguistic and non-linguistic facts. Analytic statements are made true by the former; synthetic statements are made true by the latter.

Analytic: a statement s is analytically true only if (i) s is true and either (ii) s is true in virtue of the form of s or (iii) s is true in virtue of the predicate concept of s being contained in the subject concept of s. Putative examples of propositions that are analytically true: that red apples are red, that bachelors are unmarried, etc. Synthetic: a statement s is synthetically true only if (i) s is true and (ii) s is true in virtue of the predicate concept of s extending the subject concept of s. Putative examples of propositions that are synthetically true: that whales are mammals, that the atomic number of gold is 79, that water is H 2O, etc. A modal distinction: necessary vs. contingent truth-values In addition to the analytic synthetic distinction regarding the truth-value of a declarative sentences, the truth-value of declarative sentences is modal: i.e., it s tied to possible worlds. Some sentences have their truth-value necessarily; some sentences have their truth-value contingently. Necessary truth: a sentence s is necessarily true iff (i) s is true and (ii) there is no possible world where s is false. Putative examples of propositions that are necessarily true: that x = x, that all red apples are red, that the atomic number of gold is 79, that water is H 2O, etc. Contingent: a sentence s is contingently true iff (i) s is true and (ii) there is at least one possible world where s is false. Putative examples of propositions that are contingently true: that apples are red, that Obama is a politician, that water is in my cup, etc. 2 As noted above, Kant thinks that the search for CI again, the first principle of morality is an investigation into the metaphysics of morals (i.e., into those moral laws that permit or do not permit the actions of all rational creatures). With these distinctions, we are set to answer why he thinks that is the case. Kant argues that any inquiry that is material in nature and, hence, based on impure reason can at most teach us practical anthropology (i.e., the application of the moral laws to some particular species, e.g., human beings, hobbits, etc.). Yet, before we can know how to apply the moral laws to some species, we must first know what the moral laws are and only a formal inquiry which is based on pure reason alone is capable of providing that knowledge. As such, we can see that Kant is offering the following argument: Kant s argument for the a prioricity of moral duties 1. In order for a law of morality to specify an actual/genuine moral obligation (i.e., what I actually morally ought to do), it must be absolutely true in all cases. 2. If a law of morality is to be absolutely true in all cases, we cannot discover it by observing either the way human beings behave (i.e., it is not a empirical fact about human psychology), or the kind of situations we find ourselves in (i.e., it is not a social empirical fact). 2 Note that the same can be stated for falsity. Necessarily false sentences are false in all possible worlds; contingently false sentences are false in some, but not all possible worlds.

Hence, 3. An actual law of morality cannot be sought a posteriori (that is, in empirical facts) via impure reason. 4. Anything not sought a posteriori must be sought a priori. 5. We must seek an actual law of morality a priori. 6. Given (5), an actual law of morality is sought via pure reason. Accordingly, 7. Since all inquiries via pure reason are formal inquiries, ethics is a formal inquiry. 8. Since ethics is a formal inquiry, it is an investigation into the metaphysics of morals. The good will According to Kant, the only thing that is unconditionally good is the good will. As he says, It is impossible to think of anything at all in the world, or indeed beyond it, that could be considered good without limitation except a good will (AK 4:393). Three important questions: A. What is the will? B. Why aren t there other things that are good without limitation (i.e., unconditionally good)? C. What makes a good will just that, good? Kant s answer to Question A: on the nature of the will According to Kant, the will is an autonomous, i.e., self-legislating, faculty of volition only had by rational creatures, that is, the faculty that makes plans and decisions to do (or refrain from doing) certain acts, and it is upon those plans and decisions that rational creatures act. 3 (One part of) Kant s answer to Question B: The Bad Use Argument (1) x is an unconditional good iff x can neither be immorally acquired nor used for bad. (2) Happiness can immorally acquired. (3) The virtues (i.e., knowledge, courage, etc.) can be used for bad. Thus, (4) Neither happiness nor the virtues are unconditional goods. (5) The good will can neither be immorally acquired nor used for bad. (6) The good will is an unconditional good. (7) There are no other candidates for unconditional goods. Hence, (8) The good will is the only unconditional good. 3 Note that (i) the word intention is another term used to refer to the plans and decisions to do (or refrain from doing) certain acts, and (ii) Kant often uses the term humanity as another reference to persons/rational creatures.

On Kant s answer to Question C: The Shopkeeper examples and two (more) important distinctions On two kinds of actions: actions done in conformity with duty vs. actions done from duty On two possible ways to read Kant s theory of appropriate motives: actualism vs. counterfactualism Actualism: according to this reading of Kant, a person S s action A has moral worth iff (i) S recognizes that A is her duty and (ii) S does A in the absence of any inclination to do A (and perhaps in the presence of an inclination not to do A). Counterfactualism: according to this reading of Kant, a person S s action A has moral worth iff (i) S recognizes that A is her duty and (ii) either S has no inclination to do A or S does have an inclination to do A, but (iii) S would have performed A even if she had no such inclination. Respect for the moral law According to Kant, actions that are done from duty i.e., out of respect for the moral law derive their moral worth from the maxim that leads a person to try to perform them. We ll say shortly what exactly makes a maxim a right maxim. For now, the point is that our actions have moral worth if the maxim satisfies the relevant criteria for being a right maxim; they do not derive their worth from (a) successful completion of the action or (b) from obtaining any desired end. With those details before us, we can understand the basic nature of Kant s deontological theory via the following argument: (A) (B) (C) (D) An action A is morally right only if A was done from a good will. An action A was done from a good will only if A was done from duty. An action A was done from duty only if A was done from a respect for the moral law (i.e., for no other reason than it was the morally right thing to do). An action A was done from a respect for the moral law only if A is permitted by The Categorical Imperative. (E) An action A is morally right only if A is permitted by The Categorical Imperative. 4 4 2012, Richard G. Graziano. All rights reserved. This material may not be used, or duplicated in part or whole without express written permission by the author.