Précis: Perplexities of Consciousness. for Philosophical Studies

Similar documents
New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

Self-Unconsciousness. Eric Schwitzgebel Department of Philosophy University of California at Riverside Riverside, CA

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2009

Descartes and Foundationalism

Reply to Kriegel, Smithies, and Spener. for Philosophical Studies

Chapter Seven. The Unreliability of Naive Introspection. Is it not one and the same I who is now doubting almost everything, who nonetheless

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

The Problem of the External World

Preface. I have two aims in this book. First, I aim to persuade you that people in general know

SELF-IGNORANCE. Eric Schwitzgebel. Philosophers tend to be impressed by human self-knowledge. Descartes (1641/1984) thought

BRIE GERTLER. RESEARCH INTERESTS Philosophy of Mind especially self-knowledge, mental content, and consciousness.

Russell s Problems of Philosophy

Religious Experience. Well, it feels real

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

College Tutor (Adjunct), St. Catherine s and Worcester Colleges, University of Oxford,

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Against Phenomenal Conservatism

Epistemology and sensation

In this lecture I am going to introduce you to the methodology of philosophy logic and argument

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

CARTESIANISM, NEO-REIDIANISM, AND THE A PRIORI: REPLY TO PUST

Sounds of Love. Intuition and Reason

The Moral Behavior of Ethicists and the Role of the Philosopher

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

PHIL 3020: Modern Philosophy, Spring 2010 MW 9:30-10:45, Denny 215 Dr. Gordon Hull

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Is Epicurus a Direct Realist?

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Privileged Access to the Mind: What It Is and How It Can Fail. Johannes L. Brandl

Foundations and Coherence Michael Huemer

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

BRIE GERTLER RESEARCH

Self-Knowledge for Humans. By QUASSIM CASSAM. (Oxford: OUP, Pp. xiii +

Did Marc Hauser's Moral Minds Plagiarize John Mikhail's Earlier Work?

Skepticism and Internalism

The New Puzzle of Moral Deference. moral belief solely on the basis of a moral expert s testimony. The fact that this deference is

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Lend me your eyes; I can change what you see! ~~Mumford & Sons

Oxford Scholarship Online

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

DR. MAGDALENA BALCERAK JACKSON

Course Description and Objectives:

THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF PAIN *

EPISTEMOLOGY for DUMMIES

Meditation 1: On what can be doubted

Kelly and McDowell on Perceptual Content. Fred Ablondi Department of Philosophy Hendrix College

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

PHIL History of Modern Philosophy Spring 2016

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

Subjective Character and Reflexive Content

A Philosophical Critique of Cognitive Psychology s Definition of the Person

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Epistemology. Theory of Knowledge

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Illusionism and Givenness: Comments on Frankish *

Phenomenal Indeterminacy and the Bounds of Cognition 1

Two books, one title. And what a title! Two leading academic publishers have

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

The Department of Philosophy and Classics The University of Texas at San Antonio One UTSA Circle San Antonio, TX USA.

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

IN SEARCH OF DIRECT REALISM

Epistemology. PH654 Bethel Seminary Winter To be able to better understand and evaluate the sources, methods, and limits of human knowing,

The Quest for Knowledge: A study of Descartes. Christopher Reynolds

CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

Varieties of Apriority

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

PHIL History of Modern Philosophy Spring 2015

RESPECTING THE EVIDENCE. Richard Feldman University of Rochester

Comparison between Rene Descartes and Francis Bacon s Scientific Method. Course. Date

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism. Chapter III of Skepticism and the Veil of Perception: Easy Answers to Skepticism

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Access provided by National Taiwan University (10 Aug :00 GMT)

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Qualia: A Defense. Brendan James Moore, MA, & Dr. Syed Adeel Ahmed

STROUD, AUSTIN, AND RADICAL SKEPTICISM

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 1

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Richard Carrier, Ph.D.

On the Appearance and Reality of Mind

Philosophy Courses Fall 2011

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Transcription:

Précis: Perplexities of Consciousness for Philosophical Studies Eric Schwitzgebel Department of Philosophy University of California at Riverside Riverside, CA 92521-0201 eschwitz at domain: ucr.edu May 17, 2013 Schwitzgebel May 17, 2013 Phil Studies Précis, p. 1

Précis: Perplexities of Consciousness We do not know our own stream of conscious experience very well, nor is it easy to remedy our ignorance. That is the thesis of Perplexities of Consciousness. The method is to look, in some detail, at a wide variety of cases: the coloration of dreams, the visual experience of perspective, double vision, visual imagery, the auditory experience of echolocation, combination tones, afterimages, visual illusions, the tactile experience of your feet in your shoes, emotional experience, peripheral vision, cognitive phenomenology, and visual experience with your eyes closed. About each type of case, I argue, we are prone to error or ignorance in some cases, error or ignorance of a magnitude that would be shocking if we were trying to reach similarly large-grained judgments about nearby perceptible objects in the external world. For example, we seem to miss, or alternatively invent, entire modalities of experience cognitive phenomenology (a.k.a. imageless thought or unsymbolized thinking), or echolocation, or distinctively emotional phenomenology. And we seem to miss, or alternatively invent, what one might have thought would be hugely obvious features of the experiences we do recognize, for example, that almost all of the objects that we see are visually doubled (or that they re not), or that we have a wealth of sensory experience beyond the boundaries of attention (or that we don t). Imagine being mistaken about whether nearly all the ordinary-sized physical objects in your environment were single or double, or being mistaken about whether you were surrounded by a richly-populated abundant world or a thin, sparse, mostly empty world! A long philosophical tradition, going back at least to Descartes, has held that we know our own minds, especially our current conscious experiences, better than we know the outside world maybe even infallibly, or indubitably, or incorrigibly. If the reasoning in my book is Schwitzgebel May 17, 2013 Phil Studies Précis, p. 2

correct, that tradition is badly mistaken. In the 20 th century, the strictest forms of infallibilism fell out of favor, but most critiques were limited: Critics typically argued only against perfection, while allowing that self-knowledge might still be excellent, or they focused their critiques on self-knowledge of nonconscious aspects of our own minds, such as the causes of our decisions. The most important exception to this pattern was the introspective psychology movement of the late 19 th and early 20 th centuries especially E.B. Titchener (discussed at length in Chapter 5 of Perplexities) but their arguments have been neglected. I argue from specific cases to a generalization. My arguments concerning specific cases tend to take one of three forms. The argument from variability. Group A says X about their stream of experience. Group B says not-x. It is not plausible that Group A and Group B have experiences different enough to make the claims of both groups true. Therefore, at least one group must be mistaken about their experience. The argument from error. Group A says X about their stream of experience. But X is probably false. Therefore, Group A is probably mistaken about its experience. Doubt induction. I aim to induce personal doubt in the reader about whether her stream of experience has feature X, leading her to conclude she does not know whether her experience has feature X. This doubt induction sometimes proceeds by asking the reader carefully to reflect on her own phenomenology, with some pointed questions to consider. I hope for synergy among my arguments. Suppose one type of argument works for one type of experience. To the extent that argument finds success, it can lend support to other types of argument regarding that same kind of experience. If I succeed in doubt induction about the reader s own visual experience of perspective, for example, that might make it seem more Schwitzgebel May 17, 2013 Phil Studies Précis, p. 3

plausible to the reader that large groups of people might be mistaken about their visual experience of perspective, and vice versa. Likewise across kinds of experience: To the extent I can render it plausible that people are often badly mistaken about their visual imagery, it becomes less far-fetched to suppose they might be similarly radically mistaken about their emotional phenomenology, and vice versa. Even if no single case is compelling on its own and perhaps no case is entirely compelling on its own, given the variety of countermoves available to those who aim to defend the accuracy of introspection I hope that the body of examples and arguments, considered as a whole, is still sufficient to make a good case for widespread introspective ignorance and error, even about what might have seemed on the surface to be easy and obvious matters. I aim toward both a personal conclusion and a typical-person conclusion. The personal conclusion is this: You the reader do not know your own stream of experience very well. The doubt induction arguments maybe they are better called exercises are the main path to this conclusion. However, I hope that the other two argument forms, when combined with the recognition of potentially mistaken others as your epistemic peers, can also lend considerable support to the personal conclusion. In a similar spirit, I sometimes supplement my three main argument forms with confessional epistemology sincere expression of my own degree of confidence or doubt on the matters at hand, offering myself as an epistemic peer. I ve found that most people default toward a kind of cavalier confidence when casually queried about their experience. I aim to undercut that confidence, if you tend to feel it, and launch us together into the murks of doubt. The typical-person conclusion is the conclusion that the typical person, or at least the typical person in our society, doesn t know her own stream of experience very well. The Schwitzgebel May 17, 2013 Phil Studies Précis, p. 4

arguments from variability and error are the primary arguments toward this conclusion, though doubt induction can also lend support to this conclusion if the reader believes that she is in no worse an epistemic condition regarding her stream of experience than is the typical person. The typical-person conclusion leaves open the possibility that some exceptional people have excellent knowledge of their stream of experience, through native talent or introspective training. We are subject to a certain type of epistemic illusion. Introspection seems easy, and we tend to have high confidence in its results, but that confidence is ill-tuned to epistemic reality. Our intuitive sense of confidence, or even indubitability, exceeds what is warranted. Some arguments for excellent self-knowledge in Descartes (1641/1984), for example, and in Brie Gertler (2012) appear to rely on these inflated epistemic intuitions, on an excessively selftrusting sense of the impossibility or near-impossibility of error. We are invited to ask ourselves, how can I doubt this? And from the fact that doubt seems impossible or possible only inauthetically, the epistemic authority of introspection follows. But the arguments from variability and error should lead us to mistrust these feelings of confidence, if we see what seems to be misplaced confidence in our epistemic peers. In fact, appeals to epistemic intuition can cut both ways: I use them toward skeptical ends in my doubt induction exercises. In principle, epistemic illusions could err either direction. We could trend either too low or too high, either too underconfident or too overconfident. But in fact, overconfidence is the more likely direction of error. My arguments from variability and error suggest that people are often mistaken about their stream of conscious experience despite exhibiting outward signs of confidence. Also, environmental pressures more often punish underconfidence (e.g., via looking inept or inarticulate or uninteresting when asked to discuss one s visual imagery) than they punish overconfidence, since it is unusual to find naturally occurring situations in which people s Schwitzgebel May 17, 2013 Phil Studies Précis, p. 5

confident self-reports about their stream of experience are proven embarrassingly wrong. In any case, meta-level doubts will generally tend to favor the skeptic in the end: If it is sufficiently unclear to you whether you should doubt P or not doubt P, you are already doubting P. 1 1 Thanks to Jakob Hohwy for helping me see my general argument forms, and to Jenny Windt for helping me see the central role of epistemic intuitions in my arguments. Schwitzgebel May 17, 2013 Phil Studies Précis, p. 6

References: Descartes, René (1641/1984). Meditations on first philosophy. In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch, eds., The philosophical writings of Descartes, vol. II. Cambridge: Cambridge. Gertler, Brie (2012). Renewed acquaintance. In D. Smithies and D. Stoljar, eds., Introspection and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford. Schwitzgebel, Eric (2011). Perplexities of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT. Schwitzgebel May 17, 2013 Phil Studies Précis, p. 7