Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 17. Naturalism and Norms

Similar documents
Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Davidson's objections to Quine's empiricism.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Epistemology Naturalized

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Skepticism and Internalism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Apriority in Naturalized Epistemology: Investigation into a Modern Defense

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

JUSTIFICATION INTRODUCTION

Naturalized Epistemology, Normativity and the Argument Against the A Priori

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

What is knowledge? How do good beliefs get made?

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Critical Scientific Realism

NATURALISM IN EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

A Comparison of Davidson s and McDowell s Accounts of Perceptual Beliefs

What is a Theory of Meaning? (II), p. 60

INTRODUCTION: EPISTEMIC COHERENTISM

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Assertion and Inference

Florida State University Libraries

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Stout s teleological theory of action

At the Frontiers of Reality

M rary philosophy. In philosophy of mind, the dominant project is to show

A Priori Bootstrapping

1. A first look at the question whether Quine s epistemology is normative

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Realism and instrumentalism

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later

My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research

ON EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT. by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies. II Martin Davies

Interpretation: Keeping in Touch with Reality. Gilead Bar-Elli. 1. In a narrow sense a theory of meaning (for a language) is basically a Tarski-like

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Aboutness and Justification

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Van Fraassen: Arguments Concerning Scientific Realism

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

A. Davidson s Epistemic Argument Against Empiricist Theories of Meaning

Kripke s skeptical paradox

UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI

Biola University: An Ontology of Knowledge Course Points discussed 5/27/97

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Howard Sankey Department of History and Philosophy of Science University of Melbourne

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Naturalized Epistemology

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Naturalism and is Opponents

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Transcription:

Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 17 Naturalism and Norms Kenzo HAMANO Since Professor Quine published 'Epistemology Naturalized' in 1969, many critical papers have been written. One of the main objections to Professor Quine's project of naturalizing epistemology has been that in his version of naturalized epistemology (hereafter "NE") there is no room for normative elements, that is, norms and normative judgements. However, many critics claimed, the reason why traditional epistemology can be classified as an epistemology is that it deals with normative issues, for example, that it tries to justify the system of our knowledge against sceptical attack. Therefore, NE with no room for normative elements cannot be an epistemology in the true sense of the word. Accordingly these critics concluded that NE, which is a chapter of psychology, is not an epistemology. This kind of criticism of NE still continues notwithstanding the fact that Professor Quine asserts that his NE is an enlightened version of epistemology (enlightened in the sense that NE recognizes the scientific origin of the sceptical challenge) and that NE is an epistemology which examines the relationship between scientific theory and sensory evidence. Moreover, in the 1980s Professor Quine started to explain more explicitly how his NE can accomodate normative elements. In this paper I would like to explain and examine the validity of his response to his critics. First, I will explain how Professor Quine can defend his project against two main objections. Secondly, I will show my own criticism against Professor Quine's version of NE and try to suggest an alternative version of NE which may offend his taste for more austere language and discourse, but which, I hope, will not differ so much in substance from his own version. Professor Quine's response consists in interpreting the normativity of cognitive norms as the normativity of instrumental reason. In other words, scientific method ological norms acquire their normativity because they can make a greater contribu tion to the realization of the purposes of scientific inquiry than other norms. Again, those norms can be said to be accepted as valid methodological norms because they are the best instruments available so far, given the present purposes of science. He says that: For me normative epistemology is a branch of engineering. It is the technol Nagoya Institute of Technology Gokiso, Showa-ku, Nagoya 466 Japan. ogy of truth-seeking, or, in a more cautiously epistemological term, predic- -127-

18 Kenzo HAMANO Vol. 9 tion. Like any technology, it makes free use of whatever scientific findings may suit its purpose... There is no question here of ultimate value, as in morals; it is a matter of efficacy for an ulterior end, truth or prediction. The normative here, as elsewhere in engineering, becomes descriptive when the terminal parameter is expressed. We could say the same of morality if we could view it as aimed at reward in heaven.(1) Furthermore, in Pursuit of Truth he says that: I remain occupied..., with what has been central to traditional epistemology, namely the relation of science to its sensory data. I approach it as an input-output relation within flesh-and-blood denizens of an antecedently acknowledged external world, a relation open to inquiry as a chapter of the science of that world. To emphasize my dissociation from the Cartesian dream [of a foundation for scientific certainty firmer than scientific method itself], I have written of neural receptors and their stimulation than of sense and sensibilia. I call the pursuit naturalized epistemology, but I have no quarrel with traditionalists who protest my retention of the latter word. I agree with them that repudiation of the Cartesian dream is no minor devia tion. But they are wrong in protesting that the normative element, so charac teristic of epistemology, goes by the board. In so far as theoretical epis temology gets naturalized into a chapter of theoretical science, so normative epistemology gets naturalized into a chapter of engineering: the technology of anticipating sensory stimulation.(2) By the way, the purposes of scientific inquiry, according to Professor Quine, are understanding, prediction and truth. But in Pursuit of Truth Professor Quine says that: But when I cite prediction as the checkpoints of science, I do not see that as normative. I see it as defining a particular language game, in Wittgenstein's phrase: the game of science, in contrast to other good language games such as fiction and poetry. A sentence's claim to scientific status rests on what it contributes to a theory whose checkpoints are in prediction.(3) In so far as we wish to do a scientific inqury, we must judge cognitive claims in terms of predictive power. Because the acceptance of prediction as the defining character of science is required for an inquiry to be a scientific inquiry, behaving accordingly is a necessary condition of doing a scientific inquiry. In this sense, the requirement of the acceptance of prediction as the defining character of science is, as -128-

No. 3 Naturalism and Norms 19 it were, a constitutive rule of science. If you do not obey that rule, you do not do a scientific inquiry and you play a language game different from the language game of science. While Professor Quine asserts that he does not see prediction as the checkpoints of science as normative, I presume that the acceptance of prediction as the check points of science must play the role of a constitutive rule and be the ultimate source of the normativity of norms within scientific inquiry which is defined by that rule. Metaphorically speaking, the scientific inquiry and discourse can be characterized as a magnetic field whose source of magnetic power is the acceptance of prediction as the defining character of science. Even if the ultimate purpose of science is not prediction but understanding, since the necessary condition of the validity of a theory or a cognitive norm is predictive success, players of the scientific language game must, first of all, aim at greater predictive success. Hence, in spite of Professor Quine's assertion that norms are involved with framing hypotheses and not with testing, I think that norms and justification are involved with both framing and testing hypotheses. Thus, according to Professor Quine, his NE includes two sides: the theoretical and the normative side. The important point is that once the ends are determined, the crucial information for the choice of a theory or a methodological norm is the descriptive fact, namely whether a certain norm is more predictively successful than other alternatives. Hence, the substantive part of a normative inquiry turns out to be descriptive. The description of empirical facts constitutes the substantive part of normative epistemology. Normative epistemology can be naturalized into an empirical inquiry, that is, technology or engineering, so Professor Quine seems to claim. His main example of a cognitive norm is the principle of empiricism, hence, the exclusion of telepathy and clairvoyance as reliable cognitive tools for us.(4) This way of dealing with normative elements of epistemology sounds familiar to us. In many passages where Professor Quine talks about engineering of truth -seeking and about "the whole strategy of rational conjecture," he seems to focus upon the reliability of belief-forming process. His position seems to have much affinity with so-called reliabilist theory of epistemic justification. This is not surprising at all, considering that some reliabilists were influenced by Professor Quine's idea of NE. Reliabilism claims roughly that a belief p is justifiable if p results from a reliable belief-forming process, that is, a belief-forming process with a high truth-ratio. Then, there is one of the familiar objections against reliabilism: that the concept of reliability already contains the reference to truth, although a true belief cannot be identified independently of the way in which a reliable process is identified. Accordingly, a reliable process cannot be identified properly because the identification of a reliable process needs the identification of a true belief which in its turn needs the identification of a reliable process. There is - 129-

20 Kenzo HAMANO Vol. 9 clearly a vicious circularity. Hence, reliabilists are required to make clearer the connection between truth and reliability. Nevertheless, Professor Quine's version of NE is not troubled with this kind of a vicious circularity and deals with the problem straightforwardly. The key to the solution of the problem is his naturalism. Professor Quine rejects the possibility and even the coherence of the concept of first philosophy. According to him, there is no external vantage point, hence, what he calls "cosmic exile" is impossible.(5) Only immanent epistemology and ontology are possible and make sense. Via the mediation of naturalism, his instrumentalisitc epistemology leads to his robust realism. In other words, a theory with the best predictive success, or which func tions as the best instrument of prediction available so far can be treated as true theory. We must remember that Professor Quine adopts a disquotational theory of truth, according to which to call a sentence true is simply to affirm it. He answers the question 'how can we tell whether to affirm it [a sentence]?' in the following way: The lazy answer is 'That all depends on what the sentence is. In case of ' Snow is white' you just look at snow and check the color.' The more sympathetic answer is a general analysis of the grounds of warranted beliefs, hence scientific method...(6) Thus, what the best scientific theory says exist really exists. In other words, because the best scientific theory must have the best predictive success, the best predictive success is one of the main indicators of truth. The best theory is always the best one so far. Even if science is fallible, from within the best present scientific theory we can enumerate true beliefs. The following passage clearly shows the relationship between predictive success, his instrumentalism, naturalism and his robust realism. Disavowing as I do a first philosphy outside science, I can attribute reality and truth only within the terms and standards of the scientific system of the world that I now accept: only immanently. But also, within this system, I can study man at work and appreciate how his theory -mine- is underdeter mined.(7) Thus, Professor Quine's idea of epistemic justification is similar to reliabilism, while it is not bothered with a familiar problem of reliabilism. Hence, we seem to be able to say that Professor Quine has a definite answer to one of the main objection to his NE: his NE can deal squarely with normative issues within its own field. -130-

No. 3 Naturalism and Norms 21 Another main objection to Professor Quine's NE is that he confuses causation with justification, especially, when talking of the observation sentence as valid replacement of sense-data as the solid rockbottom evidence for science. According to Professor Quine, observation sentences are "vehicles of scientific evidence and as an entering wedge into language."(8) The validity of the criticism depends on whether what causes assent to an observation sentence can also play a justificatory role. Observation, which is neural intake according to Professor Quine, causes assent to an observation sentence and because of conditioning an observation sentence is associated with ranges of perceptually similar neural intakes. The criticism takes into consideration the fact that ranges of perceptually similar neural intakes with eliciting query prompt assent to an observation sentence. Certainly, an assent may be caused by certain neural intake, but, the objection goes, that is that. That fact does not imply observation sentence can be a vehicle of scientific evidence which plays the role of the final checkpoint and the guarantor of the objectivity. A perceptual state can play a causal but not a justificatory role. But Professor Quine can defend his NE by reminding us of the significant characteristics of observation sentence. The point is that an assent to an observa tion sentence and the ranges of perceptually similar neural intakes are related with each other in the form of immediate association by conditioning. The verdict on an observation sentence, which is an occasion sentence, depends upon that particular occasion which consists of a particular pattern of neural intakes and can be judged right or wrong on the spot. An observation sentence requires a verdict on the very occasion and, in addition, the same verdict community-wide. This kind of immedi ate association with the ranges of perceptually similar neural intakes makes observa tion sentence have a special place in NE. The association with neural intakes by conditioning is so tight and immediate that an assent to an observation sentence without appropriate neural intake makes that assent inappropriate. On the other hand, an assent to an observation sentence with an appropriate neural intake makes that assent justifiable. The assent to an observation sentence elicited by a query with an appropriate neural intake is justifiable. Hence, an assent to an observation sentence indicates the presence of solid sensory evidence which justifies that assent. Thus, the ranges of neural intakes which are associated with a particular observation sentence by conditioning can not only cause but also justify an assent to the observation sentence. Hence, observation sentence can be the final checkpoints of scientific theory and the guarantor of objectivity of science. Thus, seemingly Professor Quine can answer the two main criticism of his NE with respect to the place of norm in it.(9) Now I would like to explain my own problems with Professor Quine's NE. My own dissatisfaction results from the feeling that something significant is missing from Professor Quine's naturalization of normative epistemology. I presume that -131-

22 Kenzo HAMANO Vol. 9 epistemic norm presupposes the existence of an epistemic subject which can adjust his or her judgement in accordance with the norm, in other words, a subject who can take epistemic responsibility. Taking this aspect of normativity seriously, I have a great sympathy with internalism with respect to epistemic justification. An epistemically responsible subject ought to explain why one's belief can be regarded as warranted. The subject must have a justifying reason under his cognitive perspective. Otherwise, that person cannot be justified to believe the belief in question. Such a subject would be epistemically irresponsible. Norms are created to help a cognitive subject behave responsibly in the first place. There are familiar attacks against internalism. One objection is that this kind of position mixes the two different levels of justification, the level of justification of belief and the level of justification of someone to believe something. We can discuss the first level of justification independently of the discussion of the second level, and the first level is more basic than the second. This objection is, I presume, related to the second familiar objection to internalism, what can be called the infinite regress argument.(10) If you have to justify every epistemic claim with clear awareness of justifying reasons, then there will be no stopping place to the justification game. Unless you assume some knowledge claim to be the real foundation, i.e. a self-justifying true claim, as it were, a kind of epistemic unmovable mover, the justification game will never stop. The catch is that it is not plausible that that kind of epistemic unmovable mover exists. Hence, the internalist justification cannot escape infinite regress. So the familiar objection goes. However, being an internalist with respect to epistemic justification does not mean not being able to be a naturalist in the sense of rejecting first philosophy. I do not find any conceptual obstacle to being an internalist naturalist or naturalistic internalist in so far as naturalism can depend not upon natural scientific method and knowledge in the narrow sense of the word but upon empirical method and knowl edge in general. If you take that position, you can use the result of scientific inquiry to justify your claim. It goes without saying that you can justify it with more or less clear consciousness of the justifcatory connection between the claim in question and the scientific explanation of the justifyng ground of the claim. You can fully particpate in the justification game as a responsible epistemic subject who can carry the burden of being a epistemic subject. Even if you believe in a particular sentence without a clear awareness of relevant justifying reasons, you can afterwards understand the justifying ground by means of your own or another's inquiry. One can, as it were, retrospectively justify one's belief. Or at least someone as a responsible part of the community must be able to understand justifying reasons. Otherwise, some cognitive judgements float without justifying ballast. - 132-

No. 3 Naturalism and Norms 23 Let us take the case of an observation sentence. As I showed above, observa tion sentence can be vehicles of scientific evidence. The ranges of perceptually similar neural intakes can contribute to the justification of an assent to a particular observation sentence. Nevertheless, the person who assents must believe that a particular neural intake belongs to the appropriate set of perceptually similar neural intakes. More detailed justification needs more sophisticated scientific knowledge. But an ordinary person must be able to say, however inarticulately, something about the appropriateness of sensory stimulation to an assent to the observation sentence. Let us think about how children learn observation sentence. As Professor Quine says, "Language is a social art which all acquire on the evidence solely of other people's overt behavior under publicly recognizable circumstances."(11) Here, children use other people's overt behavior under publicly recognizable circumstances as the evidence for their fledgling linguistic theory. Nevertheless, it is implausible that children in transition from the prelinguisitc to the linguistic stage have a clear awareness of the justifying reasons for their theoretical moves. This theoretical awareness will come later. However, if we change focus from learners to teachers, the picture we have of the place of norm and awareness in language acquisition is certainly different. The point is that even the acquisition of observation sentence needs training by grown - up persons. The teacher does not train fledgling members of the linguistic commu nity mechanically. The teacher trains children in order that their behavior con forms to the behavior of community as a whole, appropriate behavior under appro priate circumstances. Here, "appropriate" implies the involvement of normative elements. Because the teachers somehow understand relevant norms, they as responsible members of the community can encourage or correct children's behavior. The trainee may not have a clear awareness of norms involved, but the trainer has an awareness of the norm, or at least the trainer can say something to justify what he does to train the trainee. Thus, the concept of the acquisition of observation sentence has already a normative element. The verbal disposition related to observation sentence is characterized as appropriate assent or dissent under appropri ate circumstances. Appropriate means not just conforming to the community-wide pattern but also deserving to be reinforced by the full-fledged members of the community. Professor Quine says that language is "a matter of fluency and effective dialogue." Success in communication is the main purpose of language and commu nicative success "is judged by smoothness of conversation, by frequent predictability of verbal and non-verbal reactions..."(12) Predictive success plays an important role here, too. From these purposes arise normative pressures to conform to the verbal behavior of the community as whole. The trainers are the agents for this normative force of linguistic norm who deliberately inculcate norms into the trainees. -133-

24 Kenzo HAMANO Vol. 9 Now, in order to make my internalism more realistic, I qualify my position. I do not wish to claim that one always has to be aware of norms explicitly formulable to be justified in having a certain belief. As Professor Quine shows in "Truth by Convention," there is the level on which a regress of rules must be stopped.(13) On that level people behave in a certain regular way. That pattern of behavior cannot be justified by any explicit norm. I find this part of Professor Quine's theory very similar to later Wittgenstein's idea. If I may use a Wittgensteinian expresson, on this level one can only say that this is how the language game is played. In other words, here people agree not on judgement but on action. On this level cognitive moves depend on primitive actions about which there is no room for the justificatory talk. This is the ground-level on which the justification game can be established. This is the extreme end of the continuum of cognitive moves about whose justification we cannot speak. From this level-zero to the level of sophisticated scientific justificatory talks, there is a continuum. Hence, I admit the existence of the level on which justification does not make sense. Here, there is no justificatory talk whether external or internal. But on other level we can reasonably ask justificatory reasons from the person who makes a cognitive claim. It may be important to know where to stop, but that does not mean the underestimation of the importance of human desire to know the justificatory reasons. While it is a disease to ask for evidence and justificatory talk on every level, it is another disease to adopt as the model for the justificatory talk on other levels the absence of the justificatory talk on the level-zero which is beyond justification. I presume that internalism with the qualification fits better with our understanding of cognitive norm and justification and, above all, of human beings as self-reflective animals than the position which denies the significant role played by the subject's cognitive grasp of justifying reason in the cognitive justification game. Professor Quine accepts Professor Donald Davidson's anomalous monism and the practical indispensability of intensional discourse. If Professor Quine tries to develop normative epistemology, even if it is a naturalized version, had conscious ness better be given a more respectable place in his system? Professor Quine may answer that his normative epistemology deals only with the factual question of which norms are better at realizing adopted purposes, i.e. that his normative epistemology is in a sense, not normative but factual. In addition, he may say that norms and rules are not causally effective but merely expository devices. Whether certain patterns of research behavior tend to lead to certain purposes is what his normative epistemology seeks for. Normativity in the substan tive sense is not within his naturalized epistemology. In short, normativity is naturalized. Hence, while Professor Quine claims that normative issues are taken care of by his naturalized epistemology, what he truly means is that naturalized normativity, not normativity in the substantive sense, but expository devices for - 134-

No. 3 Naturalism and Norms 25 summing up the emprical facts of the matching of the result of certain behavior patterns, is accomodated by his epistemological inquiry. However, if we are interested in making the more whole and integrated picture of human cognitive activity, we had better, I presume, have give normative and intentional discourses a more respectable place in epistemology. The half-hearted accomodation of normativity could be an obstacle towards the more whole and integrated understanding of the dynamic and multi-dimentional character of human cognitive activity. As Professor Quine talks about purposes of science, there is more than merely logical possibility of agreement about norms, hence objectivity, hence realty.(14) The purposes and norms shape the styles of research, hence the results of the research, and vice versa, the more wholehearted accomodation of normativity would promise more productive results in our epistemological inquiry. Note (1) W. V. Quine, "Reply to Morton White" in The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, L. E. Hahn and P. A. Schillp, eds., La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, pp. 664-665. (2) W. V. Quine, Pursuit of Truth, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990, p. 19. (3) W. V. Quine, Pursuit of Truth, p. 20. (4) W. V. Quine, Pursuit of Truth, p. 19. (5) W. V. Quine, Word and Object, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1960, p. 275. (6) W. V. Quine, Pursuit of Truth, p. 93. (7) W. V. Quine, "Reply to Harold W. Lee" in The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, L. E. Hahn and P. A. Schillp, eds., La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, pp. 316. (8) W. V. Quine, Pursuit of Truth, p. 5. (9) My idea expressed in the preceding two paragraphs was stimulated in the direction by Roger Gibson, "Quine in the Naturalizing of Epistemology" in On Quine-New Essays, eds., Paolo Leonardi and Marco Santambrogio, Cambridge University Press 1994, p. 98. (10) For a perceptive criticism of internalism, see W. P. Alston, Epistemic Justification, Ithaca, N. Y.: Cornell University Press, 1989. (11) W. V. Quine, Word and Object, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1960, p. IX (12) W. V. Quine, Pursuit of Truth, p. 43. (13) W. V. Quine, "Truth by Convention" in The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, New York, enlarged ed., Harvard University Press, 1966. pp. 77-106. (14) I have a great sympathy with the idea of "more relaxed realism" which Christopher Hookway discussed in his Quine: Language, Experience and Reality, Oxford: Polity Press, 1988. p. 216. - 135-