Humanistic Thought, Understanding, and the Nature of Grasp

Similar documents
DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

Key definitions Action Ad hominem argument Analytic A priori Axiom Bayes s theorem

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Kant & Transcendental Idealism

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

Neurophilosophy and free will VI

Department of Philosophy

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

MISSOURI S FRAMEWORK FOR CURRICULAR DEVELOPMENT IN MATH TOPIC I: PROBLEM SOLVING

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

A Framework for the Good

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY. Chair: Karánn Durland (Fall 2018) and Mark Hébert (Spring 2019) Emeritus: Roderick Stewart

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT FALL SEMESTER 2009 COURSE OFFERINGS

Epistemology Naturalized

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Small Group Assignment 8: Science Replaces Scholasticism

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Why Computers are not Intelligent: An Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Uganda, morality was derived from God and the adult members were regarded as teachers of religion. God remained the canon against which the moral

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Stout s teleological theory of action

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Citation Philosophy and Psychology (2009): 1.

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

What is a counterexample?

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

BIBLICAL INTEGRATION IN SCIENCE AND MATH. September 29m 2016

Philosophy Courses-1

Metaphysical atomism and the attraction of materialism.

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

science, knowledge, and understanding

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Philosophy Courses-1

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

PHILOSOPHY-PHIL (PHIL)

Why Rosenzweig-Style Midrashic Approach Makes Rational Sense: A Logical (Spinoza-like) Explanation of a Seemingly Non-logical Approach

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

Causation and Free Will

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

Mandelbrot Set Padawan

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

Outline Lesson 2 - Philosophy & Ethics: Says Who?

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Neo-Confucianism: Metaphysics, Mind, and Morality

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

The Construction of Empirical Concepts and the Establishment of the Real Possibility of Empirical Lawlikeness in Kant's Philosophy of Science

2018 Philosophy of Management Conference Paper submission NORMATIVITY AND DESCRIPTION: BUSINESS ETHICS AS A MORAL SCIENCE

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Philosophy of Economics and Politics

NOTE: Courses, rooms, times and instructors are subject to change; please see Timetable of Classes on HokieSpa for current information

It Ain t What You Prove, It s the Way That You Prove It. a play by Chris Binge

Machine Consciousness, Mind & Consciousness

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Unit 1 Philosophy of Education: Introduction INTRODUCTION

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

PHILOSOPHY (PHIL) Philosophy (PHIL) 1

THEOLOGY IN THE FLESH

Templeton Fellowships at the NDIAS

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

A Wesleyan Approach to Knowledge

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos):

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

Nation, Science and Religion in Nehru s Discovery of India

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Class 2 - Foundationalism

Transcription:

Humanistic Thought, Understanding, and the Nature of Grasp Michael Strevens Guggenheim Research Proposal Wilhelm Dilthey and other nineteenth-century German thinkers envisaged a deep methodological division between natural science (Naturwissenschaft) and the systematic study of humankind (Geisteswissenschaft), whether anthropological, psychological, or literary. The one would achieve its goals by explaining phenomena (erklären); the other by interpreting and understanding minds (verstehen). In the twenty-first century, the techniques of the natural sciences controlled experiment, statistical analysis, causal and other formal mathematical models have largely taken over the Geisteswissenschaften. The university humanities departments are the last refuge of scholars claiming to apply methods quite foreign to the natural sciences, and their existence is often defended for their supposed ability to improve the moral fiber of liberal arts students or to inspire creativity rather than because of any special insight they impart into the things humans do. In the 1950s and 1960s, this drama of conquest and capitulation was played out in a venue of particular significance to philosophers of science like me, in a debate over the nature of historical explanation. The estimable logical empiricist philosopher Carl Hempel argued that the explanations proffered by historians work, or at least should work, in exactly the same way as explanations in physics, by deducing the phenomenon or state of affairs to be explained from laws of nature and background conditions. The implication, 1

it seemed, was that history was a kind of immature social science, a worthy enterprise but much in need of systematization and a firm scientific hand. Philosophers of history fought back by claiming a distinctive role for firstperson perspective, for seeing decisions from the inside, for grasping the networks of language, meaning, and affect in which the things they hoped to explain were embedded. In the end, however, they ceded the philosophical ground. While their ideas continue to live a vigorous life in some parts of the humanities as demonstrated, for example, by the continued influence of Hayden White s Metahistory in epistemology and the philosophy of science the notion that explanation and understanding take the same form in physics, psychology, and historical studies is well entrenched. I would like to change that. The philosophy of science has not stood still since Hempel. Whereas Hempel emphasized deduction from laws of nature, contemporary philosophers, including me, see explanation as a matter of finding a thing s place in the causal order. To explain an event, then, is to describe its causes; to explain an ongoing state of affairs is to describe the causal structure that sustains it. This hardly reduces the scientific pressure on historical scholarship, however. The great majority of historical studies concern the nature and effects of one sort of causal structure or another. This is most obvious in historical narratives that attempt to understand singular events, such as the outbreak of the First World War, by understanding their causes. But it is equally true of much social, economic, and cultural history. Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie, seeking to understand the lives of the Cathars in medieval southern France, or Alan Bray, seeking to understand the implications and accommodations of homosexuality in Renaissance England, can be seen as investigating the causal consequences of particular historically embedded social structures. (I realize that this is a controversial claim. Let me emphasize that it is not reductive, as causation need not work at the level of the individual: customs, morals, and theological doctrines all have causal power to shape society.) As 2

in Hempel s time, it is hard to resist the temptation to move the departments of history to the social sciences. (Some are already there.) Now I must admit that I am a perpetrator of the unifying trend in the philosophy of explanation. My 2009 book Depth (Harvard University Press) advances a view on which all explanation of occurrences, states of affairs, and patterns of behavior in the material world including the world of human bodies and minds is causal. It follows that all (or at least much) historical explanation is in a broad sense causal. Yet I find myself with an unabating sympathy for Hempel s opponents. Something about historical understanding is decidedly humanistic, I feel, and to some extent historians pursue goals that are foreign to the social sciences. How can that be, if explanation in particle physics and explanation in social history are governed by the same methodological norms? The answer, I believe, lies in the old distinction between explanation and understanding. I do not, however, have in mind the dichotomy envisaged by Droysen, in which one branch of knowledge pursues explanation and the other understanding. All knowers, across the sciences and the humanities, strive for both explanation and understanding. Explanation is the same thing for everyone. But understanding is not. The last decade has seen an explosion of work in (Anglo) epistemology and philosophy of science on the nature of understanding. I have been been a part of it, espousing a view on which there is a close relation between explanation and understanding: to understand why a phenomenon obtains is to grasp a correct explanation for the phenomenon. (The phenomenon might be a singular event, an effect such as the Northern Lights, a law of nature such as the second law of thermodynamics, or a pattern of obedience or friendship seen in a certain social group.) Correct explanations in both physics and history conform to the same causal requirements. But and this is the idea I hope to explore with Guggenheim support grasping, and therefore understanding, answer to different 3

requirements in the sciences than in the humanities. The sciences, because of their concern for objectivity, admit only third-person forms of grasping; the humanities by contrast allow every possible kind of grasp. Humanistic historians take advantage of this latitude, and so in their writing explore varieties of grasp, hence varieties of understanding, that are off limits to scientists. This idea hinges, of course, on the notion of grasp, a kind of relation by which the mind latches on to something in the world, such as an explanatory causal structure. To give you a sense of the relation in question, let me start with a very simple scientific example. Trilobites are arthropods that is a fact that is easy to come to know. You can verify it, if you don t believe me and don t already know it, in a few seconds on Wikipedia. Far more difficult than attaining knowledge about trilobites is attaining understanding. Understanding requires grasp, and to grasp what it means for something to be an arthropod is a real intellectual achievement, distinguishing the biological sophisticate from the trivia champion. Likewise, grasping a correct explanation for a phenomenon the essence of understanding why the phenomenon obtains is far more difficult than simply knowing a correct explanation. It is possible to have knowledge of a complete explanation that is quite as shallow as the dilettante s knowledge about trilobites, far too shallow to qualify as understanding. You can imagine someone a kind of gravitational idiot savant who has complete knowledge of the explanation why the earth orbits the sun, in the following sense. They can recite the equations according to which the mass of the sun imparts a curvature to space-time and the earth travels the most direct route along this curvature, resulting in its elliptical orbit. They can perform the mathematical derivation. They can tell you why the derivation constitutes a valid scientific explanation. They have knowledge of all of these things, in the Wikipedia sense, and yet they do not really grasp what it is for space and time to form a single four-dimensional manifold with variable curvature, or for a certain trajectory to be the straightest line through such a space. They are a model 4

answerer of exam questions on the topic they can calculate degrees of curvature and straight paths to the n th digit but so tenuous is their understanding of the subject matter that from their point of view, they might as well be answering questions about traffic patterns in Manila or the syntactic structure of Old Church Slavonic. What is needed to transform mere knowledge of an explanation into grasp? There are, I think, three answers to be found in the history of philosophy, from Plato on. First, grasp might involve a special kind of representation, an idea that motivates dichotomies such as William James distinction between acquaintance with and mere knowledge about or Husserl s distinction between proper and improper presenting. This approach is, however, better suited to accounting for grasp of everyday facts and events than for grasp of abstract states of affairs such as space-time s curvature, of which we can have no direct acquaintance. Second, grasp might involve extensive knowledge of a certain sort: grasp of the fact that trilobites are arthropods might be constituted by further knowledge about trilobites and arthropods, and grasp of the fact that spacetime is curved might be enabled by further knowledge of non-euclidean geometry. But this cannot be the complete story: if the further knowledge is itself of the shallow Wikipedia variety, then the knower seems to fall short of true grasp and genuine understanding. Third, grasp might involve abilities of a certain sort, such as the ability to classify organisms as arthropods or to prove geometrical theorems. Again there is a worry that it is possible to exhibit such abilities while having a shallow grip on the subject matter, along with the objection that the proposal gets the cognitive order of things wrong: I have these abilities because of my grasp of the subject matter, not vice versa. In my Guggenheim project, I will develop a different approach that draws on aspects of all three answers above: to grasp that a state of affairs obtains is to have command of certain strategies for recognizing that it obtains. Grasp 5

involves an ability, then, but a special sort of ability one that the gravitational idiot savant, I hope to show, does not possess. A good part of the project will be devoted to distinguishing recognitional capacities that are sufficiently rich and comprehensive to bestow grasp and thus understanding from those that are, intuitively, too parasitic on other agents (or other devices) to enable more than mere representation and knowledge. Central is the idea that the capacity must go all the way from raw input such as sensory experience to recognition itself. Going all the way may not be easy, but there are many ways to do it many ways, that is, to implement the sort of recognitional capacity that constitutes grasp. There are, in particular, many ways to implement a capacity to recognize explanatorily relevant causal structures, thereby achieving understanding. In short, there are many routes to understanding. The canons of scientific writing the rules that tacitly govern the prose that goes into scientific journals and conference papers and other official organs of scientific reporting allow only simple, direct, literal forms of communication; thus, they encourage formal or at least formulaic representations of causal structure, such as mathematical causal models and the tools of game theory. The reader, as a consequence, gains a grasp of causal structure that is in some sense objective and third personal, the kind of grasp that a wholly alien or artificial intelligence might equally easily achieve. Historical writing, by contrast, ranges far more widely in the means that it uses to put its readers in touch with causal-explanatory facts. The scientific route is permissible, but so are others that depend to a great extent on the humanness of the reader: a first-person perspective, emotional engagement, moralizing discourse, wordplay, genre, narrative structure and other literary tropes. I will argue that these devices are not merely routes to grasping causal-explanatory structure, but are themselves partially constitutive of that grasp because they are essential parts of the recognitional capacities that make up grasp. The project will take the form of three long essays (about 20,000 words 6

each), the whole of which could be published as a short book. The first essay draws on my previous work on explanation to argue that historical explanation is largely causal. (More generally, it investigates the nature of explanation across the humanities, mathematics, and philosophy.) The second essay explores the nature of grasp, developing the recognitional capacity theory. The third essay applies these conclusions to historical understanding, finding a place in history, and indeed in inquiry generally, for forms of understanding that are not scientific but intrinsically humanistic. 7