JUDICIAL ENFORCEMENT OF THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE

Similar documents
KENT GREENAWALT'S ELUSIVE CONSTITUTION

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax:

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.

THE CONSTITUTIONAL REQUIREMENT OF SENSITIVITY TO RELIGION. Richard A. Hesse*

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

RESPONSE TO ADAM KOLBER S PUNISHMENT AND MORAL RISK

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

God Loveth Adverbs. DePaul Law Review. Daniel O. Conkle

CHAPTER 1. Introduction

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

PRESS DEFINITION AND THE RELIGION ANALOGY

Case 1:18-cv Document 1 Filed 10/06/18 Page 1 of 8 UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT FOR THE WESTERN DISTRICT OF TEXAS AUSTIN DIVISION

Originalism, the Why and the What

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

New Federal Initiatives Project

Should We Take God out of the Pledge of Allegiance?

Public Reason in the Open Society

CHAPTER 2. The Classical School

1. The basic idea is to look at "what the courts do in fact" (Holmes, 1897). What does this mean?

Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Why economics needs ethical theory

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

AMERICAN CENTER FOR LAW AND JUSTICE S MEMORANDUM OF LAW REGARDING THE CRIMINAL TRIAL OF ABDUL RAHMAN FOR CONVERTING FROM ISLAM TO CHRISTIANITY

Methodist History 30 (1992): (This.pdf version reproduces pagination of printed form) CONTINUING THE CONVERSATION Randy L.

Social Rules and Legal Theory

The Church, AIDs and Public Policy

The Privatization of Religion and Catholic Justices

In Brief: Supreme Court Revisits Legislative Prayer in Town of Greece v. Galloway

Individualism, Equality, and Rights: Reactions to Jackson, Priest, And Katz

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

United Nations Human Rights Council Universal Periodic Review. Ireland. Submission of The Becket Fund for Religious Liberty.

Personal Identity Paper. Author: Marty Green, Student # Submitted to Prof. Laurelyn Cantor in partial

Student Engagement and Controversial Issues in Schools

Constitutional Law 312 Applied Assignment 2017 Application A

MULTICULTURALISM AND FUNDAMENTALISM. Multiculturalism

IN DEFENSE OF THE SECULAR PURPOSE STATUS QUO

Disputes about religious freedom are back in the spotlight again. Although many liberals

In defence of the four freedoms : freedom of religion, conscience, association and speech

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

1) What is the universal structure of a topicality violation in the 1NC, shell version?

Religious Freedom Policy

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

The Blair Educational Amendment

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Case System--A Defense

RELIGIOUS EXPRESSION AT CHRISTMASTIME: GUIDELINES OF THE CATHOLIC LEAGUE

ORIGINALISM, PRECEDENT, AND CANDOR

On the Relevance of Ignorance to the Demands of Morality 1

How To Think About Law as Morality: A Comment on Greenberg and Hershovitz

Marriage Law and the Protection of Religious Liberty: Implications for Congregational Policies and Practices

denarius (a days wages)

There Is Nothing that Interpretation Just Is

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

They said WHAT!? A brief analysis of the Supreme Court of Canada s decision in S.L. v. Commission Scolaire des Chênes (2012 SCC 7)

Paradoxes of religious freedom in Egypt

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

The Holy See APOSTOLIC JOURNEY TO THE UNITED KINGDOM (SEPTEMBER 16-19, 2010)

Argument Writing. Whooohoo!! Argument instruction is necessary * Argument comprehension is required in school assignments, standardized testing, job

FURTHER REFLECTIONS ON THE ROLE OF RELIGION IN LAWYERING AND IN LIFE

Mill and Bentham both endorse the harm principle. Utilitarians, they both rest

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

George Washington Carver Engineering and Science High School 2018 Summer Enrichment

June 4, Dear Ken (and pastors),

Principles of Legal Interpretation. Mark Greenberg, UCLA. In the large literature on legal interpretation, we find intelligent argument and

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Moral Communities in a Pluralistic Nation

SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE: HISTORICAL FACT AND CURRENT FICTION. By Robert L. Cord. New York: Lambeth Press Pp. xv, 302. $16.95.

RELIGION IN THE SCHOOLS

What Kind of Freedom Does Religion Need?

The Philosophy of Ethics as It Relates to Capital Punishment. Nicole Warkoski, Lynchburg College

Comment on Robert Audi, Democratic Authority and the Separation of Church and State

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

Neutrality and the Good of Religious Freedom: An Appreciative Response to Professor Koppelman

The statistics used in this report have been compiled before the completion of any Post Results Services.

Columbia University in the City of New York New York, N.Y

The Arduous Virtue of Fidelity: Originalism, Scalia, Tribe, and Nerve

MEMORANDUM. Teacher/Administrator Rights & Responsibilities

EXECUTION AND INVENTION: DEATH PENALTY DISCOURSE IN EARLY RABBINIC. Press Pp $ ISBN:

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Religious Purpose, Inerrancy, and the Establishment Clause

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Is the Constitutional Concern with Religious Involvement in the Public Square Hostility?

A Wall of Separation - Lemon v. Kurtzman (1971) & "The Lemon Test"

June 11, June 11, I would appreciate your prompt consideration of this opinion request.

THE RUTHERFORD INSTITUTE

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Navigating Religious Rights of Teachers and Students: Establishment, Accommodation, Neutrality, or Hostility?

Christian History in America. The Rise of the Christian Right Major Themes and Review

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views

NATURAL LAW JURISPRUDENCE: A SKEPTICAL PERSPECTIVE

what you know is a constitutive norm of the practice of assertion. 2 recently maintained that in either form, the knowledge account of assertion when

Feedback Constitutional Law 312 Applied Assignment 2017 Application B

Transcription:

JUDICIAL ENFORCEMENT OF THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE Richard W. Garnett* There is-no surprise!-nothing doctrinaire, rigid, or formulaic about Kent Greenawalt's study of the establishment clause. He works with principles and values, not "rules" or "tests" (although he finds more to admire in the "Lemon test" than many courts and commentators do 1 ). In Establishment and Fairness, the discussion and analysis are almost always highly sensitive to context, the conclusions almost always fact-bound. There is, throughout the project, a consistent openness to the possibility-indeed, to the likelihood-that different circumstances will call for different results.' His approach, he says, is a "sensible, nuanced" one, which "involves a number of debatable choices and does not reduce to any simple formula" (p. 433). In his view, the way to understand how the Constitution's religion clauses "should best be understood" is not by asking questions "in the abstract but by focusing on concrete issues in context" (p. 543). Clearly, this wonderful book is a great achievement. It is impossible not to admire the reasonableness. humility, and charity that characterizes and animates this work, and Greenawalt's entire scholarly career. That said, one has to ask: Is Greenawalt's reluctance, in the establishment clause context, to settle on bright-line rules a "good thing" or a "bad thing"? Is his "sensible, nuanced approach" the right one, or even an attractive one? And if it is-if Greenawalt's approach to establishment-andfairness questions, his appreciation for the values that are at stake in the relevant cases. and his sense that the relevant princi- * Professor of Law. Universitv of Notre Dame. 1. See. e.g.. p. 52(..!... conte~d that what the Court has done in respect to establishment is. overall. more cohesive and reasonable than many scholars of the religion clauses believe... ). See generally pp. 157-80 (examining the Lemon test). 2. See, e.g.. p. 195 (noting that.. conditions of scarcity.. with respect to public facilities.. could vary [the] conclusion.. that. as a general matter... [t]here is no reason to make public facilities available only for religious groups.. ). 273

274 CONSTITUTIONAL COMMENTARY [Vol. 25:273 ples are basically sound-then what are the implications of his approach for the challenge of finding and implementing the establishment clause's judicially enforceable content? "It is," Greenawalt insists, "in the nature of fundamental constitutional principles that their full content is never settled once and for all'' (p. 543). Perhaps. We do, however, routinely ask judges to identify and "settle"-at least for the time-being-the implications of such "principles" in the context of real-world lawsuits. Should we? Early in the book, Greenawalt addresses various forms of "skepticism" about "tests for the Establishment Clause," including the view that "the clauses reflect such complex, often conflicting, values, that no tests can do them justice" (pp. 51, 52). In my view, this "skepticism" is well founded, and Greenawalt does not dismiss it. 3 The truth in these doubts should give us some pause: What, exactly, and with what justification are judges deciding establishment clause cases doing when they invalidate or approve the actions of governments and officials in the name of "complex, often conflictinp values"? Even if "the rule of law" is not only a "law of rules," is it troubling to think that resolving disputes about matters so important and basic as the place of religion in public life, and the connections and boundaries between religious and political authorities, depends on the deployment of imperfect, incomplete doctrine by judges who will not always be as learned and sensible to "complex, often conflicting values" as is Kent Greenawalt? If deciding establishment-and-fairness cases involves-if it inescapably involves-questions like "whether instituting a moment of silence will significantly endorse prayer and will have a detrimental effect on those of minority faiths and nonbelievers" (p. 118) (emphasis in original); if "[j]udges reviewing school efforts to teach about religion face hard questions about supervision and control" (p. 135); if "judicial determinations of improper purpose'' are inevitably attended by "various subtleties" (p. 163); if these cases necessarily present (to a greater extent than every interesting legal question does) questions of degree, balancing, trade-offs, and multiple values, then why should we believe that they are best, or even better, re- 3. P. 52 (.. Justices can resolve [establishment clause] cases... according to some coherent pattern. but whether that pattern can be verbalized into a coherent set of tests and standards is debatable... These are serious obstacles. but one needs a closer look... before admitting defeat... ). 4. Antonin Scalia. The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules. 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 1175 (1989).

2008] GREENAWALT ESSAYS 275 solved by judges through litigation than by citizens. officials. and legislators through politics? These and similar questions could reflect (at least) two, related concerns: First, we might think that judges are neither better equipped nor more likely than are politically accountable actors to identify the outcome that best respects the "complex. often competing" values that are in play in establishment clause cases. In addition, we might suspect-even if we do believe that courts are the institutions to which these disputes should be entrusted-that "judicially manageable standards'' are not available.5 These and similar worries could. in turn, convince us to treat (for the most part) the establishment clause as stating, in Thayer's words, a "maxim[] of political morality"" for general consideration rather than as promulgating a prohibition that can, or should, be enforced to the full extent of its meaning by judges. We might even say not only that judges should be deferentialapplying a "rule of the clear mistake" -when evaluating legislative action in light of the establishment clause. but that they should settle for constructing and enforcing only those clear and straightforwardly administrable rules that are essential to vindicating the clause's core. clear meaning and guarantees.~ On this view, they should, for example, give up on identifying the dusktwilight point at which permissible recognition or accommodation of religion becomes impermissible endorsement or privileging, and focus instead on vindicating the self-government rights of religious institutions. 9 5. See generally Richard H. Fallon. Jr.. ludiciallv Manageable Standards and Constitutional Meaning. 119 HARV. L. REV.1274 (2006). 6. James B. Thayer. The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law. 7 HARV. L. REV. 129. 130 (1893). For a recent and engaging defense of a Thayerian approach to disputes regarding the constitutionality of the death penalty. abortion restrictins. and refusals to recognize same-sex unions. see MICHAEL J. PERRY. CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS. MORAL CONTROVERSY. Ar\D THE SL 1 PRE~IE COl:RT (2009). 7. See Michael J. Perry. Is Capital Punishment Unconstitutional? And Even if We Think it Is, Should We Want the Supreme Court to So Rule?. 41 GA. L. REV. X67 (2007) (discussing Thayer and Bickel). 8. There is a rich and growing literature suggesting a distinction. and a gap. between the Constitution's meaning and judicially crafted implementing doctrines. See generally, e.g.. Mitchell Berman. Constitlllional Decision Rules. 90 VA. L. REV. I (2004): Fallon. supra note 5: Lawrence Gene Sager. Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms. 91 HARV. L. REV. 1212 ( 1978). 9. I have argued elsewhere for the centrality of "church autonomy" and the religion-protecting distinction between the institutions and authorities of religion. on the one hand. and those of the state. on the other. See generally Richard W. Garnett. The Freedom of the Church. 4 J. CATH. Soc. THOL'GHT 59 (2007).

276 CONSTITUTIONAL COMMENTARY [Vol. 25:273 Greenawalt repeatedly acknowledges questions like the ones raised above. He engages, for example, Steve Smith's arguments concerning the "impossibility of the court's developing adequate legal principles regarding religious freedom" and his suggestion that we "should ask ourselves whether the courts might profitably play less of a role than they do in circumscribing church-state relations" (p. 438). He recognizes that "[o]ne might believe that a fair amount of legislation enforcing morality violates the Establishment Clause, but not in a way a court can declare" (p. 498). In his chapter on "legal enforcement of religionbased morality." he concedes that, given all the givens, his approach "will rarely, if ever, lead a court to invalidate a law" (p. 536). And so one might wonder why the conclusion of, or "takeaway" from, Greenawalt's context-sensitive approach to churchand-state and religion-and-public life questions isn't something like this: "These questions are hard, answering them requires balancing and trade-offs, there are many values at stake, and sometimes in tension, and so the best way to answer these questions-with a few exceptions-is through politics." To say this is not, of course, to pretend that there is not a lot at stake, or that the right answers do not matter Gust because they are hard to find). It is simply to confess that, in this area, "judicially manageable standards" are hard to come by, that the arena of politics is one where "complex, often conflicting values" are often balanced, and so, perhaps, we should admit a possible, "permissible disparity between constitutional ideals and [judicially enforceable] implementing doctrine. " 10 But couldn't we-after taking to heart Greenawalt's appreciation for conflicting values and his sensitivity to context-just as well opt for "overenforcement" as "underenforcement" of the establishment clause? 11 Not, I think, just as well. Three years ago, Jeremy Waldron set out the "core of the case against judicial review." 12 In his essay, he suggested that "rights-based judicial review is inappropriate for reasonably democratic societies whose main problem is not that their legislative institutions are dysfunctional but that their members dis- 10. Fallon. supra note 5. at 1332. 11. Professor Fallon compares. for example. Henry Monaghan's identification of overenforcing rules with Lawrence Sager's focus on judicial tests that underenforce constitutional norms. /d. at 1297-1306. 12. Jeremy Waldron. The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review. 115 YALE L.J. 13-16 (2006).

2008] GREENAWALT ESSAYS 277 agree about rights." 11 This is because (to oversimplify) there is no reason to believe that courts (or renowned and contextsensitive law professors) are more likely to better protect rights than are democratic legislatures and. in addition, judicial review is undemocratic. I am sympathetic to Waldron's suggestion, though it goes farther than I mean or need to go here. Here. the suggestion is simply that the journey with Kent Greenawalt through two volumes and a thousand pages of careful, charitable balancing might lead us to think that the better course is to find (somehow) some bright-line. on-off "rules and "tests". constructed to identify and forbid the most obvious violations of the Religion Clauses' core-murder in the Cathedrat 4 -type violations-and give up on (or. perhaps, "underenforce'') the rest. 13. /d. at 1406. 14. T.S. ELIOT. MURDER IN THE CATHEDRAL ( 1935).