Is Adam Smith s Impartial Spectator Selfless?

Similar documents
On the Origins and Normative Status of the Impartial Spectator

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

James R. Otteson, Adam Smith, London: Bloomsbury, 2013, 200 pp.

Adam Smith The Theory of Moral Sentiments Excerpts

Part I Of the Propriety of Action. Consisting of Three Sections Section I Of the Sense of Propriety Chap. I Of Sympathy I.I.1

ON THE INCOMPATIBILITY BETWEEN ARISTOTLE S AND KANT S IMPERATIVES TO TREAT A MAN NOT AS A MEANS BUT AS AN END-IN- HIMSELF

Adam Smith s Impartial Spectator

The Sympathetic Process and the Origin and Function of Conscience

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

Literature and the Moral Imagination: Smithean Sympathy and the Construction of Experience through Readership

Hume is a strict empiricist, i.e. he holds that knowledge of the world and ourselves ultimately comes from (inner and outer) experience.

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

Huck Finn the Inverse Akratic: Empathy and Justice

That which renders beings capable of moral government, is their having a moral nature, and

Hume: Of the Original Contract

Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill

A Dialogue Between the Head and the Heart Robert L. Payton Philanthropy: Voluntary Action for the Public Good

220 CBITICAII NOTICES:

Asian Philosophy Timeline. Confucius. Human Nature. Themes. Kupperman, Koller, Liu

Sentimentalism and Metaphysical Beliefs

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Adam Smith and Economic Development: theory and practice. Adam Smith describes at least two models of economic development the 4 stages of

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

Abstract: As J. Baird Callicott has argued, Adam Smith s moral theory is a philosophical

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

The Theory of Moral Sentiments.

AUTHOR & WHEN THE BOOK WAS WRITTEN-

Review: Intelligent Virtue

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Oxford University Press The Analysis Committee

Book II On Living Things. By Dr. William Pierce. 1:2 There is but one Reality, and that Reality is the Whole. It is the Creator, the Selfcreated.

Clarifications on What Is Speciesism?

PHIL 480: Seminar in the History of Philosophy Building Moral Character: Neo-Confucianism and Moral Psychology

Subject: The Nature and Need of Christian Doctrine

Ignorance, Humility and Vice

Boethius, The Consolation of Philosophy, book 5

God s Existence, Part 1 By R. Keith Loftin

The Theory of Moral Sentiments

If Everyone Does It, Then You Can Too Charlie Melman

All Souls Church, Unitarian. Compassion

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

CHRISTIANITY WITHOUT THE RELIGION BIBLE SURVEY. The Un-devotional PROVERBS. Week 3

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Virtue Ethics. Chapter 7 ETCI Barbara MacKinnon Ethics and Contemporary Issues Professor Douglas Olena

Natural Obligation and Normative Motivation in Hume s Treatise Tito Magri Hume Studies Volume XXII, Number 2 (November, 1996)

Why Speciesism is Wrong: A Response to Kagan

On Being Conscious of What We Choose to Worship. Mrinalini Sebastian

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Answers to Five Questions

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

The evolution of the meaning of SCIENCE. SCIENCE came from the latin word SCIENTIA which means knowledge.

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

The Theory of Moral Sentiments

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Communion before Confirmation

One's. Character Change

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

CLASSICS IN THE HISTORY OF LIBERTY

Comparative religion Morality and different religions

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Things Which Matter Most Must Never Be at the Mercy of Things Which Matter Least Silvia H. Allred

For Toleration Moral principles/rights: Religious principles: For Toleration Practical necessity

Many Faces of Virtue. University of Toronto. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3e Free Will

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

What is a Simple Life?

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Al-Fatihah. In the name of Allah, Most Gracious, Most Merciful

Asian Philosophy Timeline. Mencius. Human Nature. Themes. Kupperman. Human nature is innately good! Human nature is innately good!

The two voices of Adam Smith: moral philosopher and social critic

Meditation. By Shamar Rinpoche, Los Angeles On October 4, 2002

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

Virtuous act, virtuous dispositions

Introduction to a Symposium on Jack Russell Weinstein s Adam Smith s Pluralism: Rationality, Education, and the Moral Sentiments

AVOIDING A SHRIVELED SOUL BY PAUL BORTHWICK, DAI SENIOR CONSULTANT

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

Psychological Aspects of Social Issues

G. A. Cohen, Finding Oneself in the Other, Michael Otsuka (ed.), Princeton University. Reviewed by Ralf M. Bader, Merton College, University of Oxford

Critical Thinking Questions

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

Context-dependent Normativity and Universal Rules of Justice

Adam Smith, Moral Motivation and Business Ethics

Overcoming Fear and Rejection. Midweek Instruction Reid Temple AME Church Pastor Washington

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

Animal Rights By Paul Golata

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

Augustine s famous story about his own theft of pears is perplexing to him at

Practical Wisdom and Politics

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

Tocqueville s observations of religion in Democracy in America are similar

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

God, Natural Evil and the Best Possible World

Transcription:

Discuss this article at Journaltalk: http://journaltalk.net/articles/5918 ECON JOURNAL WATCH 13(2) May 2016: 319 323 Is Adam Smith s Impartial Spectator Selfless? Maria Pia Paganelli 1 LINK TO ABSTRACT The invitation to write this paper came with some suggested questions about the nature and role of the impartial spectator. The invitation also suggested that the contributors could perhaps treat a few, or bypass them entirely. But the chief intent of your contribution should be to communicate your interpretation of the impartial spectator. One of the suggested questions implied that the impartial spectator is selfless. I will use the contrast between Adam Smith s description of the man who achieves the most self-command and man who achieves the most humanity to show how, in my interpretation, the impartial spectator is not an abstract entity independent of an individual, but rather is an integral part of each individual. In this context talking about a selfless impartial spectator becomes meaningless. In The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith describes the moral development of human beings in the following way. We are born with the imaginative capacity to put ourselves in the place of another person and evaluate how we would react if we were in that situation. This mechanism, achieved through the work of our imagination, is what Smith calls sympathy. 2 It is a natural and universal mechanism, of which we may or may not be conscious. This ability of our imagination is used to evaluate the conduct of others as well as our own conduct. When we do something, with our imagination we split ourselves into two: the I-agent and the I-spectator. The I-spectator tries to see the I-agent as if it was a different and unknown person. The I-spectator puts himself in the shoes of the I-agent and thinks how he would react in that situation had the I-spectator been the I-agent (TMS, III.1). 1. Trinity University, San Antonio, TX 78212. 2. Smith uses sympathy also in other ways, but they are irrelevant for this paper. VOLUME 13, NUMBER 2, MAY 2016 319

PAGANELLI The spectator, being me looking at someone else s behavior or my I-spectator looking at my I-agent s behavior, evaluates the behavior of the person looked at: If the spectator would behave in the same way as the agent, the agent is worthy of approval. If the spectator would have acted differently, the agent is not worthy of approval and may instead be blameworthy. This means that when we see a praiseworthy behavior in others, and when the majority of other people around us also sees that behavior as praiseworthy, we make a mental note and will try to behave in the same way under similar circumstance so that we too can be the object of praise. Similarly when we see a blameworthy behavior in others, and that the majority of other people around us also see that behavior as blameworthy, we make a mental note to ourselves to avoid that behavior to avoid being the object of blame (TMS, III.2). 3 The first implication of being motivated by the desire to be praiseworthy and not to be blameworthy is that, when we sacrifice ourselves to benefit others, we are not motivated by the love for others nor by the love for mankind nor even by the feeble spark of benevolence. What drives us is just the love of what is honourable (TMS, III.2.28, III.3.4). The second implication of being motivated by the desire to be praiseworthy and not to be blameworthy is that we need to tame our self-love. Our ability to be the proper object of praise and to avoid being the proper object of blame is our ability to develop morally. The problem we incur in selfevaluation is that we are naturally biased by our self-love. We love ourselves too much to admit we are wrong. Our I-spectator is partial to us because of his proximity and love toward us. So we need to train ourselves to decrease this bias and try to distance ourselves from ourselves as much as possible, that is, we need to train ourselves to create more space between the I-actor and the I-spectator. The closer the spectator is to the agent, the more indulgent and partial the spectator will be, that is, the more biased he will be. This training is achieved through self-command (TMS, III.3). As children we have no self-command until we start playing with our peers. It is when we meet our playfellows that out of necessity we start restraining our passions. Even as adults, controlling our passions is extremely difficult because our innate egocentrism. It can be achieved, for the most part, only partially over a lifespan, and only then with great discipline. When we develop that great discipline to control our passions and behave toward ourselves as if we were behaving toward 3. There are particular circumstances in which the actual spectator may disagree with the I-spectator, but that does not affect the general mechanism just described, which is the mechanism through which the rules of just conducts, which are the base of the judgment of the I-spectator, are formed (TMS, III.3). 320 VOLUME 13, NUMBER 2, MAY 2016

IS ADAM SMITH S IMPARTIAL SPECTATOR SELFLESS? a stranger, we can judge ourselves impartially, and we properly think we deserve approbation (TMS, III.3.22 25). The more self-command a situation requires the more self-approbation it generates. This implies that we have a higher chance of mastering self-command and therefore our ability to detach ourselves from ourselves if we are often and regularly exposed to hardship, danger, and misfortunes (TMS, III.3.26). But rather than praising this achievement, Smith seems to condemn it! Under the boisterous and stormy sky of war and faction, of public tumult and confusion, the sturdy severity of self-command prospers the most, and can be the most successfully cultivated. Under these hard circumstances self-command will prosper but it does so at the expense of humanity. Humanity needs to be neglected, and every time we neglect humanity we weaken it. But, in such situations, the strongest suggestions of humanity must frequently be stifled or neglected; and every such neglect necessarily tends to weaken the principle of humanity (TMS, III.3.37, my emphasis). Situations in which a soldier needs to violate the property and the life of others always tend to diminish, and too often to extinguish altogether, that sacred regard to both, which is the foundation of justice and humanity (ibid., my emphasis). 4 When self-command is strongest, so that we are completely detached from ourselves, we become selfless, but that means we lose our humanity, our sensibility to the feelings of others, which is the foundation of manhood (TMS, III.3.34). The man who suffers the loss of his father or of his son in the same way as the loss of the father or of the son of a stranger is a moral monster, not a moral hero: such 4. This may not mean the complete and categorical impossibility of achieving both perfect humanity and perfect self-command at the same time. In theory the humanity and self-command could be achieved simultaneously. But Smith seems to imply that in practice it is highly unlikely. The person best fitted by nature for acquiring the former of those two sets of virtues, is likewise best fitted for acquiring the latter. The man who feels the most for the joys and sorrows of others, is best fitted for acquiring the most complete control of his own joys and sorrow. The man of the most exquisite humanity, is naturally the most capable of acquiring the highest degree of self-command. He may not, however, always have acquired it; and it very frequently happens that he has not (TMS, III.3.36, my emphasis). And more explicitly: The situations in which the gentle virtue of humanity can be most happily cultivated, are by no means the same with those which are best fitted for forming the austere virtue of self-command. The man who is himself at ease can best attend to the distress of others. The man who is himself exposed to hardships is most immediately called upon to attend to, and to control his own feelings. In the mild sunshine of undisturbed tranquillity, in the calm retirement of undissipated and philosophical leisure, the soft virtue of humanity flourishes the most, and is capable of the highest improvement. But, in such situations, the greatest and noblest exertions of self-command have little exercise. Under the boisterous and stormy sky of war and faction, of public tumult and confusion, the sturdy severity of self-command prospers the most, and can be the most successfully cultivated. But, in such situations, the strongest suggestions of humanity must frequently be stifled or neglected; and every such neglect necessarily tends to weaken the principle of humanity (III.3.37, my emphasis). Maybe we should aim at achieving both humanity and self-command, but in practice we will face a trade-off: if we are under a mild sunshine, we cannot at the same time be under a stormy sky. VOLUME 13, NUMBER 2, MAY 2016 321

PAGANELLI unnatural indifference, far from exciting our applause, would incur our highest disapprobation (III.3.13). Smith condemns the two sets of philosophers which preach that morality is based on selflessness. The whining and melancholy moralists (TMS, III.3.9) who want to annihilate ourselves by raising others to our level with the love of mankind. The ancient Stoics (III.3.11) want to annihilate ourselves by diminishing ourselves to the level of others with the most perfect self-command. Both, perhaps, have carried their doctrines a good deal beyond the just standard of nature and propriety (III.3.8). The development of the I-spectator from partial to impartial is a lifetime project, and even then it is never perfectly achieved. Yet, our ability to see the behavior of others and of ourselves from a distance, as a spectator who is not connected to us or the others would do, is our potential to judge impartially our own behavior and the behavior of others. This development of an impartial spectator within us is a universal feature of humankind. It is the mechanism through which our morality develops, regardless of the content of our morality. And it is a process that requires a self. The annihilation of our self by raising others to our level, by making us feel for others in the same way we feel for ourselves, would make us like the whining moralists. The annihilation of our self by lowering ourselves to the level of others, by making us as indifferent to ourselves as we are indifferent to strangers, would make us like the ancient Stoics : lacking humanity. A well-developed human being is a person able to recognize and cultivate his own self and to place it at the proper distance, to observe it neither from too close nor from too far, to balance his self-command with his humanity, and not to crush it with one or the other. The potential development of our I-spectator as an impartial viewer and judge of our actions is therefore a universal feature of humankind. But the impartial spectator cannot be selfless it cannot be too far away just like it cannot be selfcentered it cannot be too close it requires a balanced cultivation of our self. References Smith, Adam. 1976 [1790] (TMS). The Theory of Moral Sentiments, eds. D. D. Raphael and A. L. Macfie. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 322 VOLUME 13, NUMBER 2, MAY 2016

IS ADAM SMITH S IMPARTIAL SPECTATOR SELFLESS? About the Author Maria Pia Paganelli is an Associate Professor of Economics at Trinity University. Dr. Paganelli works on Adam Smith, David Hume, eighteenth-century monetary theories, and the links between the Scottish Enlightenment and behavioral economics. She is the author of numerous articles and is the coeditor of the Oxford Handbook of Adam Smith. Her email address is maria.paganelli@trinity.edu. Go to archive of Watchpad section Go to May 2016 issue Discuss this article at Journaltalk: http://journaltalk.net/articles/5918 VOLUME 13, NUMBER 2, MAY 2016 323