Review Richard Sorabji, Self: Ancient and Modern Insights about Individuality, Life, and Death

Similar documents
Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Attila Németh, Epicurus On the Self

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Dr. Tuomas E. Tahko 12 January 2012

UNIVERSITY OF MALTA THE MATRICULATION EXAMINATION ADVANCED LEVEL

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

What am I? Life after death

PHIL U282: FREE WILL AND DETERMINISM Loyola University of New Orleans, Fall 2016, Dr. Ben Bayer

Metaphysical atomism and the attraction of materialism.

Mary Cassatt, The First Mirror, captures the shared attention with mother through which infants first distinguish themselves from other people; the

Proto-egoism [DRAFT] Over the last forty years, as the rest of analytic philosophy of mind has taken an

Pointing at the Moon: Buddhism, Logic, Analytic Philosophy 2009 Oxford University Press, Inc. (pp )

Creighton University, Oct. 13, 2016 Midwest Area Workshop on Metaphysics, Oct. 14, 2016

What Really Matters. If our lives were truly horrible and the prospects of their getting better hopelessly dim,

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

IS PERSONAL IDENTITY WHAT MATTERS?

Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 73, No. 1; March 1995

Plato Phaedo. An overview of body / soul / immortality. OCR training programme GCE Religious Studies

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Dominican School of Philosophy and Theology PH/HS 1050 History of Philosophy: Ancient

Contents. Introduction 8

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

History of Political Thought I: Justice, Virtue, and the Soul

NEUROSCIENCE AND THE SOUL: CONTEXTUALIZED SCIENCE IN THE LIBERAL ARTS COLLEGE

6AANA014 Hellenistic Philosophy Syllabus Academic year 2016/7

Causal Co-personality: In defence of the psychological continuity theory

PL 407 HISTORY OF MEDIEVAL PHILOSOPHY Spring 2012

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

Would it matter all that much if there were no selves? (31 May 2006 Draft)

The self, part II: personal identity as psychological continuity

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation

Philosophy 169: Eastern and Western Philosophy Reason, Suffering, and the Self T/H 4:15-5:30 Walsh 498

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Action in Special Contexts

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Lecture I.2: The PreSocratics (cont d)

Personal Identity. Raymond Martin. John Barresi. Edited by. and. Publishing

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2012/3

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

7AAN2027 Greek Philosophy II: Aristotle Syllabus Academic year 2013/4

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

What Matters in Survival: The Fission Problem, Life Trajectories, and the Possibility of Virtual Immersion

Mind and Body. Is mental really material?"

chapter 1 HISTORY AS PROLOGUE WESTERN THEORIES OF THE SELF john barresi raymond martin

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 : N A T U R E O F R E A L I T Y

History of Modern Philosophy Fall nd Paper Assignment Due: 11/8/2019

International Phenomenological Society

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

BEYOND CONCEPTUAL DUALISM Ontology of Consciousness, Mental Causation, and Holism in John R. Searle s Philosophy of Mind

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

131 seventeenth-century news

Tm: education of man is his journey through life on earth. The

It is Christ s true flesh which we take.

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Personal Identity and Ethics

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Intellectualism versus Voluntarism, and the Development of Natural Law from Zeno to Grotius.

Glossary of Terms Jim Pryor Princeton University 2/11/03

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

Introduction to Ethics Part 2: History of Ethics. SMSU Spring 2005 Professor Douglas F. Olena

The Moral Significance of Animal Pain and Animal Death. Elizabeth Harman. I. Animal Cruelty and Animal Killing

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

Eric Schliesser Philosophy and Moral Sciences, Ghent University ª 2011, Eric Schliesser

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Chapter 2 (Part II) Early Psychological Knowledge. PSK301-History of Psychology Assoc. Prof. Okan Cem Çırakoğlu

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Philosophy of Mind PHIL 255. Chris Eliasmith T/Th 4-5:20p AL 208

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

What does Nature mean?

Realism and instrumentalism

Trinity & contradiction

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Date Morning/Afternoon Time allowed: 2 hours

Epicurean: Introduction To The Epicurean Way Of Life By Alex Caras READ ONLINE

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

Aristotle and the Soul

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

Transcription:

Review Richard Sorabji, Self: Ancient and Modern Insights about Individuality, Life, and Death Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006 In this extraordinarily rich and provocative book by an eminent intellectual historian and philosopher, Richard Sorabji argues persuasively that there was an intense preoccupation among ancient western thinkers with self and related notions. In the process, he provides fresh translations and often novel interpretations of the most important passages relevant to this contention in a host of thinkers, including Homer, Epicharmus, Heraclitus, Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, Chrysippus, Cicero, Lucretius, Seneca, Plutarch, Epictetus, Hierocles, Marcus Aurelius, Tertullian, Origen, Alexander of Aphrodisias, Plotinus, Porphyry, Methodius, Themistius, Augustine, and Proclus, among others. Sorabji s nuanced, insightful, and often novel interpretations of passages from these and other writers are invariably woven together in an illuminating way, often with an eye to modern developments. There is no other book that covers the classical western material on self and related notions anywhere near as thoroughly or as perceptively. As a consequence for decades to come this book is destined to be a major point of departure for future discussion of classical authors on such issues. That in itself Page 1

is enough to make it an extraordinary resource for philosophers and classicists. But there is more. Sorabji argues convincingly that when it comes to modern philosophical discussions of self, while it may not be quite true that there is nothing new under the sun, there is much less new than is usually supposed. For instance, he finds a narrative account of the self in Plutarch and passages in Chrysippus and Philo that prefigure some of the issues that arose in our own times in connection with fission examples. And in his chapter devoted to Locke, tellingly entitled Memory: Locke s return to Epicureans and Stoics, he begins by noting that Locke almost surely read certain passages in De Rerum Natura in which Lucretius discusses whether one should be concerned about the sufferings of a replica of oneself, and then goes on to explain how the Stoic idea that each person is attached (Latin in Seneca: conciliari) to his or her bodily parts, and to his or her current constitution anticipates much that Locke had to say: A common English paraphrase is that each person appropriates his or her body, and this is fitting because the Greek word oikeiôsis is connected with oikos, the household, and the verb oikeioun would literally mean accepting into the household, accepting as one s own. Locke, we shall see, talks both of appropriation and of reconciling.... [The] Stoics, Chrysippus and Seneca, [also] Page 2

explain the idea of attachment... [as does] the Stoic Hierocles... (p104). This passage, I think, captures the flavor of many of Sorabji s not just erudite, but deeply erudite discussions of modern thinkers, in each of which he invariably displays an excellent feel for what is historically plausible. But Sorabji does not rest content with doing intellectual history. He also argues forcefully for the reality of the self. By a person, he says, I mean someone who has psychological states, and does things, which he says can be summed up by saying that a person owns psychological states and actions (p21). In this part of what he has to say, his foil is Parfitian reductionism, which he challenges not to argue for an immaterial self (or person), but for an embodied one. Sorabji argues that self-referential, indexicals I-thoughts not only have a unique action- and emotion-guiding force, but actually enter into our perceptions, helping not only to guide, but actually to constitute, many of our emotions, the fear of death being only one (p22). He concludes that there needs to be an owner of experiences, and not just because we talk that way, but for deeper metaphysical reasons. The only plausible owner, he says, is the embodied person (p267). In Sorabji s view, the basic difficulty with Parfitian reductionism, is that it treats Page 3

talk of ownership as a façon de parler that adds nothing, or at least nothing of importance, to the reductive components of a person (p267). On the contrary, Sorabji claims, talk of ownership not only does add information of importance, but ownership relations are real. Without ever committing himself to materialism, he nevertheless appears to be arguing for a kind of non-reductive materialism about selves (or persons). But he does not call his overall position non-reductive materialism or even say much more about what it is than I have explained. Sorabji does, though, argue at length that talk about people owning (i.e., having) their experiences and owning (i.e., performing) their actions is an ineliminable feature of the ways we do and should think about agency and ethics, that this by itself creates a presumption in favor of the reality of such ownership relations, and that one cannot make sense of talk of ownership on a reductive view. In contrast to Parfitian reductionism, in which persons (or selves) are reduced to a stream of psycho-physical events each of which is unified not [by] its belonging to one owner, but its occurring in one body or brain, Sorabji claims that what unifies such a stream is precisely its belonging to one owner (p269). On his way to this conclusion he succeeds in showing that there are difficulties with Parfit s view, not the least of which is the extraordinary Page 4

importance of I-thoughts to talk about agency and ethics. His having shown this is an accomplishment. However, if the thrust of his argument is correct, then there are serious problems not just with Parfit s view, but with reductionism in general. One might question how far Sorabji s argument go toward establishing this more general result. Consider, for instance, his claim that Parfitian reductionism lacks the resources it needs to link together the putative components of any given stream so as to distinguish it from other streams (p269). He defends this claim by pointing out that since Parfit allows that teletransportation preserves ownership he cannot replace belonging to a single owner with occurs in a single brain or body. True enough. But one could still retain the spirit of Parfit s view by specifying a more complicated stream-relation that would warrant talk of belonging to a single owner not only in normal circumstances but also in cases of teletransportation. Sorabji does not argue that it would be impossible to specify such a relation, just that Parfit hasn t done it. I know of no reason to think that it would be impossible. In fact, it seems to me highly likely that if one does not simply give the back of one s hand to the idea that an individual psycho-physical stream and, with it, unique ownership might be preserved through teletransportation, one could specify circumstances that might link pre- and post- teletransported persons so as plausibly to Page 5

preserve these ideas. It s hard to see how merely saying that the body/brain that emerges at the end of a process of teletransportation owns (or does not own) the earlier body/brain s experiences would be a better alternative to an account that specifies such circumstances. For merely saying that the teletransported replica owns (or does not own) the experiences of its ancestors would not explain or justify anything, whereas specifying the nature of the psycho-physical components of a stream, including the relevant causal dependencies among its components, would explain what the relationship between the teletransported replica and its ancestors actually is in virtue of which one might (or might not) justifiably regard them as belonging to a single psychophysical stream in a way that would warrant talk of the replica as the owner of previous experiences and actions. Of course, if one is a substance dualist, one might, albeit vacuously, try to ground ownership relations differently. But there is no indication that Sorabji is a dualist. For materialists, other than the factual data specified in some such psycho-physical streamrelation (perhaps a more robust one than Parfit imagined that countenanced not only bodily and psychological components, but even social connections), there is no other relevant factual data to which one might appeal to explain and justify talk of ownership. Page 6

Hence, however necessary the notion of ownership might be for practical purposes, talk of the reality of ownership strikes me as more honorific than truly substantive. One can, if one likes, confer the honor and say that the owning relationship is real. But merely saying this does not reduce one iota the justificatory and explanatory dependence of the owning relationship on some sort of stream relationship. So, I cannot see that much hinges on whether one says that the ownership relation is real. This becomes especially apparent if one reflects that there is not just one ownership relation in which persons are intimately involved, but many. Compare, for instance, the following ownership relations: my house, my bodily parts, my joy (or sadness), my bodily movements, my actions, and my history. Each of these sorts of ownership is important to the ways we think about persons. Yet since we would have to appeal to different facts to explain and justify ownership relations of each of these sorts there seems to be little reason to think that each of the my s in the list expresses the same relation. And if they express different relations, then merely saying that one owns something cannot be the end of the story. What, then, is the rest of the story? Sorabji argues that if there is a rest of the story, Parfit has not discovered it. But other than distinguishing among ownership- Page 7

predicates, such as material-possession-ownership, bodily-part-ownership, experienceownership, bodily-movement-ownership, bodily-action-ownership, history-ownership, and so on, each of which is then accepted as primitive, how plausible is it that there s no rest of the story? Not very, it seems to me. It s difficult to imagine how there could not be more to the story than this, and the only candidates for such a fuller account point toward reductive information, including the sorts to which Parfit draws attention. Consider, for instance, Sorabji s attempt to show that a person s activities are linked together in a far greater variety of contexts than the few that Parfit considers, and that in this greater range of cases normally the linkage involves the idea of same owner (p270). In defending this point, he appeals to the suggestion, advanced by Marya Schechtman, that duration is required for talking, listening, walking, acting, having beliefs, desires, goals, intentions, thinking, and so on, as, say, when the individual words of a spoken sentence are understood as a combined whole (pp270-71). While it is undoubtably true that at the folk-psychological level such feats may evoke the idea of same owner, it is important to remember that each of them is accomplished by various bodily parts, including especially a human brain. In the case of hearing and understanding language, for instance, the words that a brain hears are Page 8

physiologically encoded by the time they reach the brain and then somehow knit together in the brain by neuronal activity. Currently no one knows enough to say what this knitting together involves or how it is accomplished. But surely there is a neurophysiological story there waiting to be told. Merely saying that the experiences of hearing a succession of individual words were had by the same owner does not take us far in explaining how the knitting together is accomplished. Sorabji does not claim that talk of ownership does explain this. But he also doesn t acknowledge that seemingly only the neurophysiological story could explain it and that with that neurophysiological story in hand a Parfit-like account of distinctive psycho-physical streams might well be fleshed out. Talk of ownership may be the best we can do now, and it may even be essential at the level of folk psychological accounts of agency and ethics, but in the case of this example all that a reductive approach if not Parfit s, then some other requires is acceptance of the idea, which seems quite plausible, that there is some more fine-grained account that makes no appeal to the notion of ownership and that does explain how the knitting together takes place. Sorabji further objects to Parfit s view on the grounds that the bodily and psychological events to which he tries to reduce talk of ownership may themselves be further reduced, apparently ad infinitum (in support of this point, Sorabji defends certain Page 9

criticisms of Nyaya Hindus against Buddhist reductionists (pp278-97)). It is true that there is a puzzle about where, if anywhere, and why just there, any sort of reductive view, including one like Parfit s, should stop the reduction. But if one decides to take the ownership relation as primitive and unanalyzable, puzzles do not vanish. For why should the refusal to reduce to a level that one needs to appeal to anyway in order to explain and justify whether in unusual circumstances ownership relations obtain be any less puzzling than not knowing where to stop a reduction? Sorabji has other arguments as well, too many to consider here. The reservations that I have with many of them are like those I have with the arguments considered above. They are not so much problems with Sorabji s narrower objections to Parfit s views or problems with non-reductionism per se, although some of them may be partly that, as they are with the view that ownership relations are real in any stronger sense than would be warranted by the following claim: for practical purposes we need to talk as if ownership relations are real and currently there is no known reductive account that would enable us to dispense with all such talk. But perhaps Sorabji does not wish to claim that ownership relations are real in any stronger sense than this. In spite of such reservations as I have expressed about Sorabji s case for the reality of ownership relations, his accomplishments in this book are outstanding. He has Page 10

illuminated areas of classical scholarship that were previously dark, shown that many of the concerns of ancient authors about the self and related notions are perennial concerns, and made provocative and insightful contributions to contemporary personal identity theory. That is enough to make this book an extraordinary accomplishment. Anyone interested in the history and/or contemporary theory of the self and related notions would profit from reading it.* *Thanks to John Barresi and to Richard Sorabji for many helpful comments on an earlier draft of this review. Raymond Martin Department of Philosophy Union College Schenectady, New York 12309 Page 11