Introduction. B Davide Fassio. Julien Dutant 1 Davide Fassio 2,3 Anne Meylan 4

Similar documents
KNOWLEDGE AS DE RE TRUE BELIEF?

Engel, Pascal, Va savoir! De la connaissance en général, Hermann Editeurs, 2007, 256 pp (including an Index), 25 euros, ISBN 13:

Varieties of Apriority

Skepticism and Internalism

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

MSc / PGDip / PGCert Epistemology (online) (PHIL11131) Course Guide

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

EPISTEMOLOGY. By Duncan Pritchard. vol.xviii vol.xviii as best I can the actual methodology employed by analytical

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Williamson on Knowledge, by Patrick Greenough and Duncan Pritchard (eds). Oxford and New

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

4AANB007 - Epistemology I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Assertion, Uniqueness and Epistemic Hypocrisy

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Philosophy Courses-1

JIE GAO. Department of Philosophy School of Humanities, Zhejiang University Tianmushan Road No. 148, Hangzhou, China

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Epistemic Justication, Normative Guidance, and Knowledge

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Philosophy Courses-1

What is a counterexample?

The unity of the normative

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Perceptual Justification and the Phenomenology of Experience. Jorg DhiptaWillhoft UCL Submitted for the Degree of PhD

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Sosa on Human and Animal Knowledge

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

V.F. Hendricks. Mainstream and Formal Epistemology. Cambridge University Press, 2006, xii pp.

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

PHIL 3140: Epistemology

knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

CURRICULUM VITAE STEPHEN JACOBSON. (Title: What's Wrong With Reliability Theories of Justification?)

ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Epistemology. Theory of Knowledge

KNOWLEDGE AND REASON

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

is knowledge normative?

Reliabilism as Explicating Knowledge: A Sketch of an Account

3. Knowledge and Justification

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

BLACKWELL PUBLISHING THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS

dialectica dialectica Vol. 65, N 4 (2011), pp DOI: /j x What Should a Theory of Knowledge Do?

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

PL 399: Knowledge, Truth, and Skepticism Spring, 2011, Juniata College

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT?

Seigel and Silins formulate the following theses:

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

Transcription:

Synthese (2017) 194:1427 1431 DOI 10.1007/s11229-017-1352-9 INTRODUCTION Introduction Julien Dutant 1 Davide Fassio 2,3 Anne Meylan 4 Received: 9 February 2017 / Accepted: 21 February 2017 / Published online: 9 March 2017 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017 On his 60th birthday Pascal Engel was presented with a collection of more than fifty papers authored by prestigious philosophers that reflected his long career of promotion and development of analytic philosophy in and out of Europe. 1 This special issue brings together a selection of those papers centred on the topics of truth and epistemic norms. The papers are followed by replies from Pascal Engel. Normative questions in epistemology have been a longstanding focus of Pascal Engel s research (see e.g. Engel 1991; Engel and Rorty 2007). A central question has been whether and in what sense truth is a norm for belief (Engel 2005, 2013a, b, c). A parallel question arises for assertion and inquiry (Engel 2008). Three of the collection s papers deal with these issues. In Engel vs. Rorty on Truth, Erick Olsson s focuses on whether rational inquiry aims at truth. The article critically assesses the debate opposing Engel and Rorty in their co-authored book What s the Use of Truth?. Olsson sides with Engel in maintaining that truth plays a distinct conceptual role in our intellectual lives. Drawing on a general theory of rational goal-setting which has 1 Dutant, J., Fassio D. and Meylan A. (eds.) Liber Amicorum Pascal Engel, University of Geneva, http:// www.unige.ch/lettres/philo/publications/engel/liberamicorum. B Davide Fassio davidefassio@gmail.com Julien Dutant julien.dutant@kcl.ac.uk Anne Meylan anne.meylan@unibas.ch 1 King s College London, London, UK 2 Zhejiang University, Hangzhou, China 3 University of Southampton, Southampton, UK 4 University of Basel, Basel, Switzerland

1428 Synthese (2017) 194:1427 1431 its roots in management science, Olsson argues that Rorty s central claim that truth is not something we should aim for over and beyond justification rests on a principle of goal-setting rationality that is generally invalid. Olsson concludes by stressing that the goal of truth is likely to have the positive effect of increasing motivation and effort in inquiry, and that this may offset the drawbacks that Rorty calls attention to. In Engel on Doxastic Correctness, Conor McHugh raises two worries for Pascal Engel s views on the norms for belief. Engel distinguishes two types of correctness, e-correctness and i-correctness, and says that a belief is e-correct if and only if it is true and it is i-correct when it is held for good reasons, on the basis of sufficient evidence; a belief is correct simpliciter if it is both e-correct and i-correct. McHugh argues instead that i-correctness is not a genuine kind of correctness. Furthermore, Engel defends the view that doxastic correctness is not a doxastic notion (permission or obligation) but an ideal of reason that belongs to the category of ought to be as opposed to oughtto-do. McHugh provides several challenges to that view. He concludes by exploring an alternative approach to the nature of correctness normativity. He suggests that correctness is a sui generis normative property, neither deontic nor evaluative, related to the notion of fittingness (see further McHugh 2014). In Engel on Knowledge and Assertion, Adam Carter argues against both the assumption that knowledge is the only norm of assertion (the so-called uniqueness hypothesis ) and against the view that knowledge constitutes a sufficient credential for assertion. Building on Lackey s (2008) Doctor Case, Carter presents another widespread range of cases in which knowledge would not make the assertion appropriate. Cases of epistemic hypocrisy as Carter calls them are cases in which the target assertion is criticisable. What would make the epistemically hypocritical assertion appropriate is that one had better epistemic support than one does when one asserts. One point of entry into the question of what epistemic norms govern belief is to ask what are the epistemic goods, that is, what is of epistemic value. Two central issues in this are whether knowledge has more value than true belief and whether the value of either is derived from their contribution to successful action. In Engel on Pragmatic Encroachment and Epistemic Value, Duncan Pritchard takes up Engel s view on the latter (Engel 2009). While Pritchard agrees with Engel s rejection of the idea that knowledge is sensitive to pragmatic factors, he criticizes Engel s way of relating pragmatic encroachment to the issues that regard epistemic value. According to Engel, once we grant that there is no such phenomenon as pragmatic encroachment on knowledge, then it follows that the kind of pragmatic factors appealed to by proponents of this view cannot confer any value on knowledge. Pritchard argues that this latter claim is mistaken: the kind of pragmatic factors appealed to by proponents of pragmatic encroachment could potentially have a role to play in determining the value of knowledge without this having any bearing on whether the pragmatic encroachment applies or not. According to Pritchard, Engel s mistake is to be located in the failure to observe an ambiguity between an attributive and a predicative interpretation of the notion of epistemic value. We can maintain that pragmatic factors add value to knowledge without having to accept pragmatic encroachment as long as we make it clear that we are talking of epistemic value in its predicative sense (the value of the epistemic as opposed to a distinctively epistemic kind of value). Thus, Pritchard argues, it is possible to reject pragmatic encroachment on knowledge while holding that pragmatic

Synthese (2017) 194:1427 1431 1429 factors explain the value of knowledge. In Commodious Knowledge, Christopher Kelp and Mona Simion put forward a new account of the value of knowledge that builds on the idea that knowledge is useful for action. Knowledge, they argue, is like water in that it is a widely and readily available commodity. Like mere true beliefs or Gettierized true beliefs, knowledge is instrumentally good in virtue of involving a correct representation of the world. However, they argue, knowledge is superior because of its commodity: like water, it is readily and widely available. According to them, the superior value of knowledge lies precisely in its being a way of correctly representing the world that is much more readily available than alternative epistemic goods. While the foregoing papers concern what we may see as the analogue of metaethics for epistemology, the next two take up the first-order questions of what, specifically, we should believe, both on ordinary matters and on academic ones. On ordinary matters, Engel has sympathies with the common sense tradition (Engel 2007). On academic matters, Engel has forcefully defended a rationalist ideal against various intellectual trends that betray it to put it in the words of Julien Benda, whose legacy Engel has recently highlighted (Engel 2012). In Common Sense and Skepticism, Keith Lehrer spells out his own defense of a common sense answer to skepticism. He first compares the defense of common sense provided by Thomas Reid to that of G.E. Moore against the skepticism of David Hume. The discussion sets the stage for Lehrer s own defense, which relies on an account of ordinary knowledge that combines Hume s notion of sense impressions with Reid s insistence on the trustworthiness of our faculties. In Tool-Box or Toy-Box? Hard Obscurantism in Economic Modeling?, Jon Elster points out that alongside the kind of soft obscurantist anti-rationalist trends of academia that Engel denounces, there exists a kind of hard obscurantism in the social sciences that abuses the tools of rational inquiry in the hard sciences such as quantitative, formal, and mathematical methods. In the writing of some economists and political scientists, Elster claims, such tools loose their explanatory function and become research goals in themselves toys. Elster makes his case by criticizing some representative examples. Two further papers focus on how knowledge relates to true belief and perception, respectively. In Knowledge as de re true belief?, Paul Egré discusses Kratzer (2002) s account of knowledge as a form of de re belief of facts and examines how best to articulate the de re versus de dicto distinction within this account. He shows that, contrary to Kratzer s view, the distinction does not require postulating a primitive difference between facts and true propositions but can be fully captured in terms of mechanisms of binding and scope. Egré argues that if one adopts this articulation of the distinction, one can use the account to explain the original pair of Gettier cases. However, Egré also recognizes that the account provides at best partial truth conditions for knowledge, for it cannot be generalized to explain Ginet-Goldman cases of causally connected but unreliable belief, as well as other cases similar to Gettier s original ones but in which it is not clear that a de re connection to a fact is missing. Egré also suggests that the de re belief analysis provides a way to spell out Starmans and Friedman s (2012) distinction between apparent evidence and authentic evidence, which he takes to be the crux of the original Gettier cases. In Knowledge, perception, and the art of camouflage, Jérôme Dokic provides an original challenge to the Epistemic Conception of Perception (ECP) according to which perception either is a

1430 Synthese (2017) 194:1427 1431 form of knowledge (Dretske 1969; Williamson 2000) or puts the subject in a position to gain knowledge about what is perceived (McDowell 1994, 1998). Against this view, Dokic puts forward a particular case in which a perceptual experience has propositional content and is veridical but fails to yield knowledge of the state of affairs presented by the experience. The case involves perceptual hysteresis, an empirically well-studied phenomenon involving the maintenance of a perceptual experience with a relatively stable content over progressively degrading sensory stimulations. In such cases, Dokic argues, the boundary between the experience being veridical and it being non-veridical does not coincide with the boundary between knowledge and ignorance. Dokic concludes by addressing three possible rejoinders by the defenders of ECP. The nature of truth itself has been one of Engel s main research topics (e.g. Engel 1991, 2002). In particular, Engel opposes a functionalist account on which truth is characterized by a functional role that is realized by different properties in different domains (Engel 2002, 2013b). In How to Account for the Oddness of Missing-Link Conditionals, Igor Douven puts forwards a functionalist account of the truth of conditionals. His starting point is the perceived oddity of missing-link conditionals, conditionals whose antecedent and consequent lack any apparent connection. On the standard account the phenomenon is a pragmatic ones: roughly, the assertion of a conditional generates the implicature that there is an internal connection between antecedent and consequent, and if no such connection exists, the assertion is infelicitous (though not necessarily false). Douven draws on recent philosophical and psychological work to provide a semantic account instead. The central idea is that the connection between antecedent and consequent is a functional property, which can be realized by a variety of more specific, first-order relations. He focuses in particular on the inferentialist account proposed in Krzyzanowska et al. (2014), according to which the truth of a conditional requires the existence of a connector that may be realized by inferential relations of different nature: deductive, inductive or abductive. While the present collection falls well short of covering all the research areas Pascal Engel has contributed to, we hope that it highlights some of the most central ones. In his replies to each of the papers, Pascal Engel strikes us as exemplifying the openmindedness, intellectual rigor and good spirit that has inspired us as his students and junior colleagues. Acknowledgements We would like to thank the authors and the reviewers for their work on this issue as well as Pascal Engel for comments on the introduction and his work on the replies. Julien Dutant s work was supported by the SNSF Research Project Knowledge, Rationality and Choice (PAOOP1-145323). Davide Fassio s work was supported by the SNSF research projects Knowledge-Based Accounts of Rationality (100018_144403) and The Unity of Reasons (P300P1_164569). Anne Meylan s work was supported by the SNSF Research Project Cognitive Irrationality (PPOOP1_157436). We are grateful to the Swiss National Science Foundation for supporting this research. References Dretske, F. (1969). Seeing and knowing. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Engel, P. (1991). The norm of truth. London: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Engel, P. (2002). Truth. Chesham: Acumen Press.

Synthese (2017) 194:1427 1431 1431 Engel, P. (2005). Truth and the aim of belief. In D. Gillies (Ed.), Laws and models in science (pp. 77 97). London: King s College. Engel, P. (2007). Va savoir!. Paris: De la connaissance en général. Engel, P. (2008). In what sense is knowledge the norm of assertion? Grazer Philosophische Studien, 77, 99 113. Engel, P. (2009). Pragmatic encroachment and epistemic value. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. H. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value (pp. 183 203). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Engel, P. (2012). Les lois de l esprit: Julien Benda ou la raison. Paris: Ithaque. Engel, P. (2013a). In defense of normativism about the aim of belief. In T. Chan (Ed.), The aim of belief (pp. 32 63). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Engel, P. (2013). Alethic functionalism and the norm of belief. In N. Jang Lee Pedersen & C. Wright (Eds.), Truth pluralism: Current debates (pp. 69 86). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Engel, P. (2013c). Doxastic correctness. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 87(1), 199 216. Engel, P., & Rorty, R. (2007). What s the use of truth?. Columbia: Columbia University Press. Kratzer, A. (2002). Facts: Particulars or information units? Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 655 670. Krzyzanowska, K. H., Wenmackers, S., & Douven, I. (2014). Rethinking Gibbard s Riverboat argument. Studia Logica, 102, 771 792. Lackey, J. (2008). Learning from words: Testimony as a source of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Harvard: Harvard University Press. McDowell, J. (1998). Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge, Meaning, knowledge, and reality. Harvard: Harvard University Press. McHugh, C. (2014). Fitting belief. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 114, 167 187. Starmans, C., & Friedman, O. (2012). The Folk conception of knowledge. Cognition, 124, 272 283. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.