Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client

Similar documents
Religion is Not Totally Irrelevant to Legal Ethics

The Lawyer's Moral Obligation of Justification

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

MILL ON LIBERTY. 1. Problem. Mill s On Liberty, one of the great classics of liberal political thought,

The Vocation Movement in Lutheran Higher Education

Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Application Form Non Teaching Position

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Enlightenment Liberalism, Lawyers, and the Future of Lawyer-Client Relations

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

FURTHER REFLECTIONS ON THE ROLE OF RELIGION IN LAWYERING AND IN LIFE

UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

III. RULES OF POLICY (TEAM) DEBATE. A. General

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur

b. Use of logic in reasoning; c. Development of cross examination skills; d. Emphasis on reasoning and understanding; e. Moderate rate of delivery;

The Philosophy of Ethics as It Relates to Capital Punishment. Nicole Warkoski, Lynchburg College

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

MEMORANDUM. Teacher/Administrator Rights & Responsibilities

Interfaith Marriage: A Moral Problem for Jews, Christians and Muslims. Muslim Response by Professor Jerusha Tanner Lamptey, Ph.D.

Ordinance violates the Indiana Constitution, which rejects any religious preference. The Indiana Constitution provides:

A Response to John W. Seaman, "Moderating the Christian Passion/or Politics rri John S. H.. Bonham

Council on American-Islamic Relations RESEARCH CENTER AMERICAN PUBLIC OPINION ABOUT ISLAM AND MUSLIMS

Supreme Court of the United States

THE RIGHT TO DIE: AN OPTION FOR THE ELDERLY. Anonymous

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

THE EFFECT OF LEGAL PROFESSIONALIZATION ON MORAL REASONING: A REPLY TO PROFESSOR VISCHER AND PROFESSOR WENDEL

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

FIRST CORINTHAINS (Student Edition) Part One: In Answer to Chloe's Report of Divisions (1:1--4:21)

What God Could Have Made

VATICAN II COUNCIL PRESENTATION 6C DIGNITATIS HUMANAE ON RELIGIOUS LIBERTY

JUDICIAL ENFORCEMENT OF THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

The Elusive Morality of Law

Henry Lord Brougham, Written by Himself

(Article I, Change of Name)

Law Faculties as Prophets

THE ETHICAL BASIS OF JURISPRUDENCE

Legal Ethics Advisors and the Interests of Justice: Is an Ethics Advisor a Conscience or a Co- Conspirator?

LIBERTY: RETHINKING AN IMPERILED IDEAL. By Glenn Tinder. William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company Pp. xiv, 407. $ ISBN: X.

UNIVERSITY TRIBUNAL THE UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO. IN THE MATTER OF charges of academic dishonesty filed October 12, 2016

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

Dedication: J. Denson Smith

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

CONTEMPORARY MORAL PROBLEMS LECTURE 14 CAPITAL PUNISHMENT PART 2

Political Science 103 Fall, 2018 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

2. Public Forum Debate seeks to encourage the development of the following skills in the debaters: d. Reasonable demeanor and style of presentation

Personal Responsibility for Professional Actions

CAN WE HAVE MORALITY WITHOUT GOD AND RELIGION?

Columbia University in the City of New York New York, N.Y

RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

Symposium: Client Counseling and Moral Responsibility

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

The Holy See APOSTOLIC LETTER IN THE FORM OF MOTU PROPRIO MATRIMONIA MIXTA ON MIXED MARRIAGES. October 1, 1970

On Choosing Clients and Careers: A Speculative Essay on the Problems of Initial Choice

Subject: The Nature and Need of Christian Doctrine

FREEDOM TO DIE: MORAL AND LEGAL ASPECTS OF EUTHANASIA. By 0. Ruth Russell. New York: Human Sciences Press Pp. 352.

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

EVANGELICAL LUTHERAN CHURCH IN AMERICA DECISION OF THE DISCIPLINE HEARING COMMITTEE

On Law. (1) Eternal Law: God s providence over and plan for all of Creation. He writes,

California Masonic Education

Bishop s Report To The Judicial Council Of The United Methodist Church

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University

... Made free to live. a holy life. Galatians 5: What these verses mean

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Marcus & Auerbach LLC Attorneys at Law 1121 N. Bethlehem Pike, Suite Spring House, PA 19477

Of Artificial Intelligence and Legal Reasoning

In champaign county court 101 E. Main st. Urbana IL James F. Osterbur 2191 county road 2500 E. St. Joseph IL

The Temptations of Creon: Philosophical Reflections on the Ethics of the Lawyer s Professional Role

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

THE ENDURING VALUE OF A CHRISTIAN LIBERAL ARTS EDUCATION

FACULTY APPLICATION FOR EMPLOYMENT Active for 180 Days

Removal of God Bless the USA From P.S. 90 Graduation Ceremony

PITTSBURGH. Issued: March 1993 Revised: October 2002 Updated: August 2003 Updated: August 2006 Updated: March 2008 Updated: April 2014

The role of ethical judgment based on the supposed right action to perform in a given

A Word of Caution: Consequences of Confession

[MJTM 14 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

Legal and Religious Dimension of Morality in Christian Literature

The Lawyer's Calling Revisited: Second Look or Second Thoughts?

STATEMENT OF EXPECTATION FOR GRAND CANYON UNIVERSITY FACULTY

An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground

The Blameless Corporation

Kant and his Successors

AMERICAN CENTER FOR LAW AND JUSTICE S MEMORANDUM OF LAW REGARDING THE CRIMINAL TRIAL OF ABDUL RAHMAN FOR CONVERTING FROM ISLAM TO CHRISTIANITY

PLATO: PLATO CRITICIZES HIS OWN THEORY OF FORMS, AND THEN ARGUES FOR THE FORMS NONETHELESS (PARMENIDES)

Introduction. Providence with the help of four authors; Paul Kjoss Helseth espousing Determinism, William

John Locke. compelling governmental interest approach to regulate. religious conduct, and I will discuss the law further below.

ARTICLE V: REGARDING THE FAITH COMMUNITY AND MISSION OF THE CHRISTIAN AND MISSIONARY ALLIANCE AND THE HAMLET UNION CHURCH

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

God's Arithmetic- Group Study Guide

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

On the Free Choice of the Will, On Grace and Free Choice, and Other Writings

STATE OF MICHIGAN COURT OF APPEALS

Transcription:

Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law Hofstra Law Faculty Scholarship 1987 Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client Monroe H. Freedman Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/faculty_scholarship Recommended Citation Monroe H. Freedman, Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client, 36 Cath. U. L. Rev. 331 (1987) Available at: https://scholarlycommons.law.hofstra.edu/faculty_scholarship/392 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hofstra Law Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law. For more information, please contact lawcls@hofstra.edu.

LEGAL ETHICS AND THE SUFFERING CLIENT Monroe H. Freedman* Thomas Shaffer is the most erudite and graceful writer in the field of lawyers' ethics, and he has few peers in any other area of legal scholarship. If I had the luxury of studying for a year under any professor in the country, it would be with Professor Shaffer. In this Commentary on his Brendan Brown Lecture,' I am going to disagree with him, but only to express a different, not a better, view. The difference between us is expressed in major part in the titles of our two pieces. Professor Shaffer is primarily concerned with his client's "goodness," while my primary concern is with the fact that my client has come to me because he or she is suffering in some way or, at least, is trying to avoid suffering. 2 That difference in our perspectives or major premises is illustrated in the first paragraph of Professor Shaffer's lecture. Legal ethics, he says, relates to "this other person, over whom I have power." ' I would say, "this other person, whom I have the power to help." Legal ethics, he continues, is concerned with "the goodness of someone else." 4 I would say that legal ethics is concerned with the limits on how far I can go as a lawyer in helping that person and, therefore, with the limits of that person's rights. That is, when we write and enforce rules of lawyers' ethics, we define clients' rights in fundamental ways. In the same paragraph Professor Shaffer says: "[L]egal ethics begins and ends with Socrates' question to the law professors of Athens: 'Pray will you concern yourself with anything else than how we citizens can be made as good as possible?' "' I would say that justice must include a concern with "how we people can have full and equal rights under law." To illustrate that difference: if all of the citizens of Athens had been as good as Socrates * Professor of Law, Hofstra University. 1. Shaffer, Legal Ethics and the Good Client, 36 CATH. U.L. REV. 319 (1986). 2. The dictionary definition of the intransitive verb "to suffer" expresses my meaning more precisely than I had thought it might: "1. to undergo or feel pain or distress... 2. to sustain injury or loss... 3. to undergo a penalty... 4. to be the object of some action.. THE RANDOM HOUSE COLLEGE DICTIONARY (rev. ed. 1982). 3. Shaffer, supra note 1, at 319. 4. Id. (emphasis in the original). 5. Id. at 319 n.1.

Catholic University Law Review [Vol. 36:331 wanted them to be, perhaps there would have been no noncitizen slaves, but that is far from clear. Socrates was willing to teach a slave about geometry (Meno), but I am not aware that he ever favored emancipating the one-third or so of the Athenian population who were slaves. In any event, the difference in emphasis between Professor Shaffer and me is a significant one. To avoid a frequent misunderstanding of my position, however, I would reiterate a point that I have made before and that Professor Shaffer properly emphasizes in his critique of my views: "[T]he attorney acts both professionally and morally in assisting clients to maximize their autonomy, that is, by counselling clients candidly and fully regarding the clients' legal rights and moral responsibilities as the lawyer perceives them... That is, although the lawyer is to serve the client's interests as the client sees them, moral discourse between lawyer and client is an important element of my view of the lawyer's role. Professor Shaffer overstates, however, the extent to which I consider the lawyer to be bound to act on a client's decision that the lawyer deems to be morally wrong. First, I hold that the lawyer's decision to accept a client or a cause is virtually wholly within the lawyer's autonomy. 7 A lawyer who finds a potential client or cause to be morally offensive can simply decline the retainer. Second, contrary to Professor Charles Fried' and others, I consider the lawyer's decision in that regard to be a moral decision that is subject to the moral scrutiny and criticism of others. 9 It is only after the lawyer has freely chosen to be the client's "champion against a hostile world," and has induced the client's reliance on that commitment, that the lawyer is then required to provide zealous representation of the client's interests as the client perceives them.' Professor Shaffer is accurate, therefore, when he quotes me as saying, "The attorney acts unprofessionally and immorally [when he deprives] clients of their autonomy, that is, by denying them information regarding their legal rights, by otherwise preempting their moral decisions, or by depriving them of the ability to carry out their lawful decisions.""' My next words, though, impose an important qualification: "Until the lawyer-client rela- 6. Freedman, Personal Responsibility in a Professional System, 27 CATH. U.L. REV. 19 1, 204 (1978) (emphasis added), quoted in Shaffer, supra note 1, at 322-23. 7. Freedman, supra note 6, at 204. 8. See generally Fried, The Lawyer as Friend: The Moral Foundations of the Lawyer- Client Relation, 85 YALE L.J. 1060 (1976). 9. Freedman, supra note 6, at 204-05. 10. ABA STANDARDS RELATING TO DEFENSE FUNCTION 145-46 (1971). See Freedman, supra note 6, at 204-05; M. FREEDMAN, LAWYERS' ETHICS IN AN ADVERSARY SYSTEM 9-26 (1975). 11. Freedman, supra note 6, at 204, quoted in Shaffer, supra note 1, at 322-23.

1987] Legal Ethics tionship is contracted, however-until, that is, the lawyer induces another to rely upon his or her professional knowledge and skills-the lawyer ordinarily acts entirely within the scope of his or her own autonomy." 1 2 In my view, therefore, there is an important difference between declining to represent a client or cause, and accepting a client but giving the client less than the lawyer's zealous best. 13 Prior to accepting the client or cause, therefore, the lawyer has virtually full autonomy. After the lawyer has deliberately chosen to represent a client or cause, however, the lawyer's autonomy is significantly limited because the lawyer's principal function is to serve the client's autonomy-to allow the client maximum freedom to exercise or to forgo rights to which the client is legally entitled. Even then, however, the lawyer retains some significant scope to avoid involvement in conduct that is morally offensive to the lawyer. This is because there are three circumstances in which I would allow the lawyer to withdraw on moral grounds: (a) if the client consents; 4 (b) if withdrawal can be accomplished without significant harm to the client's interests; 15 or (c) in a matter other than criminal litigation, if the lawyer discovers that the client has knowingly induced the lawyer to take the case or to take action on the client's behalf on the basis of material misrepresentations about the facts of the case, and if withdrawal can be accomplished without direct divulgence of the client's confidences. 6 There is another fundamental point on which Professor Shaffer and I differ. Referring to diversity as a "social justification for the ethics of autonomy," Professor Shaffer says, "[W]e have never wanted diversity more than we have wanted goodness."' 7 My first reaction to those propositions is that I have never viewed diversity as a justification for autonomy. That notion puts the collectivity first, ahead of the individual. That is, Professor Shaffer suggests that we grant the individual autonomy so that society can enjoy diversity. On the contrary, though, I see diversity in society as a byproduct (of mixed value) of the primary goal of respecting the dignity of each individual as a free human being. My reference to diversity, therefore, is far more modest than to assert it as essential in itself to the common good. In response to the idea that it is 12. Freedman, supra note 6, at 204. 13. That is the essence of my disagreements with Professor Richard Wasserstrom and with Ralph Nader. See Freedman, supra note 6, at 193-96; M. FREEDMAN, supra note 10, at 10. 14. AMERICAN LAWYERS' CODE OF CONDUCT rule 6.2(b) (Reporter's Draft, 1981) (The author was the Reporter for the AMERICAN LAWYERS' CODE OF CONDUCT.). 15. Id. rule 6.2(a). 16. Id. rule 6.5. 17. Shaffer, supra note 1, at 326.

Catholic University Law Review [Vol. 36:331 desirable to foster diversity by maximizing lawyers' autonomy in dealing with their clients, I have suggested simply that it would be better "to have that diversity as a reflection of clients' viewpoints, rather than the lawyers'."' 8 The reason it would be better is that giving dominance to lawyers as a class is, in my view, elitist and paternalistic. 9 Beyond that, I am not at all sure who the "we" are who want goodness more than full and equal rights under law. If that "we" is editorial, and consists entirely of Tom Shaffer, I am willing to take my chances and go along. If it is the Moral Majority, I am a lot less willing. If it is-and it has been-the Grand Inquisition that is insisting upon goodness over diversity, I know which side of the rack I am on, and I'll take diversity every time. 20 To sum up the differences in perspective between Professor Shaffer and me with regard to lawyers' ethics: he thinks of the client principally as someone who is capable of being good, and who is in need of moral counseling, while I think of the client principally as someone who is in trouble, vulnerable, and in need of my help; he thinks of the client as "this other person, over whom I have power," while I think of the client as one whom I have the power to help; and he, therefore, thinks of legal ethics as being rooted in moral philosophy and as beginning and ending with how "citizens can be made as good as possible," while I think of legal ethics as being rooted in the Bill of Rights and involving essentially how people in our society can have full and equal rights under law. Finally, Professor Shaffer is no more a statist than I am an anarchist, and he is no more indifferent to freedom than I am to goodness. Nevertheless, he does place somewhat more weight on a collectivistic concern that everyone be as good as possible, while I place more weight on an individualistic concern that everyone be as free as possible. Given those differences in our perspectives, it is hardly surprising that Professor Shaffer and I initially make different choices among his three ethical systems-rectitude, Freedom, and Goodness. Nor is it surprising that he and I agree that I fall rather neatly into "the legal ethics of freedom." What we do not entirely agree upon is where Professor Shaffer comes out. He thinks he belongs in the school of the ethics of goodness; I believe that the school of goodness collapses into the school of rectitude-which Profes- 18. Freedman, supra note 6, at 195. 19. Id. at 193. 20. Professor Shaffer concludes his argument on diversity vs. goodness (or wisdom) by noting: "American law schools, from coast to coast...are the most relentlessly uniform, undiverse, and fungible programs in American higher education." Shaffer, supra note 1, at 327. It seems to me, though, that our law schools might gain in wisdom (and certainly in intellectual stimulation) through greater diversity in our faculties, student bodies, and curricula.

1987] Legal Ethics sor Shaffer rightly condemns for what he calls its hubris and for what I would call its paternalism and elitism. In my view, that necessarily leads him back into the school of the ethics of freedom. What is wrong with the legal ethics of rectitude, Professor Shaffer shows, is that it is "a one-way street."'" It says that "what is important is that the client do the right thing, and that it is the lawyer's job to see to it that his client does the right thing." ' 22 That is wrong, Professor Shaffer says (quoting Karl Barth) because the lawyer "must be prepared to be counseled in turn" by the client. 2 3 Professor Shaffer says it, and I have no doubt that he means it. I do not think, though, that it really is going to come out that way. The reason is that the Barth quote goes on, as it must, to add a crucial clause: "[the lawyer] must be prepared to be counseled in turn if there is need for it. 9,24 What that means is that we have substituted two questions for another. I ask, "If the client disagrees with me in his moral decision of whether to pursue a right that is legally available to him, whose decision controls?" I answer that I have a professional obligation to counsel my client to do what I believe to be the right thing, but "[i]n the final analysis...the lawyer should always remember that the decision whether to forego legally available objectives or methods is ultimately for the client and not for himself.", 25 Professor Shaffer changes the question. He asks, "Must I be prepared to be counseled in turn [by my client] if there is need for it?" He answers yes, but that is not the crucial question. He then must ask, "Who ultimately decides, the client or I, whether I need his counsel or he needs mine?" If you have read Professor Shaffer's article, you know the answer to that question. In his discussion of the legal ethics of rectitude, Professor Shaffer rejects the hubristic lawyer's response that the lawyer's "conscience" must be his own and not his client's. 26 That is, he rejects the legal ethic that makes the lawyer's conscience prevail over the client's. In Professor Shaffer's discussion of the legal ethics of goodness, however, the lawyer's "conscience" is replaced by the lawyer's "character" or "integrity,, ' 27 and that somehow changes everything. That is, it is hubristic for the lawyer to dig in his heels and refuse to do the client's bidding in the name of the lawyer's conscience, but at the same time it is essential for Professor Shaffer that the 21. Id. at 322. 22. Id. at 321. 23. Id. at 322. 24. Id. (emphasis added). 25. MODEL CODE OF PROFESSIONAL RESPONSIBILITY EC 7-8. 26. Shaffer, supra note 1, at 321. 27. Id. at 329-30.

Catholic University Law Review [Vol. 36:331 lawyer refuse to do "some things-some lawful things ' 2 1 in the name of her character or her integrity. Who ultimately decides, then, whether the lawyer needs the client's advice or whether the client needs the lawyer's? Why, the lawyer does, of course. The street may no longer be one-way, but it is the lawyer who gets to direct the traffic. That is why I say that the legal ethics of goodness collapses into the legal ethics of rectitude. Call it conscience or call it character and integrity-it is still the same hubris, the same paternalism and elitism. That is why I also believe that Professor Shaffer has no acceptable alternative to the school of ethics in which the lawyer says, "If I freely choose to represent your interests, I will give you my best counsel, but in the final analysis, I will represent your interests as you freely determine them to be, and not as I impose upon you as your moral superior." Professor Shaffer and I both believe that the client is "the noblest work of God." '29 We will, therefore, accept the risks of the client's freedom of choice; we will respect the client's moral decision; and, as a result of that acceptance and that respect, we will maximize the chances that the client will achieve goodness in the only way that it truly can be achieved-through moral counseling and the uncoerced exercise of a free will. 28. Id. (emphasis in the original). 29. Id. at 329.