PHILOSOPHY OF LIFELONG EDUCATION Kenneth Wain London: Croom Helm.

Similar documents
Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Huemer s Problem of Memory Knowledge

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Ethical universal: An ethical truth that is true at all times and places.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

Philosophy HL 1 IB Course Syllabus

CHARITY AND JUSTICE IN THE RELATIONS AMONG PEOPLE AND NATIONS: THE ENCYCLICAL DEUS CARITAS EST OF POPE BENEDICT XVI

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

COPYRIGHT 2009ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

The title of this collection of essays is a question that I expect many professional philosophers have

What God Could Have Made

Pragmatism s Alternative to Foundationalism and Relativism. Introduction

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

How Successful Is Naturalism?

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice


Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophy Courses-1

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

The Pluralist Predicament

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Summary Kooij.indd :14

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

Pope Francis: The death penalty is contrary to the Gospel Ameri...

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Lifelong Learning Is a Moral Imperative

Rorty on the Priority of Democracy to Philosophy

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Reading Engineer s Concept of Justice in Islam: The Real Power of Hermeneutical Consciousness (A Gadamer s Philosophical Hermeneutics)

Book Review. The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. Justin Bell

Putnam, Koethe, and Metaphysical Realism

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Introduction. Bernard Williams

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Carnap s Non-Cognitivism as an Alternative to Both Value- Absolutism and Value-Relativism

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation

REASONABLY TRADITIONAL Self-Contradiction and Self-Reference in Alasdair MacIntyre s Account of Tradition-Based Rationality

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1. PHIL HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY Short Title: HIST INTRO TO PHILOSOPHY

Action in Special Contexts

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

WHY RELATIVISM IS NOT SELF-REFUTING IN ANY INTERESTING WAY

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Bigelow, Possible Worlds and The Passage of Time

LETTER FROM AMERICA : A UNITED METHODIST PERSPECTIVE Randy L. Maddox

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

An Interview with Alain Badiou Universal Truths and the Question of Religion Adam S. Miller Journal of Philosophy and Scripture

Building Systematic Theology

Robert Kiely Office Hours: Monday 4:15 6:00; Wednesday 1-3; Thursday 2-3

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Morality Totter?* If Historical Materialism is True Does

Evidence and Transcendence

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Transcription:

The Canadian Journal for the Study of Adult Education/ la Revue canadienne pour I'e'tude de l'6ducation des adultes May/mai, 1988, Vol. II. No. 1, Pp. 68-72 PHILOSOPHY OF LIFELONG EDUCATION Kenneth Wain. 1987. London: Croom Helm. Philosophy of Lifelong Education (PLE) offers a philosophical examination of lifelong education (L.E.) both as a concept and as an educational program. In popular discourse, the word 'philosophy' is frequently misused it is often equated with one's view of perspective whether or not one's view has any philosophical import or foundation. Although Wain is dealing with "an applied field", PLE is not simply an account of what the author believes about L.E. PLE clarifies the meaning of 'lifelong education', examines critically the different existing trends within L.E. theory (some of the authors referred to include E. Faure, R.H. Dave, P. Lengrand and Ettore Gelpi), argues that L.E. lacks a coherent program (i.e., "a right philosophical expression for the theory" (ii)), searches for an internally coherent program and one that is "empirically relevant because it responds adequately to the pressure and demands of historical context" (30). This quest provides a rather thorough survey of humanism (Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics, Rousseau, Marx, Huxley and Paul Kurtz), existentialism (Kierkegaard and Van Cleve Morris), liberal philosophy of education (M. Oakshott, R.S. Peters, A. O'Hear and J.P. White) and pragmatism (Dewey). Although this survey is both explanatory and critical, it is mostly a critique of the first three philosophical positions under investigation. None of these three positions, Wain argues, provide the adequate philosophical expression for the educational theory of L.E.: (a) the theories held by "humanists" about humanism indicate "little agreement about how it can present itself as a coherent programme..." (98); (b) while admitting the "positive insights" (128) of existentialism, Wain thinks that existentialism is "incompatible with the very having of an educational programme, lifelong or of any other description" (127) and it leads'to a kind of "subjectivism unacceptable to the outlook of the lifelong education movement" (129); (c) liberal philosophy of education is criticized on holding conservative and formal views about education; even J.P. White's revised position 1 is not seen as being compatible with the L.E. program. The only way to save this position, according to Wain, is by introducing "radical modifications" (160) which "entail the very abandonment of the current liberal education programme" (160). 68

Pragmatism, as expressed in the work of Dewey, is ultimately deemed by Wain as the best choice given that it is "actually consistent with the movement's lifelong education programme, because it alone is compatible with the conceptualizing of a 'learning society' within it. A humanism which emphasizes a tradition of 'tragic guilt', as Suchodoloski's does, or radical individual responsibility, as Lengrand's does, or a universal human 'community', as Kirpal's and others do, cannot be the focus of such a society" (197). The concluding chapter of PLE clarifies the concept 'learning society'. Wain argues that a 'learning society' as a community is both morally acceptable and provides the formal embodiment of the L.E. program. Wain's rationale for this is that it "satisfies the tension between the ideal of 'self-realization 1 and the demands of socialization" (207) without being restricted to either radical individualism or radical collectivism. Wain's project, then, falls within both the "public" and "professional" dimensions of philosophy of education as characterized by Jonas F. Soltis.^ For Wain's endeavor is both programmatic it aims at influencing educational practices by providing value-laden prescriptions expressed in coherent and comprehensive statements and applies the philosophical rigor (of clarifying concepts, identifying contradictions, detecting inconsistencies, flushing out assumptions of ideological positions, and providing arguments and justification) or conceptual and normative educational concerns. In this sense, Wain's general approach provides a very laudable example of how one could make progress in applied philosophy. Notwithstanding my positive comments, I do have some serious reservations with parts of the elaborate but clear thesis defended in this book. I will identify two main parts (I and II) of this thesis and then raise some questions. Part I Wain rejects the analytic philosophy of education approach which dominated the field of philosophy of education in the 60s, 70s and early 80s. According to Wain, it claims to be "value-neutral" and neglects the historical-contextual considerations. This approach, Wain contends, leads to "a liberal philosophy of education" which tends to restrict education to schooling. Thus, such an approach confuses L.E. with either lifelong upbringing or an "extension of school and university learning into adult life" (139), and "renders... 'selfeducation' a self-contradictory one..." (140). Moreover, a liberal 69

philosophy of education, according to Wain, rests on what Rorty calls the foundationalist project in philosophy. This "casts philosophy into the role of guardian of culture..." (9) and puts it in "a privileged position to adjucate between the different knowledge claims that constitute culture..." (9). Part II Wain claims to be working within the paradigm offered by Pragmatism and Philosophical Hermenutics. He also attempts to defend "the 'relativistic' consequences of hermenutic philosophy... [which] rejects the possibility of an objective commensuration between different programmes, between different knowledge-claims, [and] which rejects the traditional fact-value distinction" (12). This is a central point in Wain's thesis. For, according to Wain, one of the main reasons Dewey's pragmatism is compatible with the pragmatic L.E. program (in contrast to the utopic trend, as exemplified in Faure's work) is precisely Dewey's notion of growth and his refutation of static ideals. A defense of relativism, then, becomes crucial to Wain's philosophy of L.E. proposed in this book. Criticism of I There are different stages in the development of analytic philosophy of education. Representatives of the more recent mode of this approach moderate analytic philosophers of education do not defend neutrality. They also take contextual considerations into account. I have argued at length that the recent criticism of analytic philosophy of education is outdated since it focuses on a trend in analytic philosophy of education which no longer exists.^ Analytic philosophers of education have reflected on the early analytical work, realized certain mistakes and broadened their approach to analysis. Moreover, the recent analytic approach does not necessarily adhere to all of the tenets of the liberal philosophy of education program as identified by Wain. Although some proponents of the analytic approach have tended to defend a narrow concept of the education person, this approach is not necessarily incompatible with the openness required by the L.E. program, nor does it necessarily lead to a defense of the status quo. Wain writes: "it is evident 'that education for a fixed and static order accommodates the status quo better than one that encourages an experimental outlook, ihat concentrates on the dynamic aspects of life..." (181-2). And the liberal philosophy of education approach is characterized as one that strives for objectivity. While I do not want to discourage "an 70

experimental outlook" in education, one needs to point out that Wain's claim is not necessarily the case. One should recall the example of Plato who proposed an ideal educational program which aimed at fixed and static forms but which, given the context, actually would have disrupted the status quo if it were to have been implemented. A similar point can be made with regard to R. S. Peters' vision of an educated person: if Peters were to be taken seriously some things in schools would have to be altered radically. (This remark should not be taken as a defense of Peters' notion of an educated person.) Criticism of II One of Wain's reasons for defending "the hermeneutical form of inquiry" is that it allows an "openness to the world" and encourages "the ideal attitude of tolerance of the other... [which] opens the way for the 'fusing' of other horizons with one's own" (20). Moreover, it seriously takes into account the historical context. One needs to question, however, whether (i) these qualities are unique to the kind of inquiry defended by Wain and (ii) these qualities necessarily lead to the kind of relativism embedded in philosophical hermeneutics. William Hare, for example, a moderate analytical philosopher of education who has argued for the ideal of open-mindedness, warns us that this ideal does not lead to relativism or subjectivism. 4 In fact, Hare argues quite convincingly that the attitude of open-mindedness is not incompatible with the notion of objectivity. Harvey Siegel has made a similar point with regard to the notion of critical thinking.^ Moreover, it is important to indicate that moral tolerance ought not to be confused with relativism; neither is it the case that contextualism necessarily amounts to a defense of relativism. As J. F. Soltis and K. A. Strike conclude: "We can be objective without being certain, and we can be tolerant and open to other points of view without being relativists."- 1 a view which Wain, unfortunately, does not consider. 6 Wain's defense of relativism includes an attempt to reject the common critique of the paradox or contradiction of relativism. It seems to me that he fails to do this. According to Wain, the defining premise of all forms of relativism is the following: "All our judgments about the world are made from a cultural view point" (15, my emphasis). Is this statement a publicly pronounced one made from a cultural standpoint? Wain's reply, to be consistent, has to be in the affirmative. But then how can one claim that this statement applies to all cases? Wain is correct in holding that the relativist's defining premise does not preclude the possibility of their being several beliefs, values, and dispositions that "happen to be held cross-culturally" (17, my emphasis). But this does not save relativism from the critique of the 71

paradox or contradiction of relativism. I should add that I am not denying the fact that people hold different views because of their cultural context. What I am claiming, as Mary Warnock puts it, is: "If we really believed that any moral [and non-moral] view was as good and worthy to be adopted as any other, then we would of course make no moral [and non-moral] judgements at all" (7). But in fact we do! In conclusion, PLE is a well-organized book, and in general the argument flows very well. The book ought to be very useful as an initial reading for a graduate seminar in the foundations of lifelong education. In this respect, it is unfortunate that the book lacks a chapter on the various shades of Marxism and L.E. (At the end of the chapter on L.E. and Liberal Philosophy of education, Wain rather hastily concludes that the Marxist position does not deserve a separate chapter "because there are no fundamental differences between Marxists and liberals over the technical definition of education" (158).) Some might even complain about the omission of D. Vandenberg and Maxine Greene in the discussion on Existentialism, as well as the omission of Van Cleve Morris' criticism of Experimentalism in the chapter on Dewey. Notwithstanding these omissions, the book ought to generate very productive discussions and further inquiry into the foundations of a lifelong education program. Reference Notes 1. White, J.P. 1982. The aims of education restated. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. 2. Soltis, J.F. 1983. Perspectives on philosophy of education. Journal of Thought 18(2): 14-21. 3. Portelli, J.P. 1987. Analytic philosophy of education: Development and misconceptions. Journal of Educational Thought 21(l):20-32. 4. Hare, W. 1985. In defence of open-mindedness. Montreal: McGill-Queen's Press. 5. Siegel, H. 1980. Critical thinking as an educational ideal. The Educational Forum xiv(l):7-23. Siegel, H. 1987. Rationality and ideology. Educational Theory 37(2):153-168. 6. Soltis, J.F. and K.A. Strike. 1985. The ethics of teaching. New York: Teachers College Press. 7. Warnock, M. 1975. The neutral teacher. In Philosophers discuss education, by S.C. Brown (ed). Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield. John P. Portelli Mount Saint Vincent University 72