The Overpopulation of Solutions to Philosophical Problems

Similar documents
The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

The Philosophy of Logic

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Falsification. David Miller Department of Philosophy University of Warwick COVENTRY CV4 7AL UK.

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Inductive Inference, Rationality and Pragmatism: Peirce and Ajdukiewicz

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Draft of a paper to appear in C. Cellucci, E. Grosholz and I. Ippoliti (eds.), Logic and Knowledge, Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

Class 6 - Scientific Method

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Presuppositional Apologetics

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Assertion and Inference

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

1. What arguments does Socrates use in Plato s Republic to show that justice is to be preferred over injustice?


MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

The poverty of mathematical and existential truth: examples from fisheries science C. J. Corkett

ALETHIC, EPISTEMIC, AND DIALECTICAL MODELS OF. In a double-barreled attack on Charles Hamblin's influential book

Philosophy 240: Symbolic Logic

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Critical Thinking: Present, Past and Future 5 April, 2015

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

THE HYPOTHETICAL-DEDUCTIVE METHOD OR THE INFERENCE TO THE BEST EXPLANATION: THE CASE OF THE THEORY OF EVOLUTION BY NATURAL SELECTION

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

A Critique of Friedman s Critics Lawrence A. Boland

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Could i conceive being a brain in a vat? John D. Collier a a

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Commentary on Feteris

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

A Note on Straight-Thinking

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Argument as reasoned dialogue

The Theory/Experiment Interface of the Observation of Black Holes

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Falsification of Popper and Lakatos (Falsifikace podle Poppera a Lakatose)

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

PHILOSOPHY IM 25 SYLLABUS IM SYLLABUS (2019)

complete state of affairs and an infinite set of events in one go. Imagine the following scenarios:

What is Game Theoretical Negation?

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Moore s Paradox and the Norm of Belief

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Transcription:

The Overpopulation of Solutions to Philosophical Problems Nathan Oseroff King s College London OZSW Graduate Conference in Theoretical Philosophy nathan.oseroff@kcl.ac.uk

Outline 1. The Problem of Overpopulation 2. The Primary Function of Argumentation: Giving Good Reasons 3. Two Problems for Good Reasons 3.1 The Problem of the Criterion 3.2 The Scandal of Deduction 4. A Conjecture 5. A Response 5.1 Answering the Problem of the Criterion 5.2 Answering the Scandal of Deduction 6. Conclusion

A Conjecture What can be learned through intersubjective dialogue in philosophical disputes? That is, what can be learned from mutual criticism of the validity and soundness of proposed deductive arguments? I conjecture that dialogue exposes nothing more than that (1) there exists incoherence in a set of propositions or that (2) a set of propositions entails unacceptable consequences. Thus, I cannot give an argument that justifies the above conjecture, but I can eliminate competing conjectures. This talk explains how to eliminate the competition.

The Problem of Overpopulation There is a difficulty for a community in choosing in a principled way among competing, mutually exclusive solutions to philosophical problems. That is, it is a problem of group decision making under conditions of ignorance. Each solution is plausible to individuals that hold different assumptions about which properties of solutions are desirable. These solutions are not mundane: they are conceptually distant from whether there is an apple on a table or whether I ought to go to the corner shop. This is the problem of overpopulation. How can we adjudicate between competing solutions?

The Problem of Overpopulation The problem of overpopulation is expressed in Kołakowski s Law of Infinite Cornucopia [Kołakowski, 2001, 79]: For any proposition, including propositions about which sorts of properties of propositions (specifically, propositions about solutions) are desirable, it is possible to construct a deductive argument that entails the proposition.

All propositions are (in principle) defensible so long as one is willing to accept premises that entail the proposition. The problem of overpopulation is related to but different from the Duhem-Quine problem: [a]ny statement can be held true come what may, if we make drastic enough adjustments elsewhere in the system [Quine, 1961, 43. cf. 41].

The first problem: a system of coherent propositions exists that entails any proposition; the second: any singular proposition can be defended from criticism by revising other members of the presently accepted system of propositions. The two conclusions are absurd: some propositions are not (presumably) defensible, or at least not rationally defensible; some revisions to members of a system of propositions are (presumably) rational, yet after some number n of revisions they are no longer rational.

The Primary Function of Argumentation: Positive Reasons for Belief How can we rationally adjudicate between solutions to our philosophical problems? A proposal: Reduce the population down: the solution that has a good reason for belief (the belief is justified, warranted, probabilified, etc.). All other solutions that lack good reasons are rejected; if no good reasons are given, then one should refrain from belief.

The Scandal of Deduction Since Aristotle philosophers have attempted to tackle the problem that all deductive arguments appear to be circular or question-begging. [Aristotle, 1960, II xvi 64b28-65a26].1 This conflict has been elaborated on in the scandal of deduction : sound arguments implicitly or explicitly include the objective information of the conclusion within the premises. [Dummett, 1978, 297]2 However, begging the question or a petitio principii is considered an informal fallacy where a deductive argument includes the objective informative content of its conclusion within the premises. 1Cf. [DeMorgan, 1847]; [Govier, 2001, 85, 163-5]; [Harris, 1992]; [Mill, 1842, Book II, Ch. II-III, 1]; [Keynes, 1906, Part III, Ch. IX]; [Walton, 1991]. 2[Hintikka, 1973, 222 et passim]; [Peirce and Ladd-Franklin, 1901, D Agostino and Floridi, 2009]

If all sound deductive arguments are question-begging, which premises ought to be adopted? If we can identify a set of rationally defensible standards for good reasons for belief, the problem of overpopulation is solved. What if there is disagreement about the set of standards for good reasons for belief? The problem of overpopulation reasserts itself: there exist many different competing standards. How should we adjudicate between these standards?

The Problem of the Criterion What standards of argumentation are rationally defensible? Philosophers desire a criterion of rationality. How can they determine which criterion should be accepted? They must rationally adjudicate between different criteria. But how do they determine that they rationally adjudicate between different criteria? They must have a criterion of rationality This is a variation of the problem of the criterion: we would need a judicatory instrument; to verify this instrument, we need a demonstration; to verify the demonstration, an instrument: there we are in a circle. [Montaigne, 1976, 454]3 3Cf. [Plato, 1967, 80d]

Two quotations from Wittgenstein exemplify this pessimism: If I have exhausted the justifications, I have reached bedrock, and my spade is turned. Then I am inclined to say, This is simply what I do [Wittgenstein, 2001, 217].⁴ Where two principles really do meet which cannot be reconciled with another, then each man declares the other a fool and a heretic At the end of reasons comes persuasion. [Wittgenstein, 1972, 611-12] ⁴ Cf. the summary of Peirce s thought in [Hookway, 1985, 229], Principle Zero in [van Fraassen, 2002, 41]; [Huyssteen, 1999, 195]

Wittgenstein s remarks reveal at least four undesirable consequences of argumentation as persuasion: 1. The standards of argumentation are accepted without good reason; [t]here is no rock which can serve as a fulcrum on which claims can be weighed in some absolutely decisive way [White, 1959, 48]. This creates an independent standing ground or impregnable stronghold for any standard [Heim, 1957, 32-33]. 2. Other forms of persuasion may serve equally well, such as linguistic trickery or threats of violence. 3. The problem of overpopulation is not solved by appealing to good reasons for belief: there is now the problem of overpopulation of standards. 4. Nothing is learned through argumentation other than that there exists disagreement.

A Few Conjectures The function of intersubjective argumentation is entirely critical, of dissuading someone from accepting a solution to a philosophical problem that has already been accepted. If it deductively entails a contradiction (modus tollendo tollens) or entails an unacceptable consequence (reductio ad absurdum, at least one proposition is false [Hattiangadi, 1978, Hattiangadi, 1979]. In both cases the conjunction of propositions entails no course of action for it entails all courses of action: A self-contradictory sentence asserts too much; it is too informative to be true [Bar-Hillel and Carnap, 1964].

A Response Any contradiction is not a good reason for rejecting a conclusion, for when a conjunction is refuted, there is no principled way to distribute blame among the conjuncts [Strevens, 2001, 516].⁵ Therefore, any choice in response to criticism is not logically forbidden, including embracing contradictions [Grünbaum, 1962]. ⁵ Cf. [Lakatos, 1970, 100-2]; [Grünbaum, 1962, 19].

A Response, cont. However, there still exist guiding normative principles: we ought to abhor contradictions. This is why the problem of overpopulation is about a finite number of competing, mutually philosophical solutions to philosophical problems. We already exclude a vast number of theories. Instead of focusing on standards of permissibility, we should focus on standards of impermissibility.

Answering the Problem of the Criterion We must have a criterion of irrationality: its role is to proscribe, not to prescribe. To adopt a criterion, we make a conjecture. If there are problems with this conjecture, reject it, for it is a bad criterion; if there are not problems with the conjecture, it is permissible to (tentatively) adopt it. The problem of the criterion is terminated before it can begin.

We can (maybe) do no more than show how good reasons as a standard of argumentation lead either to a contradiction or an absurd conclusion. We cannot give good reasons to think that criticism succeeds in all circumstances. If good reasons are impossible, what is left? Bad reasons, i.e., incoherence. [Bartley, 1984]. Are there any problems for the conjecture? Should we accept incoherence in most cases? No, I think not. We have no solution worth considering if we have contradictory courses of action. Coherence is (possibly) a minimal standard (outside some cases involving liar paradoxes [Priest, 2001]).

Answering the Scandal of Deduction Arguments reveal contradictions within a conjunction of premises. A subject learns something new when they discover a contradiction, i.e., that not all premises can be accepted. Arguments still serve a function, even though it is not to give good reasons for belief.

Some Potential Problems 1. Preface Paradox: Already rational to believe that for all sets of sentences, at least one sentence is false. This is already known. Therefore, discovering incoherence is not discovery. 2. Preface Paradox Extended: The preface and the body of sentences imply the other s falsify. It is rational to accept both. Therefore, all proposed solutions are incoherent. Reply: but this is absurd. Two approaches: there is a small enough set of sentences that the preface paradox does not apply to; or, the issue is the discovery of the existence of falsity, not prior rational belief in the existence of falsity.

Conclusion This conclusion is not just meta-philosophical: argumentation simpliciter functions to discover error; any present success may be overturned by the discovery of error. It restructures our understanding of the history of philosophy: all is nothing but conjectures and criticisms, including the conjecture that the standards of argumentation involve good reasons for belief [Popper, 1972].

Although ancient self-refutation arguments cannot falsify our most radical adversaries views (and defuse our own most hyperbolical doubts) by proving that what they envisage is logically impossible they can silence them, by delimiting the area of constructive philosophical inquiry and debate. [Castagnoli, 2007, 69]

For sometimes we conclude a manifest absurdity from the negation of a hypothesis, and then the hypothesis is true; or instead we conclude a manifest absurdity from its affirmation, and then the hypothesis is established as false; and when we have not been able to derive an absurdity, from either its negation or its affirmation, the hypothesis remains in doubt; so that, to establish the truth of a hypothesis, it is not enough that all the phenomena follow from it, but if there follows something contrary to one of the phenomena, that is enough to establish its falsity. [Pascal, 1647, 29.v.1647]

References I Aristotle (1960). Aristotle: Posterior Analytics. Topica. tr. by Hugh Tredennick and E.S. Forster. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Bar-Hillel, Y. and Carnap, R. (1964). An outline of a theory of semantic information. In Bar-Hillel, Y., editor, Language and Information, pages 221 274. Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA. Bartley, W. (1984). The Retreat to Commitment. Open Court, London, 2nd edition. Castagnoli, L. (2007). Everything is true, everything is false: Self-refutation arguments from democritus to augustine. Antiqvorvm Philosphia, 1:11 74. D Agostino, M. and Floridi, L. (2009). The enduring scandal of deduction. Synthesis, 167(2):271 315. DeMorgan, A. (1847). Formal Logic. The Open Court Co. Dummett, M. (1978). The justification of deduction. In Truth and Other Enigmas, pages 290 318. Duckworth.

References II Govier, T. (2001). A Practical Study of Argument. Wadsworth/Thomson Learning, Belmonst, CA, 5th edition. Grünbaum, A. (1962). The falsifiability of theories: Total or partial? a contemporary evaluation of the duhem-quine thesis. Synthese, 14(1):17 34. Harris, J. (1992). Against Relativism. La Salle. Hattiangadi, J. (1978). The structure of problems, part i. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 8:345 365. Hattiangadi, J. (1979). The structure of problems, part ii. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 9:49 76. Heim, K. (1957). Christian Faith and Natural Science. Harper and Brothers, New York. Hintikka, J. (1973). Logic, Language-Games and Information. Carendon, Oxford. Hookway, C. (1985). Peirce. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

References III Huyssteen, J. V. (1999). The Shaping of Rationality. Eerdmans, Grand Rapids. Keynes, J. N. (1906). Studies and Excersises in Formal Logic. Macmillan and Company, London, 4th edition. Kołakowski, L. (2001). Religion: If There Is No God : On God, the Devil, Sin, and Other Worries of the So-Called Philosophy of Religion. St. Augustine s Press. Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A., editors, Criticism and The Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, MA. Mill, J. (1842). A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. Longmans, Green and Company, London, 8th edition. Montaigne, M. (1976). Michel de Montaigne. The Complete Works. Essays, Travel Journal, Letters, tr. by Donald M. Frame. Stanford University Press, Stanford.

References IV Pascal, B. (1647). Reply by blaise pascal to the very reverend father noël, rector, of the society of paris in paris [oct.-nov., 1647]. In Cailliet, E. and Blankenagel, J. C., editors, Great Shorter Works of Pascal. Westminster Press, Philadelphia. Peirce, C. and Ladd-Franklin, C. (1901). Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, volume 2, chapter Petitio Principii. Macmillan, London. Plato (1967). Plato in Twelve Volumes. tr. by W.R.M. Lamb, volume 3. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Popper, K. R. (1972). Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Clarendon Press. Priest, G. (2001). Introduction to Non-Classical Logic. Cambridge University Press. Quine, W. (1961). From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition.

References V Strevens, M. (2001). The bayesian treatment of auxiliary hypotheses. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. van Eemeren, F. H. and Grootendorst, R. (2004). A Systematic Theory of Argumentation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK. van Fraassen, B. C. (2002). The Empirical Stance. Yale University Press. Walton, D. N. (1991). Begging the Question: Circular Reasoning as a Tactic of Argumentation. Greenwood, London. White, M. (1959). Religion, Politics and the Higher Learning. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Wittgenstein, L. (1972). On Certainty. Harper & Row. Wittgenstein, L. (2001). Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell Publishers.