Mohammed Rustom a a Carleton University. Available online: 28 Feb 2012

Similar documents
To link to this article:

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

Contradicting Realities, déjà vu in Tehran

Self-Awareness in Islamic Philosophy: Avicenna and Beyond. By JARI KAUKUA. Cambridge:

In defence of the Simplicity Argument E. J. Lowe a a

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

To link to this article:

Alastair Norcross a a Department of Philosophy, University of Colorado at Boulder,

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Rosetta E. Ross a a Spelman College, Atlanta, Georgia, USA. To link to this article:

From Aristotle s Ousia to Ibn Sina s Jawhar

Review of The use of bodies by Giorgio Agamben, translated by Adam Kotsko

Introduction: Discussion:

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Jewish and Muslim Thinkers in the Islamic World: Three Parallels. Peter Adamson (LMU Munich)

An Analysis of the Proofs for the Principality of the Creation of Existence in the Transcendent Philosophy of Mulla Sadra

Book Review: From Plato to Jesus By C. Marvin Pate. Submitted by: Brian A. Schulz. A paper. submitted in partial fulfillment

Development of Soul Through Contemplation and Action Seen from the Viewpoint of lslamic Philosophers and Gnostics

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

The Illuminationist Philosophy. Author: Hossein Ziai - Introduction of his book Hikmat al-ishraq, The Philosophy of Illumination

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Individual Essences in Avicenna s Metaphysics

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Mulla Sadra s Theory of Perception. Afifeh Hamedi

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Survey of Mulla Sadra's Interdisciplinary Approach to Ontological and Epistemological Issues

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

Could i conceive being a brain in a vat? John D. Collier a a

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Heidegger s Interpretation of Kant

Dressing after Dressing: Sadra s Interpretation of Change

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Daniel Lapsley a & Darcia Narvaez a a University of Notre Dame, USA. Available online: 18 Oct 2011

CRITICAL REVIEW OF AVICENNA S THEORY OF PROPHECY

AN INTRODUCTION TO THE SPIRIT OF ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

From Being to Energy-Being: An Emerging Metaphysical Macroparadigm Shift in Western Philosophy. Preface

Heidegger Introduction

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

PHILOSOPHY AS THE HANDMAID OF RELIGION LECTURE 2/ PHI. OF THEO.

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Book Reviews. The Metaphysics of Relations, by Anna Marmodoro and David Yates. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016, 304 pages, ISBN:

Sep. 1 Wed Introduction to the Middle Ages Dates; major thinkers; and historical context The nature of scripture (Revelation) and reason

Encyclopedia of Animal Rights and Animal Welfare Andrew Johnson Published online: 04 Jun 2010.

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Metaphysics by Aristotle

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Tuesday 1-3, Wednesday 1-3, and by appointment

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Book Reviews. Rahim Acar, Marmara University

An Improvisation on Margaret Barker s The Lord Is One

Islamic political philosophy: prophecy, revelation, and the divine law

A Review of Norm Geisler's Prolegomena

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

1. FROM ORIENTALISM TO AQUINAS?: APPROACHING ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY FROM WITHIN THE WESTERN THOUGHT SPACE

PL 407 HISTORY OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY Spring 2012

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

Practical Wisdom and Politics

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

IJBPAS, June, 2015, 4(6): REASON AND ITS EPISTEMOLOGY IN AVICENNA S PERSPECTIVE

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

On Phronetic Political Judgement

Creativity of Spirit in Philosophical System of Mulla Sadra

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

SUBSISTENCE DEMYSTIFIED. Arnold Cusmariu

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

A note: Ibn Sīnā on the subject of logic

1. What arguments does Socrates use in Plato s Republic to show that justice is to be preferred over injustice?

Rorty on Language and Social Practices

The British Empiricism

Metaphysical Dependence and Set Theory

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

Transcription:

This article was downloaded by: [University of Toronto Libraries] On: 28 February 2012, At: 08:43 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Iranian Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cist20 Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy: Mullā Ṣadrā on Existence, Intellect, and Intuition Mohammed Rustom a a Carleton University Available online: 28 Feb 2012 To cite this article: Mohammed Rustom (2012): Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy: Mullā Ṣadrā on Existence, Intellect, and Intuition, Iranian Studies, 45:3, 457-461 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00210862.2012.655066 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.

Reviews 457 Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy: Mullā Sạdrā on Existence, Intellect, and Intuition, Ibrahim Kalin, New York: Oxford University Press, 2010, ISBN 978-0-19-973524-2, xxii + 315 pp. Ibrahim Kalin s Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy is an investigation into the epistemology of the famous Safavid philosopher Mullā Sạdrā Shīrāzī (d. 1640). Such a study is an event in itself, owing to the fact that although there are some twenty books on various aspects of Sạdrā s thought in European languages, this wideranging dimension of his philosophy has not received the attention it rightly deserves. Kalin approaches Sạdrā s theory of knowledge through a detailed analysis of his treatment of a particular issue in the history of philosophy, namely the problem dealing with the unification of the intellector and the intelligible (ittih ād al-ʿāqil wa-lmaʿqūl). The significance of this question may seem unclear at first blush. Why would there be a problem with respect to the unification or unity between the knower and the known (or subject and object) in the first place? What is essentially at stake is this: how do we know the things around us, that is, everything under the sun? As Aristotle states, and which has many profound cognates in other religious and philosophical traditions east of the Mediterranean, only the like can know the like. Yet what makes this possible? Do we come to know things simply by looking at them with the resultant effect that they then become stamped onto our minds such that we have them as mental objects? Or do we come to know them in some other fashion, seeing as it is that not all things that we can know function like stamps upon our minds? Knowledge of pain, for example, is a kind of knowing which is not limited to mental impressions only. There is an experience in this case from which a particular kind of knowledge ensues, and one which is different than just having an image in the mind or grasping some kind of concept. Whichever side of the fence we fall on over this issue, what is clear is that there is a fundamental problem vis-à-vis the knowing subject and her object of knowledge how can she know anything unless there is some kind of intimate relationship that already exists between the knower and the thing known? We cannot know, for example, things that stand outside of our scope of experience and frame of reference.

458 Reviews We thus lose our ignorance of particular things the more we become acquainted with them, which implies a process of familiarization. Kalin begins his inquiry by drawing attention to the range of possible influences upon Sạdrā s understanding of the unification problem. He rightly calls attention to some of Sạdrā s likely but unacknowledged sources, amongst both the Sufis and Muslim philosophers. With respect to the latter, Kalin invokes the name of Afdạl al-dīn Kāshānī (commonly known as Bābā Afdạl), who is still not as well-known to students of Islamic philosophy as he should be. It is indeed very likely that Bābā Afdạl influenced Sạdrā on this question, especially since Bābā Afdạl explicitly treats the topic in a letter to one of his students, and Sạdrā is known to have freely drawn upon his Persian work, Jāwidān-nāma, in writing his own Arabic treatise, Iksīr al-ʿārifīn. With respect to Sạdrā s unacknowledged Sufi sources, we have, as is well-known, two very likely candidates: Ibn ʿArabī and Sạdr al-dīn Qūnawī. Kalin does not venture into these sources here, but instead leaves readers with some key references and passages in these authors writings which may have influenced Sạdrā s thinking in one way or another. Kalin is wise to avoid venturing too far into this issue, since Sạdrā s solution to the unification problem is formed in direct engagement with the Islamic philosophical tradition proper. At the same time, any possible direct Sufi influences upon Sạdrā tend to become veiled in the language of philosophy, thus obscuring the point at hand even further. Where Sạdrā explicitly engages his Sufi predecessors is on those questions which he felt were not dealt with adequately in Islamic philosophy and theology, particularly on issues pertaining to eschatology. Yet these important Sufi influences do resurface in the practical dimension of Sạdrā s epistemology, as Kalin intimates and goes on to address in the book s third and final chapter. Kalin devotes the remainder of the first chapter to charting the different forms that the unification problem has assumed in various historical, cultural, and philosophical/ religious guises and contexts. This is a very useful exercise in historical scholarship since it gives us a window into the evolution and even distortions (often deliberate) of a major epistemological concept from antiquity into the medieval period. It also shows us how incredibly learned Sạdrā is, and how he reads history to its detriment and his advantage. Kalin moves from Plato (where the unification question is arguably addressed) to Aristotle, where he shows how the unification problem relates to Aristotle s understanding of the active intellect, a doctrine posited by Aristotle to account for the gap in his epistemology introduced by his rejection of the objective, intelligible existence of the Platonic Forms (and hence the introduction of the language of abstraction in Aristotelian epistemology, which was so influential on Islamic philosophy s Peripatetic and Illuminationist traditions) (pp. 14 15). Kalin s discussion of the views of the important commentator upon Aristotle, Alexander of Aphrodisias, who is explicitly discussed by Sạdrā with respect to the unification question (p. 17), is cogent and to the point. The treatment of Plotinus which follows is particularly helpful, since it sets the stage for the mainstream Islamic philosophical engagement with the unification problem, as it was largely through the so-

Reviews 459 called Theology of Aristotle that these discussions were broached in Islamic philosophical circles. Since Kalin s concern is to focus on the issue as articulated by Sạdrā, he limits his presentation of this aspect of the Theology as it appears in Sạdrā s own works (pp. 26 7). Along the way, Kalin observes how Sạdrā avoids two issues in Plotinus on account of the fact that they had no role to play in his own thought in particular, and the later Islamic philosophical tradition in general emanation and the composite nature of the divine intellect (p. 27). Kalin then turns to al-kindī, as he was the first Muslim philosopher to write a treatise on the intellect. Kindī introduces a kind of perspectivalism here: the soul as intelligible substance is one with the first intellect (the sum total of all things that are intelligible) from its own perspective, but not from the perspective of the first intellect, since nothing can unite with it. Kalin then demonstrates how Sạdrā manages to manipulate some of Fārābī s statements about the nature of the intellect and intellection, having his predecessor say that the human intellect is also potentially a simple active intellect (ʿaql basīt faʿʿāl) (p. 45), meaning that it can unite with the divine intellect, here understood as God (although Fārābī is somewhat vague on this idea) (p. 46). Next, Kalin moves to the refutation of the unification argument in Ibn Sīnā, who is its strongest opponent in Islamic philosophy. Ibn Sīnā refutes the problem on logical grounds, stating that two separate things cannot be united by the act of intellection since their own individual substances cannot fundamentally change, owing to the fact that they are two different entities. Also, he argues that if two substances conjoin, then a third thing would come about as a result of their union (p. 48). As Kalin observes, Sạdrā s major problem with Ibn Sīnā s rejection of unification between knower and known was the result of his univocal ontology, since it does not permit any kind of graded nature to existence in terms of its intensification or diminution in existence (p. 51). Kalin dedicates the remainder of the book s first chapter to Suhrawardī, the one figure whose metaphysics and epistemology would seem to lend themselves to a unificationist reading, but who, surprisingly, and no doubt frustratingly for Sạdrā, sides with the mainline of Peripatetic thinkers in their rejection of the unification argument. At best, Suhrawardī says that we can speak of conjunction, admixture, and unitive composition, but not unification as such. Sạdrā is astonished by the lack of concern his eminent predecessor has for the problem, and again notes that the problem here is one of an imperfect ontology (p. 65). How, then, does Sạdrā recommend his view over and against the denial of his illustrious predecessors? He does this by arguing for the fluid nature of the physical world, which is the consequence of his ontology. His fundamental ontological stance, discussed in detail by Kalin in chapter 2 (pp. 96 102), is that although existence is one, its reality is graded and multi-level through its varying degrees of intensity and diminution. Like all things, knowledge, knowing, and intellection are bound up in existence and are the result of its graded nature. Knowledge therefore is a mode of existence. It is indeed clear what Sạdrā would have said to his contemporary, Descartes. It is not I think, therefore I am. Rather, it is I am, therefore I think. If knowing is an accident of ontology, then the very act of knowing is predicated upon the reality of existence, of which knowledge is a mode.

460 Reviews At the same time, Sạdrā also demonstrates how knowledge is mysteriously linked with existence in a way quite unlike any of its others modes: both existence and knowledge pervade all things, and both are, in themselves, indefinable since they form the basis for any definitions put forth which attempt to encompass them (pp. 103 4). An existent person, in other words, cannot define existence, much less encompass it in its entirety, precisely because he is himself an instantiation of existence, and his very existence itself assumes existence. Thus the part cannot define the whole of which it is a part. Knowledge, likewise, behaves in the same way. A person cannot define knowledge, since whatever definition he puts forward for knowledge will itself be part of a much larger whole, of which the knowing subject is himself a part. Knowledge therefore is evasive, like existence. Yet since existence is the ground of all reality, even knowledge falls under its purview. To truly know a thing, the unification argument tells us, at the very moment of knowing, in the act itself, there is a kind of dissolving of barriers between the object of knowledge and the knower, making knowledge possible. It is to the extent that there is a unity between subject and object that knowledge of the object is greater or lesser. This is indeed a far cry from what we know as epistemology today, and this is because of the lack of an ontology which undergirds our notions of knowledge, the self, and the world about us (cf. pp. 195 7). Yet for Sạdrā any act of knowing itself entails, first and foremost, a thorough metaphysics in which the question of existence occupies centre-stage. Existence and knowledge therefore meet in the act of unification between subject and object. As Kalin demonstrates in chapter 3, knowledge ultimately is not a kind of representation for Sạdrā, but in fact an experience, and at its highest reaches leads to nothing other than finding, witnessing, and being present with God (pp. 227 45) it is important to recall here the two-fold meaning of wujūd as existence and finding. Sạdrā s understanding of the unification argument leads him to exposit a kind of participatory way of knowing between subject and object, but one which tends to blur the distinction between the act of knowing and the act of existence, and, by extension, the knower and the known. This, for Sạdrā, lies at the heart of the very problem of knowledge, which is the problem of existence: to be is to know, and to know is to be. Kalin points out that a key aspect of Sạdrā s epistemology is his modification of Suhrawardī s famous thesis of knowledge by presence against the backdrop of his own dynamic metaphysics. Since God s existence and knowledge are the same reality, all things, Sạdrā says, are present with Him. And this presence of things is nothing other than their existence. Kalin reminds us that one of the significant similarities between Plotinus and Sạdrā is the notion that Divine intellection implies ontological production (p. 33). This is why, for Sạdrā, God s knowing something itself entails the existentiation of that particular thing. Thus, the things that exist are known to God by virtue of His presence with them, which means that they are nothing other than God s knowledge of them. On the human side of the equation, the act of knowing is intimately tied to the existential state of the knowing subject who, by virtue of knowing, is first and foremost characterized by existence. So the more intense our knowledge, the more intense is our

Reviews 461 existence. The act of knowing, in other words, becomes a process in becoming more real. And since God s knowledge of us is our very existence, the more we come to know ourselves, the more we come to know our reality, as our realities are nothing other than God s presence with us. This is tantamount to saying that to know ourselves is to know ourselves as God knows us. Knowing subjects, by virtue of where they stand on the scale of existence, are less ignorant or more ignorant. But since the possibility exists for them to unite with the active intellect and ultimately God as the object of intellection, their attempt to know is intimately connected to their everyday lives, which are grounded in existence. Hence living, existing, and carrying out the spiritual life to its logical end become means of gaining knowledge and becoming more real and less ignorant and unreal, with the net effect that the fruit of knowledge is nothing other than knowing the nature of things. This is why things like uncertainty, doubt, and ignorance no longer apply to the realized knower. For such a person, the nature of things is grasped, which is to see things as God sees them, or, in more philosophical language, to be a simple intellect in act which perceives all things, and which is all things. Appended to the book (pp. 256 91) is a thorough, annotated translation of Sạdrā s main text on the unification argument, the Treatise on the Unification of the Intellector and the Intelligible (al-risāla fī ittih ād al-ʿāqil wa-l-maʿqūl). The translation is smoothflowing and accurate, both in terms of its rendering of technical terms and its interpretation of the Arabic text. Here Sạdrā s arguments in support of the unification position are presented without the detailed historical and interpretive apparatus that we find in the book s preceding chapters. This allows the argument as Sạdrā presents it to unfold in seamless fashion, which is best made sense of when consulting Kalin s meticulous notes to the translation (where many other relevant passages from Sạdrā s oeuvre are translated in order to shed light on the issues raised in the translated text). There is no doubt that this is a remarkably learned book. Not only is Kalin s writing clear, but he is also able to convey what is at stake in Sạdrā s epistemology without sacrificing textual accuracy on the one hand, and philosophical depth on the other. At the same time, the book also attempts to bring Sạdrā s insights into conversation with some of the more significant philosophers of modern Western philosophy, ranging from Descartes and Kant to Heidegger and Taylor. Suffice it to say, Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy is an excellent contribution to the rapidly-growing field of Sạdrā studies, and is sure to set the bar very high for the kind of historical range, philosophical rigour, and even mystical sensitivity demanded by any serious engagement with Mullā Sạdrā s thought. Mohammed Rustom Carleton University Mohammed Rustom 2012 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00210862.2012.655066