QUESTION 22. God s Providence

Similar documents
QUESTION 116. Fate. Article 1. Is there such a thing as fate?

QUESTION 19. God s Will

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

QUESTION 10. The Modality with Which the Will is Moved

QUESTION 54. An Angel s Cognition

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

QUESTION 65. The Work of Creating Corporeal Creatures

QUESTION 90. The Initial Production of Man with respect to His Soul

QUESTION 55. The Medium of Angelic Cognition

QUESTION 59. An Angel s Will

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

QUESTION 45. The Mode of the Emanation of Things from the First Principle

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

QUESTION 42. The Equality and Likeness of the Divine Persons in Comparison to One Another

QUESTION 34. The Person of the Son: The Name Word

QUESTION 23. Predestination

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

QUESTION 64. The Punishment of the Demons

QUESTION 56. An Angel s Cognition of Immaterial Things

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue

QUESTION 63. The Cause of Virtue

QUESTION 27. The Principal Act of Charity, i.e., the Act of Loving

QUESTION 8. The Objects of the Will

QUESTION 65. The Connectedness of the Virtues

QUESTION 113. The Guardianship of the Good Angels

QUESTION 30. Mercy. Article 1. Is something bad properly speaking the motive for mercy?

QUESTION 28. The Divine Relations

QUESTION 45. The Gift of Wisdom

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

QUESTION 94. The Natural Law

Francisco Suárez, S. J. DE SCIENTIA DEI FUTURORUM CONTINGENTIUM 1.8 1

QUESTION 66. The Equality of the Virtues

QUESTION 69. The Beatitudes

QUESTION 59. The Relation of the Moral Virtues to the Passions

QUESTION 86. What Our Intellect Has Cognition of in Material Things

QUESTION 26. Love. Article 1. Does love exist in the concupiscible power?

QUESTION 53. The Corruption and Diminution of Habits. Article 1. Can a habit be corrupted?

QUESTION 67. The Duration of the Virtues after this Life

QUESTION 34. The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures

QUESTION 83. The Subject of Original Sin

Thomas Aquinas College Napa Institute, Saint Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae First Part, Question 21

QUESTION 57. The Distinctions Among the Intellectual Virtues

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

QUESTION 18. The Subject of Hope

QUESTION 92. The Production of the Woman

QUESTION 97. The Conservation of the Individual in the First State

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

QUESTION 4. The Virtue Itself of Faith

QUESTION 96. The Force of Human Law

QUESTION 107. The Speech of Angels

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

QUESTION 36. The Causes of Sadness or Pain. Article 1. Is it a lost good that is a cause of pain rather than a conjoined evil?

QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It

QUESTION 84. How the Conjoined Soul Understands Corporeal Things That are Below Itself

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

QUESTION 39. The Goodness and Badness of Sadness or Pain

QUESTION 45. Daring. Article 1. Is daring contrary to fear?

Thomas Aquinas on God s Providence. Summa Theologiae 1a Q22: God s Providence

Thomas Aquinas on Law

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologiae la Translated, with Introduction and Commentary, by. Robert Pasnau

QUESTION 44. The Precepts that Pertain to Charity

QUESTION 55. The Vices opposed to Prudence that are Similar to it

QUESTION 95. Things Relevant to the First Man's Will, viz., Grace and Justice

QUESTION 66. The Order of Creation with respect to Division

QUESTION 111. The Divisions of Grace

1 Concerning distinction 39 I ask first whether God immutably foreknows future

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

QUESTION 39. The Persons in Comparison to the Essence

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

QUESTION 20. The Goodness and Badness of the Exterior Act

Disputation 20. On the First Efficient Cause and on His First Action, Which Is Creation

ON UNIVERSALS (SELECTION)

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

QUESTION 28. Joy. Article 1. Is joy an effect of charity within us?

CHAPTER THREE ON SEEING GOD THROUGH HIS IMAGE IMPRINTED IN OUR NATURAL POWERS

THE ORDINATIO OF BLESSED JOHN DUNS SCOTUS. Book Two. First Distinction (page 16)

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

Saint Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologiae Selections III Good and Evil Actions. ST I-II, Question 18, Article 1

The Nature and Extent of Sacred Doctrine Thomas Aquinas

QUESTION 40. Hope and Despair

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

Aquinas on Law Summa Theologiae Questions 90 and 91

QUESTION 36. Envy. Article 1. Is envy a type of sadness?

William Ockham on Universals

What God Could Have Made

Fr. Sebastian Walshe, O.Praem. PREDESTINATION: SOME QUESTIONS AND MISCONCEPTIONS 1

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

St. Thomas on the Philosophical Intelligibility and Plausibility of the Doctrine of Divine Providence: Situating Summa Contra Gentiles 3, chap.

KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE

Transcription:

QUESTION 22 God s Providence Now that we have considered what pertains to God s will absolutely speaking, we must proceed to those things that are related to both His intellect and will together. These include providence, which is had with respect to all things (question 22), as well as predestination and reprobation and what follows upon them in the order of salvation especially with respect to human beings (questions 23-24). For in moral science prudence, which clearly pertains to providence, is considered after the moral virtues. On the topic of providence there are four questions: (1) Does providence exist in God? (2) Are all things subject to God s providence? (3) Is God s providence immediate with respect to all things? (4) Does God s providence impose necessity on the things it provides for? Article 1 Does providence exist in God? It seems that providence (providentia) does not exist in God: Objection 1: According to Tully, providence is a part of prudence (pars prudentiae). But since, according to the Philosopher in Ethics 6, prudence involves good deliberation, it cannot belong to God; for there is nothing which God is not sure about and which He would thus need to deliberate about (qui nullum dubium habet, unde eum consiliari oporteat). Therefore, providence does not belong to God. Objection 2: Whatever exists in God is eternal. But providence is not eternal, since, according to Damascene, providence has to do with existing things that are not themselves eternal. Therefore, providence does not exist in God. Objection 3: Nothing composite exists in God. But providence seems to be something composite, since it includes within itself both the will and the intellect. Therefore, providence does not exist in God. But contrary to this: Wisdom 14:3 says, But Your providence, O Father, governs all things. I respond: It is necessary for providence to be posited in God. For, as has been shown (q. 6, a. 4), all the good that exists in things is created by God. But good is found in things not only with respect to their substance, but also with respect to their being ordered toward their end, and most especially toward their ultimate end, which, as was established above (q. 21, a. 4), is God s goodness. Therefore, this good of ordering that exists among created things is itself created by God. However, since God is a cause of things through His intellect, and since, as is clear from what was said above (q. 15, a. 2 and q. 19, a. 4), the idea of each of His effects must thus preexist in Him, it is necessary that a plan for the ordering of things to their end should preexist in God s mind (necesse est quod ratio ordinis rerum in finem in mente divina praeexistat). And this plan for ordering things to their end is providence, properly speaking. For providence is the principal part of prudence, and the other two parts viz., memory of what is past and understanding of what is present (memoria praeteritorum et intelligentia praesentium) are ordered toward it. For it is from the past as remembered and the present as understood that we make inferences about future things that have to be provided for (coniectamus de futuris providendis). Now according to the Philosopher in Ethics 6, it is the role of prudence to order other things toward their end whether this be (a) with respect to one s own self, and in this sense a prudent man is one who skillfully orders his acts toward the goal of his life, or (b) with respect to the end of others who are subject to one in the family or in the city or in the kingdom, and it is in this sense that Matthew 24:45 says,... the faithful and prudent servant, whom his lord has appointed over his family. It is in this second way that prudence or providence can belong to God. For in God Himself there is nothing that can be ordered toward an end, since He Himself is the ultimate end.

Part 1, Question 22 184 Therefore, it is this plan for ordering things toward their end that is called providence in God. Accordingly, in De Consolatione Philosophiae 4, Boethius says, Providence is divine reason itself, grounded in the ultimate ruler of all things, which disposes all things. Now disposition can refer either to a plan for ordering things toward their end or a plan for ordering the parts in a whole. Reply to objection 1: According to the Philosopher in Ethics 6, prudence, properly speaking, gives commands about matters which good deliberation (euboulia) has correctly inquired into and which sound judgment (sunesis) has correctly passed judgment on. Hence, even though deliberating does not belong to God, given that deliberation involves inquiry into matters that one is not sure about, nonetheless, it does belong to God that He should issue commands about the ordering of things toward their end, concerning which He has right reason (recta ratio) this, according to Psalm 148:6 ( He has made a decree, and it shall not pass away. ) And this is the sense in which the nature of prudence and providence belongs to God. Moreover, even though one can claim that the plan for things to be done may itself be called deliberation or counsel (consilium) in God, this will not be because of any sort of inquiry in God; instead, it will be because of the cognitional certitude that all those who deliberate aim to arrive at by means of their inquiry. Hence, Ephesians 1:11 says, Who works all things according to the counsel of His will. Reply to objection 2: Two things are pertinent to care (pertinent ad curam), viz., (a) the plan of the ordering, which is called providence and disposition, and (b) the execution of that ordering, which is called governance. The first of these is eternal, and the second is temporal. Reply to objection 3: Providence exists in the intellect but presupposes the willing of the end. For one does not give commands concerning what is to be done for the sake of an end unless he has willed the end. Hence, prudence also presupposes the moral virtues, through which the appetite is ordered toward the good, as Ethics 6 says. Still, even if providence were related equally to God s will and to His intellect, this would still not compromise God s simplicity. For, as was explained above (q. 19, a. 1 and a. 4), in God the will and the intellect are the same. Article 2 Are all things subject to God's providence? It seems that not all things are subject to God s providence: Objection 1: Nothing that is provided for is fortuitous. Therefore, if all things are provided for by God, then nothing will be fortuitous, and so there will be no such thing as chance or fortune. But this is contrary to common opinion. Objection 2: Every wise provider eliminates defects and evils as much as possible from the things that he takes care of. But we see that many evils exist among things. Therefore, either God is unable to prevent them and so is not omnipotent, or else He does not have care of all of them. Objection 3: What happens by necessity does not require providence, i.e., prudence. Hence, according to the Philosopher in Ethics 6, prudence is right reason with respect to contingent things that are open to deliberation and choice. Therefore, since many things in the world happen by necessity, not everything is subject to providence. Objection 4: Whoever is left to himself is not subject to the providence of any ruler. But men are left to themselves by God, according to Ecclesiasticus 15:14 ( God made man from the beginning, and

Part 1, Question 22 185 left him in the hand of his own counsel ). And this holds especially for evil men, according to Psalm 80:13 ( So He let them go according to the desires of their heart ). Therefore, not all things are subject to God s providence. Objection 5: In 1 Corinthians 9:9 the Apostle says, God is not concerned about oxen, or, for the same reason, about other non-rational creatures. Therefore, not all things are subject to God s providence. But contrary to this: Wisdom 8:1 says of God s wisdom, She reaches, therefore, from end to end mightily, and orders all things sweetly. I respond: Some thinkers, e.g., Democritus and Epicurus, have completely denied providence, claiming that the world came about by chance. Others have claimed that only incorruptible things are subject to providence, and that corruptible things are subject to providence not as individuals but only according to their species, since in this respect they are incorruptible. In the person of these thinkers Job 22:14 says, The clouds are His hiding place, and He does not consider our things, and He walks about the poles of heaven. Rabbi Moses separated men off from the general run of corruptible things because of the splendor of the intellect they participate in, but he followed the opinion of the others in the case of other corruptible individuals. Nonetheless, it is necessary to claim that all things are subject to divine providence not only in general, but also as individuals. This is made clear as follows: Since every agent acts for the sake of an end, the ordering of effects toward their end extends as far as the first agent s causality does. For in the works of any given agent, the reason why an effect occurs that is not ordered toward the end is that this effect follows from some other cause and falls outside the intention of the relevant agent. But the causality of God, who is the first agent, extends to all beings not only with respect to the principles of their species, but also with respect to their individual principles, and not only with respect to the principles of incorruptible things, but also with respect to the principles of corruptible things. Hence, everything that has esse in any way must be ordered by God toward its end this according to the Apostle in Romans 13:1 ( The things that are from God are ordered by God ). Therefore, since, as has been explained (a. 1), God s providence is nothing other than a plan for ordering things toward their end, it must be the case that all things, insofar as they participate in esse, are to that extent subject to God s providence. Similarly, it was shown above (q. 14, a. 11) that God knows all things, both universals and particulars. And since, as was explained above (q. 14, a. 8), God s cognition is related to things as a craftsman s cognition is related to his artifacts, it must be the case that all things are subject to God s ordering in the way that all of a craftsman s artifacts are subject to his ordering. Reply to objection 1: Universal causes differ from particular causes, since something can elude a particular causes s ordering, but not a universal cause s ordering. For something eludes a particular cause s ordering only because of some other particular cause that impedes that ordering; for instance, a piece of wood is prevented from bursting into flame by the action of water. Hence, since all the particular causes are included under the universal cause, it is impossible for any effect to escape the universal cause s ordering. Therefore, insofar as a given effect escapes the ordering of some particular cause, it is called a chance effect or fortuitous effect with respect to that particular cause. However, with respect to the universal cause, whose ordering it cannot be released from, it is said to be provided for. Similarly, it might happen that two servants of the same master meet one another, and that even though the meeting is a chance event from their perspective, it was nonetheless provided for by their master, who knowingly dispatched them to the same place in such a way that neither knew about the other. Reply to objection 2: Someone who has care of a particular thing differs here from someone who

Part 1, Question 22 186 is a universal provider. For a particular provider eliminates defects as much as possible from that which is subject to his care, whereas a universal provider permits defects to occur in particular cases in order not to impede the good of the whole. Hence, the corruptions and defects in natural things are said to be contrary to a particular nature, but they nonetheless fall within the intention of nature as a whole, insofar as a defect in one thing works to the good of some other thing or to the good of the universe as a whole. For instance, the corruption of one thing is the generation of some other thing, and through this generation a species is preserved. Therefore, since God is the universal provider for the totality of being, it pertains to His providence that He should permit certain defects to exist in some particular things in order that the complete good of the universe not be impeded. For if all evils were prevented, then many goods would be absent from the universe. For instance, the life of a lion would not exist if there were no killing of animals; again, the patience of the martyrs would not exist if it were not for the tyrants persecution. Hence, in the Enchiridion Augustine says, Almighty God would never allow any evil to exist among His works if He were not good and powerful enough to do well even given the evil. Now these first two objections that we have just answered seem to have influenced those who excluded corruptible things from God s providence, since it is among corruptible things that chance events and evils occur. Reply to objection 3: Man did not institute nature, but instead uses natural entities to his own advantage in his works of art and virtue. Hence, human providence does not extend to the necessary things that happen by nature. However, the providence of God, who is the author of nature, does indeed extend to these things. This third objection seems to have influenced those who removed the course of natural things from God s providence and attributed it to the necessity of matter e.g., Democritus and other ancient natural philosophers. Reply to objection 4: Man is not excluded from God s providence by the statement that God left man to himself. Instead, what this statement shows is that an operative power determined to a single effect is not fixed for man ahead of time, as it is for natural things. For natural things act only as if they are directed by another toward their end, and they do not act as if they are directing themselves toward the end, in the way that rational creatures do through the power of free choice by which they deliberate and choose. Hence, rational creatures are explicitly said to be in the hand of their own counsel. However, since the very act of free choice is traced back to God as a cause, the things that are done by free choice must be subject to God s providence. For human providence is contained under God s providence in the way that a particular cause is contained under a universal cause. Moreover, God has providence over just men in a more excellent way than over wicked men, since He does not permit anything to happen to just men that would definitively undermine their salvation. For as Romans 8:28 says, To them that love God all things work together unto good. On the other hand, from the fact that He does not restrain the wicked from the evil of sin, He is said to send them away not, however, in the sense that they are totally excluded from His providence. For they would fall into nothingness if He did not conserve them through His providence. The present objection seems to have influenced Tully, who removed from God s providence human affairs of the sort we deliberate about. Reply to objection 5: Since, as has been explained, a rational creature has dominion over his own acts through free choice, he is subject to God s providence in a special way, so that guilt and merit are imputed to him and punishment and reward are rendered to him. And it is in this respect that the Apostle denies that God cares about oxen. However, he does not mean that individual non-rational creatures do not fall under God s providence, as Rabbi Moses thought.

Part 1, Question 22 187 Article 3 Is God s providence immediate with respect to all things? It seems that God does not have immediate providence with respect to all things: Objection 1: Whatever is dignified must be attributed to God. But it is part of a king s dignity that he has ministers through the mediation of whom he provides for the things subject to him. Therefore, a fortiori God does not provide immediately for all things. Objection 2: It pertains to providence to order things toward their end, and the end of each thing is its perfection and its good. But it pertains to a cause that it should lead its own effect to the good. Therefore, every agent cause is a cause of an effect of providence. Therefore, if God provided immediately for all things, then all secondary causes would be eliminated. Objection 3: In the Enchiridion Augustine says, There are some things it is better not to know about than to know about, e.g., vile things. And the Philosopher says the same thing in Metaphysics 12. But everything that is better should be attributed to God. Therefore, God does not have immediate providence with respect to things that are vile and evil. But contrary to this: Job 34:13 says, What other has He appointed over the earth? Or whom has He set over the world which He made? Commenting on this, Gregory says, He rules by Himself the world which He created by Himself. I respond: Two things are relevant to providence: (a) a plan for ordering the things provided for toward their end (ratio ordinis rerum provisarum in finem); and (b) the execution of this ordering, which is called governance (gubernatio). As regards the first of these, God immediately provides for all things. For in His intellect He has a plan for all things, even the very least things, and He has given the power to produce given effects to every cause that He has preordained for those effects. Hence, He had to have had the order of those effects in His plan beforehand (oportet quod ordinem illorum effectuum in sua ratione praehabuerit). As regards the second, there are certain mediators of God s providence. For God s providence governs lower things by means of higher things not because of any defect in His power, but rather because of the abundance of His goodness, so that He might communicate the dignity of causal activity even to His creatures. This rules out an opinion of Plato s that is reported by Gregory of Nyssa. According to this opinion, there are three kinds of providence. The first kind belongs to the highest God, who provides primarily and principally for spiritual things and, as a result, for the whole world with respect to its genera, species, and universal causes. The second kind of providence is that by which generable and corruptible individuals are provided for, and this kind of providence he attributes to the gods who circle the heavens, i.e., to the separated substances that move the celestial bodies in circles. Lastly, the third kind of providence has to do with human affairs, and this kind of providence he attributes to the daimons (attribuebat daemonibus), whom the Platonists posited between us and the gods, as reported by Augustine in De Civitate Dei 9. Reply to objection 1: It is indeed part of a king s dignity to have ministers who execute his providence, but it is a defect for him not to have a plan for those things that are to be done through his ministers. For all operational knowledge (scientia operativa) is more perfect to the extent that it considers things that are more particular, since acts have to do with particulars. Reply to objection 2: As is clear from what has been said, the fact that God has immediate providence with respect to all things does not rule out secondary causes insofar as they execute this ordering.

Part 1, Question 22 188 Reply to objection 3: For us it is better not to know evil and vile things because (a) they keep us from considering better things, since we are unable to hold many things in our understanding at the same time, and also because (b) thinking about evil things sometimes perverts our will toward evil. However, these considerations have no place in God, who sees all things at once with a single act of vision and whose will cannot be turned to evil. Article 4 Does God s providence impose necessity on the things it provides for? It seems that God s providence imposes necessity on the things it provides for: Objection 1: As the Philosopher proves in Metaphysics 6, every effect that has a per se cause which now exists or has already existed and from which that effect follows by necessity is such that it has issued forth by necessity. But since God s providence is eternal, it has already existed; and an effect follows from it by necessity, since God s providence cannot be frustrated. Therefore, God s providence imposes necessity on the things it provides for. Objection 2: Every provider makes what he produces as stable as possible, lest it perish. But God is maximally powerful. Therefore, to the things He provides for He gives the firmness of necessity. Objection 3: In De Consolatione Philosophiae 4 Boethius says that fate, proceeding from the sources of immutable providence, constrains men s acts and fortunes with an indissoluble series of causes. Therefore, it seems that providence imposes necessity on the things provided for. But contrary to this: In De Divinis Nominibus, chap. 4, Dionysius says, It is not part of providence to corrupt nature. But the nature of certain things is such that they are contingent. Therefore, divine providence does not impose necessity on things in a way that excludes contingency. I respond: God s providence imposes necessity on some things, but not as some have held on all things. For it pertains to providence to order things toward their end. But after God s own goodness, which is an end that is separated from things, the principal good that exists in the things themselves is the perfection of the universe, which would not exist if there were not many grades of being found among things. Hence, it pertains to God s providence to produce all the grades of beings. And so God has prepared necessary causes for certain effects, so that those effects occur necessarily, whereas for other effects He has prepared contingent causes, so that they occur contingently in accord with the status of their proximate causes. Reply to objection 1: The effect of God s providence is not just that something should occur in some way or other, but that something should occur contingently or that it should occur necessarily. And so if God s providence disposes a thing to occur infallibly and necessarily, then it occurs infallibly and necessarily, whereas if the plan of God s providence decrees that a thing should occur contingently, then it occurs contingently. Reply to objection 2: The ordering of God s providence is unshakable and certain in the sense that the things that are provided for by God all occur in the mode which He Himself has provided for them, i.e., either necessarily or contingently. Reply to objection 3: The indissolubility and immutability that Boethius mentions pertain to the certitude of providence itself, which cannot fail either in its effect or in the mode of occurrence that it has provided for. Nonetheless, indissolubility and immutability do not pertain to the necessity of the effects themselves.

Part 1, Question 22 189 Also, notice that necessary and contingent follow upon being as such. Hence, the modes of contingency and necessity fall under the oversight of God, who is the universal provider for all of being, and not just under the oversight of certain particular providers.