Reply to Gabriel Stolzenberg

Similar documents
Review of Who Rules in Science?, by James Robert Brown

REVIEW. Kinder, Gentler Science Wars. Gabriel Stolzenberg

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

ACCOUNT OF SOCIAL ONTOLOGY DURKHEIM S RELATIONAL DANIEL SAUNDERS. Durkheim s Social Ontology

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Introduction The Science Wars in Perspective

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

what makes reasons sufficient?

5 A Modal Version of the

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Kelly James Clark and Raymond VanArragon (eds.), Evidence and Religious Belief, Oxford UP, 2011, 240pp., $65.00 (hbk), ISBN

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Oxford University Press and The Analysis Committee are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Analysis.

Naturalism and is Opponents

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

Plantinga, Van Till, and McMullin. 1. What is the conflict Plantinga proposes to address in this essay? ( )

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

The Arguments for Determinism. Herman H. Horne

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice Andrés Perea Excerpt More information

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Strange bedfellows or Siamese twins? The search for the sacred in practical theology and psychology of religion

2014 Examination Report 2014 Extended Investigation GA 2: Critical Thinking Test GENERAL COMMENTS

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Temperate Rationalism: An Option for the Methodology and Understanding of Scientific Enterprise

Action in Special Contexts

Cartesian Rationalism

Horwich and the Liar

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

NORMATIVITY WITHOUT NORMATIVISM 1

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

What God Could Have Made

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Are There Moral Facts

A Priori Bootstrapping

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

Lectures on S tmcture and Significance of Science

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

THE QUESTION OF "UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY?" IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS

The Advancement: A Book Review

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

CAUSATION 1 THE BASICS OF CAUSATION

Realism and instrumentalism

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Tara Smith s Ayn Rand s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution to the Literature on Objectivism?

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Evidence and Transcendence

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

Transcription:

Reply to Gabriel Stolzenberg Jean Bricmont and Alan Sokal Gabriel Stolzenberg s (2004) review of The One Culture (Labinger & Collins, 2001) makes some incisive observations concerning the Strong Programme, which merit further discussion. It is a pity, therefore, that he mars his essay with snide comments about philosopher Paul Boghossian ( had he not been doing his Ken Starr imitation ) and ironically in the light of his focus on misreading tendentious misrepresentations of our own views. Let us, therefore, deal quickly with the latter, before addressing more substantive questions. Referring to our views on the Strong Programme, Stolzenberg asserts (p. 79) baldly that we wish to see it dead. This is a pure invention on Stolzenberg s part, without the slightest basis in what we have written. 1 Indeed, we are perplexed as to why Stolzenberg would choose to describe an intellectual debate in such emotion-laden (not to say militaristic) terms. 2 Quite simply, we think that some aspects of the Strong Programme are epistemologically and methodologically misguided; our essay in The One Culture was devoted to explaining our objections and the reasons behind them. Stolzenberg also accuses us of misreading a second-round comment of Jane Gregory s. We think that Stolzenberg s accusation is unjustified; but since the point at issue is relatively minor a comment made in passing on the way to discussing the central question raised by Gregory we leave the reader to judge for herself. 3 Stolzenberg cites (p. 80) approvingly Michael Lynch s thoughtful analyses of pop metaphysical one-liners by Sokal, Weinberg and Richard Dawkins. But he does not ask why Lynch chose to analyse a one-liner taken from a three-page polemical article, rather than the 56-page book chapter devoted to a detailed analysis of questions from the philosophy of science. 4 Finally, Stolzenberg takes us to task for prefacing a statement with the words it seems obvious that ; he claims that we give no argument in favour of the assertion in question, and he concludes by asking sarcastically: Is this the kind of scholarship that they and their admirers favor? But Social Studies of Science 34/1(February 2004) 107 113 SSS and SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks CA, New Delhi) ISSN 0306-3127 DOI: 10.1177/0306312704040491 www.sagepublications.com

108 Social Studies of Science 34/1 Stolzenberg carefully omits to mention the sentence immediately following the one he quoted, which is devoted precisely to giving an argument in support of the preceding assertion. Is this the kind of scholarship that Stolzenberg favours? 5 Let us now proceed to discuss Stolzenberg s very interesting comments concerning the Strong Programme. The central aim of the Strong Programme, as set forth by David Bloor and others, is to give a causal account of the acceptance of scientific ideas, while remaining impartial (or symmetrical ) as to whether they are true or false, rational or irrational. 6 The controversy over the Strong Programme, as we point out, arises in part from ambiguity about how the symmetry and impartiality theses are to be understood. We illustrate the problem with two examples (cited by Stolzenberg), one from everyday life and the other from the history of physics. Stolzenberg (pp. 81 82) comments that: In each of these statements, Bricmont and Sokal claim that the truth of a certain belief is a partial cause of its acceptance. However... it does not follow, logically, from this alone that an adequate explanation of the acceptance of this belief must include its truth as a partial cause. To reach that conclusion, one must also assume that every adequate explanation of it must contain all of its partial causes. But it is implausible that a finite explanation of an event or phenomenon could contain all its partial causes... Indeed, in their first example, they omit the many partial causes of the fact that it is raining today [such as the antecedent atmospheric conditions (J.B./A.S.)]... We agree with Stolzenberg s comment, but would like to amplify it slightly, by observing that much of the apparent controversy stems in fact from differing notions of what it means for an explanation to be adequate. Philosophers of science have extensively discussed the notion of explanation, and it is not our purpose to enter into that debate here. Suffice it to say that when one explains a fact (or alleged fact) A, it is always with reference to some other set of facts (or alleged facts) B, which are temporarily taken for granted for the purposes of the argument. 7 The idea, roughly speaking, is that we explain surprising facts in terms of unsurprising (or less surprising) ones, complicated facts in terms of simpler ones, etc. Note also that many aspects of B, and of the claimed link between B and A, inevitably remain implicit, being taken for granted by both speaker and listener (at least until someone demands that they be made explicit and subjected to questioning). Thus, when someone asks, Why did the United States and Britain invade Iraq? and we reply, In part to control Iraq s oil resources, we take for granted the knowledge that Iraq possesses vast oil resources, that the western world consumes far more oil than it produces, that countries sometimes invade other countries in order to exploit their economic resources, etc. The key point, however, is that there is no natural end to the explanatory process. Having explained A in terms of some simpler facts B, one can then ask to explain B in terms of some yet simpler facts C, and so on.

Bricmont & Sokal: Reply to Gabriel Stolzenberg 109 Indeed, one characteristic of modern science is precisely to demand deeper and deeper levels of explanation, in which the facts taken for granted are both fewer and (in some sense) simpler or more fundamental. 8 Furthermore, how far one wishes to push the chain of explanation or, conversely, at what point one considers the explanation to be adequate depends strongly on the interests (in both senses of the word) of the inquirer. Thus, when an evolutionary biologist explains the rise in drugresistant tuberculosis as an effect of natural selection, a molecular biologist will naturally want to know the details of the mutations that rendered the tuberculosis bacilli resistant to particular antibiotics. When a chemist explains a reaction in terms of oxidation and reduction, a physicist will naturally seek a more fundamental explanation in terms of quantum mechanics and electrodynamics. Let us stress that these different levels of explanation are complementary, not contradictory. But they are not equally adequate ; rather, they stand in a relation of hierarchy, in which the deeper explanation subsumes and extends the less deep one. Thus, it is perfectly legitimate to explain A in terms of some simpler facts B, and stop there; but if someone explains A in terms of B, and then goes on to explain B in terms of some yet simpler (or more fundamental) facts C, this is in an important sense a better explanation. (How much better depends on the details of the case at hand, as well as on the purposes for which the explanation is sought.) With these considerations in mind, let us now turn to the Strong Programme, and in particular to one of the concrete examples raised in our article: why did the European scientific community become convinced of the truth of Newtonian mechanics sometime between 1700 and 1750? Advocates of the Strong Programme are correct to claim that, at least in principle, one can provide a complete explanation of the acceptance of Newtonian mechanics by 18th-century scientists without ever referring to the actual motion of the planets it suffices to refer to the observations concerning planetary motion that were available to scientists of the time. Furthermore, in order to explain the beliefs of those scientists who did not personally make observations of planetary motion, it is not even necessary to refer to those observations; it suffices to refer to the published articles and books, public lectures and private conversations, and so on, through which all their knowledge of planetary motions was acquired. 9 In this narrow sense, therefore, Strong Programmers can validly contend that it is possible to provide a complete explanation of the acceptance of Newtonian mechanics that makes reference only to social factors. 10 But the unsatisfying nature of such a purely social explanation should be manifest. If one aims to explain scientist X s belief in some theory, one can, if one wishes, answer because Y and Z published papers purporting to give strong experimental evidence in favor of that theory, and stop there; but it is not natural to stop there. One would quite reasonably want to know, Why did Y and Z publish papers purporting to give experimental evidence E? And the answer might be, Because Y and Z performed experiments whose results were E, and they are honest and conscientious

110 Social Studies of Science 34/1 scientists. (Or the answer might alternatively be, Because Y and Z, though their experiments gave results quite different from E, believed that they could attain fame or fortune by publishing papers purporting to find E. The correct answer is, in each concrete case, an empirical question of history and sociology.) Nor is it natural to stop there: if Y and Z performed experiments whose results were E, one would quite reasonably want to know, Why did Y and Z s experiments yield result E? And the answer might be, Because E is at least approximately the way the world is. (Or it might alternatively be, Because Y and Z s experiments were afflicted with a systematic error that led them to mistakenly observe E. This is once again an empirical question, which can be investigated by attempting to replicate the experiments, by carrying out related experiments, by investigating the internal consistency of Y and Z s data, and so on.) It is in this sense a limited sense, to be sure, but a crucial one in our opinion that we contend that any truly adequate explanation for the acceptance of Newtonian mechanics must include, as one element, the fact that the planets and comets really do move (to a very high degree of approximation, though not exactly) as predicted by Newtonian mechanics. 11 Stolzenberg (p. 82) makes one other criticism of our view. He says: Bricmont and Sokal explain that they have in mind cases in which the truth of a belief is a partial cause of what is recognized to be evidence for it. On first sight, this may seem promising: the truth helps make there be evidence and observation of the evidence helps make us believe. But to carry this out in any case, one must show that the fact that it is evidence, which is a state of the world, is a partial cause of the belief that it is evidence, which is a state of mind. So far so good; but Stolzenberg then goes on to assert that: Not only do Bricmont and Sokal fail to do this, they write in a way that conflates the two states, if not in their minds, at least in their words. Not true! Far from conflating evidence with belief, we explicitly observe even in the trivial example of a person standing in the rain who says it is raining today that no one today knows the complete details of the causal mechanisms that lead a person standing in the rain to believe he is standing in the rain. And it goes without saying that, in the case of scientific theories, the relation between evidence and belief is yet more complicated; many issues in the history of science revolve around precisely this question. Stolzenberg (p. 82) also points out that: because of my past experience, whenever one side of a sheep looks white to me, I believe that the sheep is white. So, when it is white, my belief is true. Yet the fact that it is true seems to play no role in making me believe it. Well, yes and no. The first question one should ask is, why is it that whenever one side of a sheep looks white to me, I believe that the sheep is white? And the answer is of course that in the past I have seen both sides of

Bricmont & Sokal: Reply to Gabriel Stolzenberg 111 a large number of sheep, and they were unfailingly monochrome; moreover, I possess a brain that is predisposed to make inductive inferences in certain circumstances these facts together explain my propensity to believe that sheep observed to be white on one side are in fact fully white. Furthermore, the biology of sheep is stable over short periods of time, so if in my youth all (or nearly all) sheep were monochrome, the same is likely to be true today; the whiteness of the sheep today is thus causally correlated with the facts that led me to believe, decades ago, that when one side of a sheep is white, the other side is probably white too. The reply that Stolzenberg (p. 82) concocts on our behalf ( Bricmont and Sokal might say... ) misses the main point. Stolzenberg concludes his review by noting that participants in this debate are divided by two radically different conceptions of reasoning : a purely descriptive one, about how people reason, to be used in studying the acquisition of scientific beliefs, and a normative one, about how to reason correctly, to be used in seeking scientific knowledge. (p. 86) According to Stolzenberg, these are incommensurable mindsets. But in our view, the divide is rather more banal. For there is no incompatibility whatsoever between descriptive and normative investigations of an issue, provided that one takes care to distinguish the two. Indeed, we all use both types of analysis in our everyday life. 12 Philosophers may be more interested in normative analyses, and sociologists in descriptive analyses; but this is no excuse for philosophers to make errors of sociological description, or for sociologists to make errors of logic. Notes 1. It is telling that Stolzenberg does not cite even a single word from our text in support of this characterization of our alleged attitudes, even though he does quote extensively from our essay when discussing the content of the Strong Programme. 2. The strongest emotion mentioned in our own text is irritation at the proliferation of sloppy relativist ideas (of which we cite five examples from prominent Science Studies practitioners). 3. Gregory writes (p. 202): In science, replications, peer-review and publication in Nature are usually good enough: the end-product is usually well on its way to becoming what Bricmont and Sokal might call reality or truth. We reply (p. 251): To begin with, this grossly misunderstands what we mean by truth : as we explained at length in our essay, truth signifies for us correspondence with reality ; it thus makes no sense to say that an assertion becomes true through replication, peer-review and publication. But more importantly, while replications, peer-review and publication in Nature can constitute evidence (sometimes strong evidence) for the truth of a scientific claim, they are by no means conclusive... and we then proceed to discuss at length the specific case cited by Gregory, namely Jacques Benveniste s claims concerning the alleged memory of water. Stolzenberg, in citing Gregory s sentence, appends to it the phrase i.e., to becoming accepted by them as true ; but this reformulation is Stolzenberg s, not Gregory s. Indeed, our own second

112 Social Studies of Science 34/1 sentence provides a charitable reinterpretation of Gregory s sentence along lines similar to Stolzenberg s, by referring to evidence. 4. The one-liner analysed by Lynch appears in the article in which Sokal reveals his Social Text parody (Sokal, 1996). The book chapter not mentioned by Lynch is Sokal & Bricmont (1998: chap. 4). For further elaboration of our philosophical views, see Bricmont & Sokal (2004). 5. We do think, nevertheless, that our discussion of the issue in question was too brief; we will amplify it later. 6. See for example, Bloor (1991: 7, quoted on p. 39 of our article). See also Barnes & Bloor (1981: 21 47). 7. We refrain from discussing in detail here the nature of the claimed relation between B and A. In some cases it might be B logically implies A ; but in other cases it might be, for example, the conditional probability of A given B is (vastly) higher than the conditional probability of A given not-b, or some other type of evidential relation. 8. For an excellent illustration of the demand for deeper levels of explanation, see Weinberg (1992: chapter II). 9. Note for mathematicians: we like to think of this as the Markov property in the sociology of science by analogy with the Markov property in probability theory, according to which (for a certain class of stochastic processes called Markov processes) the past affects the future only through the present, or the exterior of a region affects the interior only through the boundary. 10. It is important to stress that we are here using the word social in an extremely wide sense; indeed, the social factors at issue here are merely the social encodings of the scientific evidence. By contrast, Strong Programmers, in their practice, often interpret social in a much narrower sense, referring primarily to professional and class interests, struggles for power and prestige, and so on. We emphasize that analyses restricted to causal factors of this latter kind are not necessarily valid, as they may omit important causes (notably the scientific evidence). 11. See also footnote 31 of our article (pp. 40 41) in which we make this assertion more precise. 12. See, for example, Linda Feldmann (2003: 2), in which the journalist attempts to analyse why 45 % of US citizens believe that Saddam Hussein was personally involved in the 11 September attacks, even though there is no credible evidence to support this belief. For a more detailed recent study, see Steven Kull et al. (2003). References Barnes, Barry & David Bloor (1981) Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowledge, in Martin Hollis & Steven Lukes, eds, Rationality and Relativism (Oxford: Blackwell): 21 47. Bloor, David (1991) Knowledge and Social Imagery, 2nd edn (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press). Bricmont, J. & Alan Sokal (2004) Defense of a Modest Scientific Realism, in Proceedings of the Bielefeld ZiF Conference in Welt und Wissen Monde et Savoir World and Knowledge (in the Press, Springer-Verlag). Feldmann, Linda (2003) The Impact of Bush Linking 9/11 and Iraq, Christian Science Monitor, 14 March: 2. Kull, Steven et al. (2003) Misperceptions, The Media and The Iraq War, The PIPA/ Knowledge Networks Poll, Program on International Policy Attitudes (PIPA), 2 October 2003. < http://www.pipa.org/ > (accessed 27 November 2003) Labinger, Jay A. & Harry Collins (eds) (2001) The One Culture? A Conversation about Science (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). Sokal, Alan (1996) A Physicist Experiments with Cultural Studies, Lingua Franca 6(4): 62 64.

Bricmont & Sokal: Reply to Gabriel Stolzenberg 113 Sokal, Alan & J. Bricmont (1998) Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals Abuse of Science (New York: Picador): 50 105. Stolzenberg, Gabriel (2004) Kinder, Gentler Science Wars, review of Labinger & Collins (2001), Social Studies of Science 34(1): 77 89. Weinberg, Steven (1992) Dreams of a Final Theory (New York: Pantheon). Jean Bricmont is Professor of Theoretical Physics at the University of Louvain, Belgium. Address: Institut de Physique Théorique, Université Catholique de Louvain, 2 chemin du Cyclotron, B-1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium; fax: +32 10 472 414; email: bricmont@fyma.ucl.ac.be Alan Sokal is Professor of Physics at New York University. Address: Department of Physics, New York University, 4 Washington Place, New York, NY 10003, USA; fax: +1 212 995 4016; email: sokal@nyu.edu