Human rights, universalism and conserving human rights practice

Similar documents
University of St Andrews DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY. PY 4652, The Philosophy of Human Rights (2016)

Clarifications on What Is Speciesism?

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Freedom of Religion as a Distinct. Human Right

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

Four Asymmetries Between Moral and Epistemic Trustworthiness Susann Wagenknecht, Aarhus University

The Prospective View of Obligation

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Why Good Science Is Not Value-Free

POLITICAL SECULARISM AND PUBLIC REASON. THREE REMARKS ON AUDI S DEMOCRATIC AUTHORITY AND THE SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

UPI 2205 Ethics and the Environment

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN:

Postscript: Reply to McLeod

Hannah Arendt and the fragility of human dignity

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Your signature doesn t mean you endorse the guidelines; your comments, when added to the Annexe, will only enrich and strengthen the document.

The Discounting Defense of Animal Research

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Skepticism and Internalism

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Practical Wisdom and Politics

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

What Is Speciesism? Oscar Horta. ABSTRACT: In spite of the considerable literature nowadays existing on the issue of the moral

Ethical Analysis: PRINCIPLISM. Patrick T. Smith, Ph.D.

The Foundations of Capability Theory: Comparing Nussbaum and Gewirth

"Book Review: FRANKFURT, Harry G. On Inequality. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2015, 102 pp., $14.95 (hbk), ISBN

SOME CONSEQUENCES OF MICHAEL THOMSON S LIFE AND ACTION FOR SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SUPPLEMENTARY VOLUME LIFE AND ACTION IN ETHICS AND POLITICS ITALO TESTA

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis

Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, Pp $90.00 (cloth); $28.99

Our responsibility towards future generations. Lars Löfquist, Theology Department

Judging Subsistence Rights by their Duties Eric Boot

What s God got to do with it?

Do not open this examination paper until instructed to do so. Section A: answer one question. Section B: answer one question.

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

Human Dignity 1. Universität Zürich Institut für Sozialethik Prof. Dr. Johannes Fischer November in Zürich.

What Should We Believe?

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Buddhist Psychology: The Mind That Mindfulness Discloses

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2)

Philosophy HL 1 IB Course Syllabus

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

Postface. Locke s theory of personal identity links four fundamental notions: identity, consciousness, concern, and responsibility.

A Contractualist Reply

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

Rethinking Development: the Centrality of Human Rights

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

THE FOUNDATIONS OF CAPABILITY THEORY: COMPARING NUSSBAUM AND GEWIRTH

The ontology of human rights and obligations

International Environmental Law, Policy, and Ethics

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

THE UNITY OF THE MORAL COMMUNITY

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

The Earth Charter and Global Ethics. Nigel Dower

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Act individuation and basic acts

KNOWLEDGE ESSENTIALLY BASED UPON FALSE BELIEF

Contemporary Social and Moral Problems in the U.S.

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

Democracy and epistemology: a reply to Talisse

Student Learning Outcomes Assessment Plan. Department of Theology. Saint Peter s College. Fall Submitted by Maria Calisi, Ph.D.

Philosophy Courses-1

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

Transcription:

Human rights, universalism and conserving human rights practice Draft 30th May 2016 -do not circulate or quote- Dr. Gerhard Bos, Ethics Institute Utrecht University g.h.bos2@uu.nl One objection to the recognition of human rights for future people is that human rights existence, attribution and contents depend on a postwar agreement at the international level. In others words, human beings had no human rights before that and future people will have human rights only if and to the extent these will be recognized for them (Beitz, 2003; Raz, 2010). What is more, the content of human rights depends on postwar agreements at the international level, which were primarily a response to the atrocities in the world war although they have had and continue to have their development today. Although there has been some recognition of the environmental aspects of human rights, this has been insufficient to focus the debate on long-term sustainability via human rights (Knox, 2009; Woods, 2010; Bos and Düwell, 2016; Düwell and Bos, 2016). In moral philosophy, the question of long-term environmental responsibility has been discussed in a variety of theoretical frameworks. There are approaches that focus on our responsibilities regarding non-human nature as such; but also those pointing that treat our environmental responsibilities as a function of satisfying the basic needs of human beings both present and future (Boylan, 2001; DesJardins, 2006). Some of the latter approaches ground in a moral understanding of human rights, i.e., the key idea of inherent dignity as the foundation of equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family. On the moral understanding of human rights, human rights practices would be interpreted critically as ramifications of a normative core (Shue, 1996; Claassen and Düwell, 2012; Waldron, 2013). The moral understanding of human rights is targeted by a variety of charges that are raised in the context of intergeneration justice more generally, which has lead to a variety of what I call direct approaches to the protection of the rights of future people (Bos, 2016). The challenges raised concern the non-existence, non-identity of future persons; reciprocity issues our independence from them; as well as the impracticability given epistemically uncertain connections between action and harm and the indeterminateness of the victim etc. I will sidestep these concerns for a moment, although I assert that my arguments in what follows avoids them. 1

The moral understanding of human rights faces the following challenge: human rights may not have significant bearing on future people. The challenge, framed in this way, would allow for at least two readings. On a first understanding, unknowns concerning our impact on the planet s future as well as unknowns about future a person s needs and circumstances, would make it problematic to frame and tackle the question of long term responsibilities in terms of the human rights institutions as we have them. This points at issues related to a second one, i.e., the determinate character of human rights, i.e. that it s origin, specification and justification are primarily a matter of postwar international negotiations that although ongoing, are primarily in response to the atrocities of that war. In other words, the human rights practices as we have them should not be interpreted as voicing the ramifications of the core idea of human rights that is central to a moral understanding of human rights. In other words: whether human rights practical apply to questions of long-term environmental responsibility, does not boil down to the question whether the normative core idea would require recognition of the environmental circumstances of future people to have their rights secure The argument from human rights that I develop regarding the environmental condition of future persons avoids making assumptions about the justification, specification and draws only from the conditions of attributing human rights. Instead I will argue that, in conditions of temporal overlap between the lives of human beings, full recognition of human rights for our present contemporaries concerns the conservation of human rights institutions over time. What such conservation entails would an interesting question. I will pick up on that later in this paper, but for now let me draw out the relevance of recognizing one way in which human rights can be said to be universal. There is no denying that human rights are attributed on universal grounds, they are rights to be attributed to a human being without discrimination. In other words, human rights theory and practice is vitally committed to what I call the human rights conditional If x is a human person, then x should have, qua human being, certain rights secured for him What I will do is elaborate the human rights conditional as one that, in conditions of partial overlap between lives of human persons, entails that we should be concerned with the possibility of that conditional to hold true in our lives and beyond. It should hold in our future and for that to be the case, I argue, the possibility that it holds true should be conserved for our future contemporaries, theirs and so on. 2

I have characterized conditions of partial overlap as follows: (t1) (t2) (t3) Members of generation A exist; members of generation B do not exist; members of generation C do not exist. Members of generation A exist; members of generation B exist; members of generation C do not exist. Members of generation A do not exist; members of generation B exist; members of generation C exist. In time, there is a chain between individual members of different generations based on a partial overlap of members of different generations. At t1, members of B are future contemporaries of members of A, while at t2, members of C will be future contemporaries of members of B. I will refer to this as the assumption of partial overlap. (Bos, 2016, pp. 108 9) For theories of intergenerational justice the basic task is to account for current obligations regarding future non-contemporaries (Gardiner, 2003; Gosseries, 2008). This task can be approached in at least two ways. On the first, direct approach the claim is that we have duties to future people, primarily in response to their future human needs. On the second, indirect approach, our duties to our contemporaries require recognition of duties regarding certain conditions in the future say because of normatively relevant chain of connections between current contemporaries, future contemporaries and future non-contemporaries. This is not the place to delve deeper into differences between these approaches, but I would like to emphasize that they may in principle be compatible and may require recognition of them as two sides of the same coin. Notwithstanding this, they are two approaches that should be assessed in their own terms especially since both face different objections. I think that once we combine the human rights conditional and assumption of partial overlap, we get a normative perspective on the continuation of our human rights practices including the task to keep the environmental preconditions of these practices in line with that perspective. Forget for a moment about the question whether or not we owe it to future people to leave them a hospitable environment. At least we owe it to each other to advance our human rights institutions and practices. We cannot allow for a treatment of the environment, so that the contents of human rights can only be secured for us, currently living, now and in our future, and for others only if and to the extent they are our contemporaries. 3

I have referred to this idea as the chain of status. Roughly, the idea is that our status as bearer of human rights is relevantly connected with those of our future contemporaries, which in turn is again relevantly connected with those of their future contemporaries even given that the latter are non-contemporaries for us. We should be concerned with the possibility that, in our future, rights are secured for us simply in response to our being human. That is to say, not necessarily because of the inner significance of human beings, but at least because we are committed to human rights institutions institutions in which rights are to be attributed to human persons without discrimination. In other words, the truth of the human rights conditions should be possible into the future of us currently living. For that to be the case, it should be possible for our future contemporaries to have the same rights secured for them simply in response to their being human then and in their future. This in turn implies, it should be possible for their future contemporaries and so on ad infinitum. Note that this possibility would not obtain, if these rights would be secured for them only as long as they live with us. For in that case, the rights would be secured for humans qua being our contemporaries. That would be a discriminatory specification of the human rights condition, which is fundamentally at odds with the human rights conditional. Hence, the possibility that certain rights are secured in our future for us qua humans, requires the possibility that the very same rights are secured for our future contemporaries as humans while we live together and beyond that. Hence conditions of partial overlap require us to advance the robustness of institutions that secure human rights, and that for relatively formal reasons. This may seem to boil down to a rather inflexible conservatism of current human rights practices. Not only would it require concern for the securability of all and any human right currently recognized, it would also demand concern for the institutions that are needed for their securability. At the same time, one can wonder whether such conservatism is warranted, in the face of the environmental threats we face. To get rid of this sort of inflexible conservatism of human rights practices, I suggest, we would have to draw them together and critically reconstruct them in terms of central normative commitments which then will allow us to focus the question of what should be securable and what institutions are up to that task. Let me return to one of the objections that I raised earlier about the determinate character of human rights. This objection emphasizes that origin, specification and justification of human rights are primarily the results of postwar international negotiations arguably aimed to address the future possibility of atrocities like that of that war. I think that the chain of status requires international politics to be vitally concerned about the possibilities of securing 4

human rights into the future that is if they are committed to these practices. The only feasible way of doing so is by setting priorities on what requires protection as a human right, and accommodating institutionally so that the possibility of these protections is secured in the prospect of future environmental threats. This in the end, I assume requires a moral philosophical understanding of what it is that matters about human beings; and what we need institutions for to secure it (Düwell, forthcoming). References Beitz, C. (2003) What Human Rights Mean, Daedalus, 132(1), pp. 36 46. Bos, G. (2016) A Chain of Status, in Bos, G. and Düwell, M. (eds) Human Rights and Sustainability. Routledge, pp. 107 20. Bos, G. and Düwell, M. (eds) (2016) Human Rights and Sustainability: Moral responsibilities for the future. London; New York: Routledge (Routledge Studies in Sustainability). Boylan, M. (2001) Environmental Ethics. New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Claassen, R. and Düwell, M. (2012) The Foundations of Capability Theory: Comparing Nussbaum and Gewirth, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16(3), pp. 493 510. doi: 10.1007/s10677-012-9361-8. DesJardins, J. R. (2006) Environmental ethics: an introduction to environmental philosophy. Belmont, Calif.: Thomson Wadsworth. Düwell, M. (forthcoming) Human dignity and intergenerational human rights, in Bos, G. and Düwell, M. (eds) Human Rights and Sustainability. Routledge. Düwell, M. and Bos, G. (2016) Human rights and future people Possibilities of argumentation, Journal of Human Rights, 15(2), pp. 231 250. doi: 10.1080/14754835.2015.1118341. Gardiner, S. (2003) The Pure Intergenerational Problem, The Monist, 86(3), pp. 481 500. Gosseries, A. (2008) Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis, S.A.P.I.EN.S. Surveys and Perspectives Integrating Environment and Society, (1.1). Available at: http://sapiens.revues.org/165 (Accessed: 10 March 2015). Knox, J. H. (2009) Climate Change and Human Rights Law. SSRN Scholarly Paper ID 1480120. Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network. Available at: http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1480120 (Accessed: 3 June 2015). Raz, J. (2010) Human Rights Without Foundations, in The Philosphy of International Law. Oxford University Press. 5

Shue, H. (1996) Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy. Princeton University Press. Waldron, J. (2013) Is Dignity the Foundation of Human Rights? SSRN Scholarly Paper ID 2196074. Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network. Available at: http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=2196074 (Accessed: 17 March 2014). Woods, K. (2010) Human Rights and Environmental Sustainability. Edward Elgar Publishing. 6