The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism

Similar documents
Suki Finn. Abstract. Introduction

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Postmodal Metaphysics

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

Structural realism and metametaphysics

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

On Quine s Ontology: quantification, extensionality and naturalism (from commitment to indifference)

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Against Vague and Unnatural Existence: Reply to Liebesman

Comments on Ontological Anti-Realism

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Unrestricted Quantification and Reality: Reply to Kim. Takashi Yagisawa. California State University, Northridge

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Necessity and Truth Makers

Bayesian Probability

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Neo- Carnapian Quietism:

UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Metaontology: Introduction Berto, F.; Kroon, F.; Voltolini, A. Published in: The Monist

The Correspondence theory of truth Frank Hofmann

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Idealism and the Harmony of Thought and Reality

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

God of the gaps: a neglected reply to God s stone problem

Modal Realism, Still At Your Convenience

Haberdashers Aske s Boys School

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

Russell on Plurality

Metametametaphysics and Dialetheism

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

The Methodology of Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Russell on Metaphysical Vagueness

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Van Fraassen s Appreciated Anti-Realism. Lane DesAutels. I. Introduction

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

Anaphoric Deflationism: Truth and Reference

Can logical consequence be deflated?

From Grounding to Truth-Making: Some Thoughts

Metametametaphysics and Dialetheism

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

What kind of Intensional Logic do we really want/need?

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Arguments Against Metaphysical Indeterminacy and Vagueness 1 Elizabeth Barnes. Draft, June 2010

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Transcription:

1 2 3 4 5 Q1 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 42 43 The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism SUKI FINN Abstract Scientific realism holds that the terms in our scientific theories refer and that we should believe in their existence. This presupposes a certain understanding of quantification, namely that it is ontologically committing, which I challenge in this paper. I argue that the ontological loading of the quantifiers is smuggled in through restricting the domains of quantification, without which it is clear to see that quantifiers are ontologically neutral. Once we remove domain restrictions, domains of quantification can include non-existent things, as they do in scientific theorizing. Scientific realism would therefore require redefining without presupposing a view of ontologically committing quantification. Introduction In modern classical logic we cite the existential (or particular) quantifier as meaning there exists an and as such quantification is a mark of ontological commitment. Yet, in the words of Priest, the view that the particular quantifier is existentially loaded is a relatively new one historically and it has become entrenched in modern philosophical logic for less than happy reasons. 1 Not only is it entrenched in philosophical logic but also in the philosophy of science, where the debate over scientific realism presupposes that quantification is existentially loaded. In this paper I argue that should be read as some (not there exists ), and known as the particular (not existential ) quantifier, as quantification is existentially neutral. I will do this by using Quine, our exemplar of a realist and naturalist, to show that there is no legitimate justification for treating quantification in this loaded way. I will describe Quine s loading of quantification via domain restriction, and attack elements of the Quinean picture that lead to this restriction. I appeal to quantification in natural and formal languages for evidence of their neutrality in order to show that we should not take our domains of quantification in our scientific theorizing to include all and only existent things. It is 1 Graham Priest, The Closing of the Mind: How the particular quantifier became existentially loaded behind our backs, The Review of Symbolic Logic 1.1 (2008), 42. doi:10.1017/s0031819117000031 The Royal Institute of Philosophy, 2017 Philosophy; Page 1 of 17 2017 1

Suki Finn 44 45 46 47 48 49 50 51 52 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61 62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81 82 83 84 85 86 inherent in the scientific realist position that we believe the ontology provided to us through the successful reference of scientific terms in our scientific theories, and so, in other words, the domain is supposed to contain our ontology. 2 If quantifying over such domains is not the appropriate method for extracting our ontology, then scientific realism appears to be false, or else is in need of redefining without utilizing existentially loaded quantification. This shows the impact that the philosophy of logic can have on scientific realism. 1. The Quinean Ontological Criterion Quine, in his seminal paper OnWhat ThereIs (1948), puts forward a criterion for how to recognise the ontological commitments of a discourse, manifested via translation into classical first order predicate calculus. Quine believes that we speak in an ontologically committing way in natural language by the use of (what he sees as quantificational) idioms like there exists or there are. He is careful to stipulate that it is only those uses of quantificational idioms made seriously with regard to our best scientific theory that will be the assertions to whose ontology we ought to regard ourselves as committed. And he then requires that best scientific theory to be regimented into first order predicate logic in order to reveal its ontological commitments. Science speaks of things and as such they are members of the domain of quantification, and the Quinean (and the scientific realist) move is to say that whatever is in this domain will provide our ontology. Thus quantification is said to be the meansto display ontological commitment. Quine takes all statements in natural language to be (in principle at least) regimented into a quantified first order logical statement which will manifest its ontological commitments. After specifying which sentences are fit for ontological commitment in natural language, namely those in our best scientific theorizing, the next step in Quine sstrategy is to search through terminological resources in formal language to 2 I take that this is standard scientific realism. For examples that follow this definition see J.J.C. Smart, Philosophy and Scientific Realism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963); R.N. Boyd, On the Current Status of the Issue of Scientific Realism, Erkenntnis 19 (1983), 45 90; M. Devitt, Realism and Truth (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991); A. Kukla, Studies in Scientific Realism (Oxford: OUP, 1991); I. Niiniluoto, Critical Scientific Realism (Oxford: OUP, 1999); S. Psillos, Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth (London: Routledge, 1999); A. Chakravartty, A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable (Cambridge: CUP, 2007). 2

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99 100 101 102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111 112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128 129 determine what should carry and manifest such ontological commitment. Quine stipulates that the bearer for ontological commitment is the quantifier in first order logic, after eliminating all other candidates. So, in stating 3 is a prime number one is actually stating Na Pa which entails x(nx Px), which for Quine is read as there exists something that is a number and is prime. Thisishowcommitments are derived from natural language through regimentation, which is intended to display the underlying logical form of our language. We can thus deduce our ontology from the regimentation of our best scientific theory, by looking to what is quantified over in the domain. Therefore, to be quantified over in science is the Quinean realist ontological criterion. Quine does not provide any reason for ontologically loading the quantifier, nor argues for his criterion of ontological commitment, claiming that it is trivial and obvious. 3 I explore two possible reasons why such a realist may conclude that the quantifier carries ontological commitment: (1) because is a regimentation of the ordinary language there exists idiom and this already carries ontological commitment; (2) because is ontologically loaded by virtue of its semantics. These reasons correspond to the two issues I clarify in this paper: (1) whether quantification in natural language is ontologically committing; and (2) whether quantification in formal language is ontologically committing. I argue that quantification in both English and first order logic are ontologically neutral in section 3 and 4 respectively. In the next section 2, I explore if there is anything nearing an argument in Quine for ontologically loading quantification, looking to other elements of his philosophical picture for clues or justification. In particular I will look to Quine s set theory, and his slogans about entities and identity. 2. Domain restrictions from SET, NE, and TB Quine s commitment to set-theoretic model theory (described as SET below) and the following two slogans 4 NE and TB contribute to loading quantification: SET: Domains are sets NE: No entity without identity TB: To be is to be the value of a bound variable 3 W. V. O. Quine, Pursuit of Truth (Harvard University Press, 1992, revised edition), 26. 4 Willard Van Orman Quine, On What There Is, Review of Metaphysics 2.5 (1948), 33. 3

Suki Finn 130 131 132 133 134 135 136 137 138 139 140 141 142 143 144 145 146 147 148 149 150 151 152 153 154 155 156 157 158 159 160 161 162 163 164 165 166 167 168 169 170 171 172 Quine s slogan TB is intended as a descriptive tool to find out what exists our ontology will be made up of those things bound by variables in the best scientific theory. To be is for Quine to be an existent entity, and to be a value of a bound variable is to be quantified over in the domain. So TB states that to be existent is to be in a domain of quantification. I reject TB as it entails loaded quantification. The way to evaluate TB is thus to evaluate what it means to be included in a domain, to see whether domains are restricted to existent things. I show how the domain may be restricted using SET and NE in turn, and I reject these in favor of unrestricted domains. With a neutral domain, we get neutral quantification. 2.1. Restriction from SET For Quine, and in the standard set-theoretic version of model theory, domains are seen as sets. Domains therefore will for Quine be restricted in the same way that sets are restricted. Sets are restricted by identity, since sets are required to have determinate identity conditions. To have determinate identity conditions is for there to be a determinate answer as to whether one set a is identical to another set b. Set theory also tells us that sets are identified extensionally by their members, and as such their members must also have determinate identity conditions for every member of the set, there is a determinate answer as to whether it is identical to another member of the set. Since the set-theoretic version of model theory states that domains are sets, domains thus take on these same conditions. Domains, and members of domains, therefore also have determinate identity conditions. This is the restriction from SET on what can go in a domain: all members must have determinate identity conditions. 2.2. Restriction from NE Quine s slogan NE states that there is no entity without identity. So all entities must have determinate identity conditions. This may sound similar to the restriction imposed by SET as having identity, but this restriction posed by NE applies to only certain kinds of thing. An entity for Quine means an existent entity, as there are no other entities for Quine. As such, his NE states that there can be no existent entity without determinate identity conditions. Whereas, SET states that there can be no member of the domain (existent or not) without determinate identity conditions. So the restriction 4

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 173 174 175 176 177 178 179 180 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 188 189 190 191 192 193 194 195 196 197 198 199 200 201 202 203 204 205 206 207 208 209 210 211 212 213 214 215 from NE on what can go in a domain is: all the existents must have determinate identity conditions. We are trying to find motivation or justification for TB, where the whole domain is restricted to only existent things. So far, from SET and NE we only have the domain restricted to those things with identity. What the Quinean realist must do to get domain restrictions out of the identity condition requirement, is to hold a biconditional reading of NE, so that the identity restriction selects all and only existent things to be possible members of the domain. 5 That way, all things with identity must be existent, and thus restricting the domain to those with identity also restricts to existents. The biconditional is between being an entity and having identity, and is read as going in both directions not only do all existent entities require identity, but all entities with identity require existence. So we read NE as saying both no entity without identity and no identity without entity (where entities exist). These are the two directions for the biconditional: Left-Right: X cannot exist without having determinate identity conditions as in order to exist it must be determinately distinct from other existents. Right-Left: X cannot have determinate identity conditions without existing as existence is required for completeness or determinacy. From the biconditional NE we bridge the gap between SET and TB: SET provides us with the restriction that domains can only contain things with determinate identity conditions, and the biconditional NE provides us with the restriction that the only things with determinate identity conditions are existents, which brings us to TB which states that to be in a domain is to be an existent entity. Therefore, we derive that all and only existent things can be quantified over in a domain, hence TB and why is read there exists.for Quine, this is the natural reading of, and being part of the domain is how we use the term exists as this is just what exists means. Quine s identity constraint on domains ensures this reading of, but this 5 I am not claiming that Quinean s do hold a biconditional reading of NE, but rather that they need to in order to motivate TB or else there is a lack of argument for why quantification is taken to be existentially committing. It does nevertheless seem that they may hold the biconditional reading given that they seem to hold that non-existents lack determinate identity conditions and things with determinate identity conditions are existent things. I discuss this further in section 2.3. 5

Suki Finn 216 217 218 219 220 221 222 223 224 225 226 227 228 229 230 231 232 233 234 235 236 237 238 239 240 241 242 243 244 245 246 247 248 249 250 251 252 253 254 255 256 257 258 constraint is unnecessary. I will go on to reject this constraint by rejecting the restriction that SET imposes (that all members of domains require determinate identity conditions) and by rejecting the restriction that NE imposes (that all things with identity are existent). 2.3. Rejecting TB via SET or NE To burn the bridge that leads us to TB we can deny the biconditional reading of NE, in particular by denying the direction Right-Left by showing that non-existents can have identity and can go in a domain, and thus we quantify over non-existents, so is neutral. To do this we need to find non-existents which meet the determinate identity conditions imposed by SET. Or, we can simply reject SET by denying the set-theoretic version of model theory that requires domains to be sets with determinate identity conditions. To do this we need to show that we can quantify over things that lack determinate identity conditions. In the rest of this section I explore these options of rejecting either SET or NE. Quine s NE is motivated by his issue with the possible fat man in the doorway. 6 The problem with this man is that there is no determinate answer as to whether he is identical to the possible tall man in the doorway. Without there being a determinate answer as to whether one is identical with another is for those things to lack determinate identity. For Quine, not having determinate identity goes against what it is to be an object or an existent entity. So the possible fat man doesn t qualify. For Quine this may be just a plea to stop talking about possibilia, but it has the effect of restricting domains. The question is whether NE is motivated by the possible fat man being an illegitimate thing to talk about or by such talk problematically introducing him as an object into the domain as existent. If being in the domain has no ontological significance and only signifies that we talk of that thing then it seems unproblematic to talk of possibilia it seems only problematic if quantification is loaded to give you existent possible fat men. Yet Quine s identity constraint on domains and its entities is defended as he thinks it affords our resultant theory a degree of clarity and definiteness. But I hope to demonstrate that it is not necessary to impose such a constraint, and so quantification without Quine s add-ons is naturally ontologically neutral. 6 W. V. O. Quine, From A Logical Point Of View (Harvard University Press, 1961), 4. 6

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 259 260 261 262 263 264 265 266 267 268 269 270 271 272 273 274 275 276 277 278 279 280 281 282 283 284 285 286 287 288 289 290 291 292 293 294 295 296 297 298 299 300 301 The biconditional NE ensures that all and only existents have determinate identity conditions, and this is a substantial and controversial claim which makes Quine s logic heavily theory-laden. We needn t accept such a heavy load with our logic though, and in rejecting NE we can reject Quine s ontologically loaded logic. Firstly, it is not clear that all existent things meet Quine s identity conditions (and as such the conditions are not necessary), and secondly, some non-existent things may meet those identity conditions too (and as such are not sufficient). By not being necessary we deny the direction Left-Right by showing that we can have an entity without identity, and by not being sufficient we deny the direction Right-Left by showing that we can have non-existents with identity. So even if the domain is restricted by SET to include only those things with determinate identity conditions, this set of things need not be a set of existent things, and thus we cannot look to the domain to provide us with an ontology. Determinate identity may not be necessary nor sufficient for existence, and so would not pick out all and only existents, and so even if the domain is restricted by SET to have determinate identity this may not restrict the domain to all and only existents. In contesting whether NE is true, by seeing if determinate identity is necessary for existence, we must cite existent things without determinate identity. As stated before, to have determinate identity means that for all a and all b there must be a definite answer as to whether a=b. Let us consider numbers as an example. Benacerraf 7 notes there are many potential reductions from numbers to sets, but since there is no principled way to choose between them then there is no definite answer as to which, if any, sets the numbers are. So if numbers exist they do not meet the condition from NE. Many philosophers of mathematics in the structuralist tradition take the lesson of this to be that numbers exist but without determinate identity, denying NE. Other examples to show that determinate identity is not necessary for existents may include vague objects. 8 There are also examples in modern science of existents without having determinate identity conditions, such as fermions and bosons in Bose-Einstein statistics. 9 Azzouni 10 denies NE by showing that determinate identity 7 Paul Benacerraf, What Numbers Could Not Be, Philosophical Review 74 (1965), 62. 8 See Gareth Evans, Can There Be Vague Objects?, Analysis 28 (1978), for arguments against this. 9 Cie & Stoneham Let the occult quality go, European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 5.1 (2009) 87. 10 J. Azzouni, Deflating Existential Consequence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 101. 7

Suki Finn 302 303 304 305 306 307 308 309 310 311 312 313 314 315 316 317 318 319 320 321 322 323 324 325 326 327 328 329 330 331 332 333 334 335 336 337 338 339 340 341 342 343 344 is not sufficient for existents as non-existent fictional things may meet the condition by stipulation. Thus the biconditional NE may be too strong and would not be a constraint on domain specification, and by rejecting the biconditional in some direction we break the argument that leads to TB, leaving logic naturally neutral. But if we feel compelled to allow for the biconditional NE, then in order to prevent the restriction on our domains to only existents we would thus have to reject SET. This would allow for things without determinate identity conditions into the domain, and NE would merely state that those things in the domain with determinate identity conditions will also be those things in the domain that exist. To reject SET is to deny the set-theoretic version of model theory, and so is to deny that domains are sets. It is standard to take domains as sets however this leads to problems that may motivate its rejection anyway. For example, when domains are sets we cannot have unrestricted universal quantification. This is because unrestricted quantification requires an unrestricted domain, and if the domain is a set then this requires the set to be unrestricted. Such an unrestricted set is a set of everything, which will therefore contain itself, opening the way to Russell s Paradox. So, treating domains as sets can lead to paradox. If one wants to allow for unrestricted quantification or an unrestricted domain, as Quine seems to (as he answers the question of what exists with everything! ), then one needs to deny SET to avoid ending up in Russell s Paradox. This allows for us to quantify over things without determinate identity conditions, and prevents the move from SET to the biconditional NE that leads us to TB which loads in turn. 2.4. Rejecting TB via quantification If Quine has an argument for TB it s a poor one, depending on a biconditional reading of NE, a paradoxical acceptance of SET, or an unmotivated statement that quantification being loaded is simply trivial and obvious. We can deny SET or NE as done above to block getting to TB, or we can provide independent reasons for neutral quantification to show that not only is Quine s loaded reading unmotivated but also is not at all trivial or obvious. I will now deny TB by looking at what quantification is in natural and formal languages. As described earlier, there could be two reasons why one may hold that quantification is ontologically loaded: (1) because is a regimentation of the ordinary language there exists and this is already ontologically loaded; (2) because is ontologically 8

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 345 346 347 348 349 350 351 352 353 354 355 356 357 358 359 360 361 362 363 364 365 366 367 368 369 370 371 372 373 374 375 376 377 378 379 380 381 382 383 384 385 386 387 loaded by virtue of its semantics. These reasons correspond to the two issues I clarify in the next two sections: (1) whether quantification in natural language is ontologically committing; (2) whether quantification in formal language is ontologically committing. I argue that quantification in both English and first order logic are ontologically neutral, and that examples of uses of quantification in natural and formal languages provide evidence against TB and do not support Quine s triviality thesis, whereas neutral quantification is consistent with the evidence. 3. Natural language quantification is neutral In this section I attack the assumption that quantification in natural language can be ontologically committing. I will explain why it is incorrect to say there exists is synonymous with some in English 11 to show why there exists is not quantificational and how some (along with other quantified idioms) is ontologically neutral. cannot represent the meaning and logical role of both some and there exists in English (and cognates in other natural languages) since exists is not quantificational (but rather is a predicate). Quantified sentences have nothing to do with existence they shouldn t require existence for their truth or meaning, and they shouldn t imply ontological commitment. If some is to mean at least one existent thing, then there will be no difference between some and there exists. Burgess and Rosen for instance argue it is not easy to understand what the difference can be. 12 Priest responds that they could simply reflect on the sentence I thought of something I would like to give you as a Christmas present but I couldn t get it for you as it doesn t exist. 13 Here, the something cannot mean some existent thing as it would be contradictory. However, other quantified some sentences do appear to be ontologically loaded, like some beers are in my fridge, which will be true only if there exists beer in my fridge. Here however, it is not the some that is giving the appearance of 11 Though I focus on English, since quantificational logic is meant to be a formalization of idioms in a range of natural languages, my discussion has a global scope across other languages too. 12 J. P. Burgess and G. Rosen, A Subject With No Object (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 224. 13 G. Priest, Towards Non-Being (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005), 152. 9

Suki Finn 388 389 390 391 392 393 394 395 396 397 398 399 400 401 402 403 404 405 406 407 408 409 410 411 412 413 414 415 416 417 418 419 420 421 422 423 424 425 426 427 428 429 430 ontological loading, rather the in my fridge is. Some needn t require existence, but to be physically in my fridge does. Furthermore, some cannot require existence since that would entail that we cannot talk truly of some non-existent things without contradiction. For example, some mice have American accents is arguably true due to Mickey Mouse, yet we do not feel that the truth of this commits us to his existence. This is contrasted with there do not exist mice with American accents to articulate lack of ontological commitment. Priest s example is a variant of a famous example of Strawson s, 14 who points to a dictionary of legendary and mythical characters and says, with regard to the characters, some of these exist and some of them don t exist. The seemingly loaded word here is exist, and some must be considered neutral, to prevent the contradiction in the second disjunct there exist some characters that don t exist. To account for sentences such as this without contradiction, we must be able to use some in an ontologically neutral way. This points towards the ordinary usage of quantification in natural language to be ontologically neutral. Furthermore, there may be no way of making sense of our fictional practice but to quantify over fictional entities, and as such we must ensure that quantification is neutral to avoid commitment to such fictional entities. Treating the quantifier as ontologically neutral, and distinguishing some as a quantifier and exists as a predicate, will gain expressive resources for sentences which contain both some and not exist (like the examples above) in order to prevent contradictions. One may protest that some just by definition means at least one existent thing and these examples can thus be dealt with by being not strictly speaking true. They could argue that all such examples are a misuse of language that is parasitic on their use of some, and are properly interpreted as involving a cancelling prefix to create a more accurate sentence such as in Disney there exists at least one mouse that has an American accent to make it true. Those who adopt such a reading will argue that all uses of some are loaded until it is cancelled by such a prefix, otherwise the sentence will just be false if it involves non-existent things. However such a strategy will not work for Priest and Strawson s examples, which involve a true sentence and a neutral use of the word some, where no prefix will easily fit. These examples give cases when you quantify over a domain of objects some of which are existent and some are not, so you cannot prefix your quantification to explain what is going on. This is since only part of the sentence will pertain to non-existents 14 Peter Strawson, Is Existence Never A Predicate?, Critica 1 (1967), 13. 10

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 431 432 433 434 435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443 444 445 446 447 448 449 450 451 452 453 454 455 456 457 458 459 460 461 462 463 464 465 466 467 468 469 470 471 472 473 and another part of the same sentence pertains to existents, and so an overarching cancelling prefix for the whole sentence will not do since only part of the sentence will require the commitment to be cancelled. So far I have thus argued that, against Quine, cannot be a regimentation of the ordinary language there exists in virtue of it carrying ontological commitment, since quantificational terms in natural language like some are ontologically un-committing. In the next section I further argue against Quine that cannot be ontologically loaded in virtue of its semantics either, since the semantics of the quantifier in formal language are ontologically neutral. I show quantification in formal languages like first order predicate logic to be ontologically neutral, and therefore unregimented quantification in natural language is neutral too. 4. Formal language quantification is neutral Reading as there exists is incorrect, as there exists is not a quantificational phrase. properly understood is simply some. The difference between some and there exists is that some is an ontologically neutral quantificational term, and there exists is not a quantificational term at all. Some is about the number of things (namely only some of them), and so is quantitative, whereas there exists describes the way things are (namely as existing things), and so is qualitative. The word some is fit for numerical quantificational use, and there exists is not. As a suggestion, exists may be better understood as a predicate, as cannot be the logical regimentation of the non-quantificational there exists. The reason there exists is not quantificational can be motivated by looking to Generalized Quantifier Theory (GQT) 15. According to GQT a quantificational noun phrase is made up of a determiner and noun. Determiners are words like some, all, a, most, five. (Determiners, I argue, can be taken as ontologically neutral since we can talk about five unicorns for example). Nouns include words like numbers, cats, objects. So, it is true that the sentence there is a number that is prime between 2 and 4 is a quantified sentence, but it is false that the quantifier is there is. Actually, the quantifier is a number, with a being a determiner and number being a noun. The there is is part of the existential construction, and is not 15 Thomas Hofweber, Innocent Statements and their Metaphysically Loaded Counterparts, Philosophers Imprint 7.1 (2007), 23, and L. Gamut Logic, Language and Meaning (Chicago, 1991). 11

Suki Finn 474 475 476 477 478 479 480 481 482 483 484 485 486 487 488 489 490 491 492 493 494 495 496 497 498 499 500 501 502 503 504 505 506 507 508 509 510 511 512 513 514 515 516 part of the quantification, and sometimes is not even existential, for example there are many clever detectives, some of which do not exist, where there are and some are both ontologically neutral. The quantification itself is neutral, located in the determiner and noun. Therefore in logic translates to the neutral quantifier some in English, rather than the non-quantificational there exists. The argument for quantifiers being neutral can be strengthened by looking at the connection between the two quantifiers and. Berto asks, why existential? The dual of universal is not existential, but particular. 16 As such, the dual of all is some, and not there exists. This can be demonstrated by considering the intertranslatability between and where one quantifier is defined in terms of the other: x(cx)= x( Cx) and x(cx)= x( Cx). Furthermore, when we look to the numerical quantities of such words, we can see that is 0%<n 100% ( some ) and so as n=100% ( all ) is an instance of. Therefore, x(φ)x x(φ)x should be a valid inference, since whatever is true of all of the x is true of some of the x. For example, when I have eaten all the cakes it is true that I have eaten some of the cakes. What is true in the universal case ought to carry over to the particular case. However when the particular case is ontologically loaded in virtue of reading (incorrectly) as there exists, then when we infer the particular case from the universal we therefore can prove that something exists. We can thus somehow derive ontology from logical inferences if we accept x(φ)x x(φ)x as valid and take to be ontologically loaded. The above inference x(φ)x x(φ)x is therefore taken as invalid when you allow for domains to include non-existent things, or to be empty, and treat as loaded. Classical logicians have responded by not allowing for empty domains, and Quineans respond by not allowing for non-existent things in domains, in order to retain the validity of the inference and not prove the existence of the things they do not want in their ontology. This is because if we do allow for an empty domain or for domains to include non-existents, whilst we can hypothesize about what all the x would be like in the universal part of the inference, we cannot say anything about a particular x since this requires existence when we read as loaded. Yet my response is that we should take to be ontologically neutral and simply to mean >0%, so that the inference is valid, even when the domain contains non-existents (or is empty). This ensures that we cannot derive 16 F. Berto, Existence as a Real Property (Synthese Library: Springer, 2012), 21. 12

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 517 518 519 520 521 522 523 524 525 526 527 528 529 530 531 532 533 534 535 536 537 538 539 540 541 542 543 544 545 546 547 548 549 550 551 552 553 554 555 556 557 558 559 ontology from logic. We can keep the consistencyand inter-translatability between and by treating them both as ontologically neutral, which allows them to quantify over domains that contain whatever it is that we speak about. And these domains can be neutrally specified by a meta-language. Formal languages like first order predicate logic are interpreted with model theory. The model theory for a language is a specification of a model, which consists of a domain and for every 1-place predicate an extension which is a subset of the domain, and for every n-place predicate a set of n-tuples of members of the domain. There are two rules for the quantifiers in our formal language of logic: ( ) when at least one element of the domain is in the extension of the predicate; ( ) when all elements of the domain are in the extension of the predicate. We specify the domain, and specify the extension of the predicates. Thus far there has been no mention of existence or ontology in the meta-language of model theory, and so the model is naturally metaphysically quiet. The metaphysical noise comes through not in the quantification but in the specification of the domain to be quantified over if the domain is specified in a metaphysical or ontologically loaded way then quantifying over it will also be loaded. Quantification is only committal if the specification of the domain in the model theory is committal. And whether domain specification is committal depends upon whether the metalanguage in which the model theory is couched is itself committal. Model theory doesn t require an ontology and ensures that formal languages have no ontological commitments, so that quantification is neutral. Quine s background rules for inclusion in a domain isn t neutral, and this is where ontology is smuggled in, through the back door of domain specification. In practice, whatever the natural language of English can talk about can go in a domain. Any further restriction (like Quine s) is therefore not part of standard model theory. The point of looking at the model theoretic approach to semantics is to show that it is done in an ontologically neutral way, and that the metaphysics is an addition that is not necessary and may be incorrect. Quine included this addition due to his preconception of what things exist (not including the possible fat man in the doorway). He thus looked to what he thought existed in order to derive his loaded logic which was then used to tell us what exists. So it seems he constructed logic to fit around his premade metaphysical ideas. Quine s method as such is circular (he calls it holistic ), as he decides on his ontology and molds identity conditions to fit, then these conditions deliver ontological results. Azzouni makes a similar remark: One can t read ontological 13

Suki Finn 560 561 562 563 564 565 566 567 568 569 570 571 572 573 574 575 576 577 578 579 580 581 582 583 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 598 599 600 601 602 commitments from semantic conditions unless one has already smuggled into those semantic conditions the ontology one would like to read off 17 and this is precisely what Quine does. It s circular to get ontology from logic given how Quine choses his logic to fit his ontology. We thus get a circular criterion for existing (to be in the domain) and for being in a domain (to exist). 5. Domains in scientific theories Azzouni argues that Quine is wrong to equate the ontology of a science with the domain of discourse of that science, and as such it is wrong to equate the ontological commitments of the science with its quantificational commitments. Therefore, if TB is applied to the sciences (which for Quine and the scientific realist it specifically is), we will end up with incorrect results. Azzouni clarifies that sometimes domains and ontologies overlap for a scientific subject but mostly domains include other things that are not part of the ontology, and also may not include all things that are part of the ontology studied by that scientific subject: There isn t anything, I think, that can (or should) be said in general about the nature of the overlap (if any) between the domain of a scientific language Ls and the actual ontology of (or that underlies, i.e., involves the truth-value inducers of) the phenomena being studied. 18 If this is the case then this shows that being bound by a quantifier is neither necessary nor sufficient for existence in the case of scientific theorizing. Azzouni explains that scientists do not care for domains to contain all and only existents: Scientists formulate domains of discourse and the vocabulary items that refer to the contents of those domains of discourse in ways that maximize successful applications of scientific doctrine to phenomena studied. That what is in those domains doesn t strictly speaking exist, is of no scientific concern. 19 17 J. Azzouni, Deflating Existential Consequence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 55. 18 J. Azzouni, Talking About Nothing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 169. 19 Ibid., 216. 14

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 603 604 605 606 607 608 609 610 611 612 613 614 615 616 617 618 619 620 621 622 623 624 625 626 627 628 629 630 631 632 633 634 635 636 637 638 639 640 641 642 643 644 645 For example, scientists work with idealized situations, as Leng states, in dealing with frictionless planes or in treating liquids as continuous substances in fluid dynamics. 20 Since such things are spoken of in science for the purpose of successful theorizing, they will feature in our domain of quantification. Such a domain should not then be treated as the set of things that make up our ontology, as included in that domain are these idealized non-existent things. If scientific realism takes quantification to be committing in this Quinean way then the realist becomes ontologically committed to too much. But, as Leng describes: Quine has a story to tell about the use of such idealizations, in order to explain why their occurrence in our scientific theory doesn t require our belief in their existence. According to Quine, they are linguistic conveniences that can be replaced by literally true paraphrases. 21 However, if Quine and the scientific realist are to take all successful cases of reference (and thus all true quantified statements) in our best scientific theorizing as being ontologically committing, then every case of idealization and the non-literal will require paraphrasing to prevent being quantified over. And as Maddy has argued for, it is clear that the method of Quinean paraphrase will not successfully eliminate idealizations from natural science. 22 Therefore, I argue that it is also clear that the method of Quinean ontological commitment through quantification will not successfully establish the ontology from natural science. Scientific realism traditionally follows this Quinean methodology, and takes it that we should believe in the ontology from our scientific theories, as our scientific terms will successfully refer to existent things. Scientific realists should drop this Quinean use of quantification, and redefine their position accordingly. Quantifying over the scientific domain with quantifiers such as some and all is inappropriate for deriving ontology. Some is ontologically neutral since logic is only interested in quantifying over a formal domain, and this has ontological significance only depending on the constraints on (and specification of) inclusion in a domain to restrict the domain. When the domain is restricted, the 20 Mary Leng, What s Wrong With Indispensibility?, Synthese 131 (2002), 399. 21 Ibid., 399. 22 P. Maddy, Naturalism in Mathematics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 145. 15

Suki Finn 646 647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654 655 656 657 658 659 660 661 662 663 664 665 666 667 668 669 670 671 672 673 674 675 676 677 678 679 680 681 682 683 684 685 686 687 688 quantifiers will only be able to quantify over things that made it through the constraint. Logic, without such constraints, is ontologically neutral. The constraint of being part of the best scientific theory will have to be independently motivated to restrict to only the existent things, but as others have argued it seems that the domains in our scientific theories are not fit to be taken as sets of existent things. Furthermore I have shown that first order logic needn t be existentially loaded by looking to model theory to show how quantification stripped down is ontologically neutral. It is only in Quine s background rules from SET and NE that restrict what can be quantified over to give quantification ontological significance. Model theory has no ontological commitments, showing that the domain is not the set of existents, and as such formal languages are naturally neutral. I have denied TB, via rejecting SET and NE and showing that quantification is neutral, as it s not the logic that supports loaded quantification, it s just Quinean rhetoric about possible fat men motivating restrictions on domains, making them loaded. Without such a domain restriction, quantification ceases to have anything to do with existence. As Berto nicely summarises: [Neutral] quantifiers had better be called just quantifiers. Existentially committing quantification is restricted quantification. 23 And what I have argued in this paper, is that such restricted quantification to only existent things is unmotivated and incorrect, and certainly is not trivial and obvious as Quine states. Quantification is thus naturally ontologically neutral, and cannot be used to derive ontology from the domain of our best scientific theory. Conclusion Quantification becomes ontologically loaded when the domain that is being quantified over is restricted to include only existent things. In this way, the realist can then look to the values of bound variables in scientific theories for their ontology, with the quantifier being the signifier of ontological commitment. thus becomes ontologically loaded and read as there exists, due to this domain restriction. But without such a restriction, quantification ceases to have anything to do with existence, and the quantifier should be read as some and known as the particular as there is nothing existential about it at all. I therefore conclude that scientific realism, being the position 23 F. Berto, Existence as a Real Property (Synthese Library: Springer, 2012), 72. 16

The Role of Existential Quantification in Scientific Realism 689 690 691 692 693 694 695 696 697 698 699 700 701 702 703 704 705 706 707 708 709 710 711 712 713 714 715 716 717 718 719 720 721 722 723 724 725 726 727 728 729 730 731 that takes quantifying over our best scientific theories to be ontologically committing, is either false or requires redefining without presupposing such a problematic view about quantification. 24 SUKI FINN (suki.finn@soton.ac.uk) is a Research Fellow at the University of Southampton. Her recent publications include Metametametaphysics and Dialetheism (Australasian Journal of Logic, 2016), Dissolving Yablo s Hostage Crisis: In Defence of Defiance (Australasian Philosophical Review, 2016), and Humean Supervenience Rebugged (Philosophia, 2014). 24 Special thanks goes to Mary Leng, Keith Allen, Tom Stoneham, Francesco Berto, and Graham Priest, for their very helpful comments, and to the audiences of the 20 th Amsterdam Colloquium 2015 (University of Amsterdam), the 1 st Epistemology of Metaphysics workshop (University of Helsinki), and the Mind and Reason group at the University of York, where I presented this paper. 17