Florida State University Libraries

Similar documents
A Framework for Thinking Ethically

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES My Answers

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

The Pleasure Imperative

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Nietzsche and Aristotle in contemporary virtue ethics

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Messiah College s identity and mission foundational values educational objectives. statements of faith community covenant.

Hoong Juan Ru. St Joseph s Institution International. Candidate Number Date: April 25, Theory of Knowledge Essay

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Consequentialism. Mill s Theory of Utility

The Jesuit Character of Seattle University: Some Suggestions as a Contribution to Strategic Planning

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

The Need for Metanormativity: A Response to Christmas

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

ETHICS (IE MODULE) 1. COURSE DESCRIPTION

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Justice and the fair innings argument. Dr Tom Walker Queen s University Belfast

Ethics in a Historical View & A Framework for Ethical Decision Making

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2014 Russell Marcus

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

[name] [course] [teaching assistant s name] [discussion day and time] [question being answered] [date turned in] Cultural Relativism

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

APPENDIX A NOTE ON JOHN PAUL II, VERITATIS SPLENDOR (1993) The Encyclical is primarily a theological document, addressed to the Pope's fellow Roman

Saint Joseph High School Christian Service Program Student Agreement

Logic clearly dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few or the needs of the one (Spock and Captain Kirk).

Prentice Hall U.S. History Modern America 2013

THE QUESTION OF "UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY?" IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS

Year 9: Be With Me (We are Strong Together: CCCB)

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333

Prentice Hall United States History Survey Edition 2013

The How and Why of Love An Introduction to Evangelical Ethics, by Michael Hill.

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age


FOLLOWING CHRIST IN THE WORLD

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Rethinking Development: the Centrality of Human Rights

Chapter 12: Areas of knowledge Ethics (p. 363)

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

TABLE OF CONTENTS. Lesson 10 August 5, 2018 Romans 2:1-12 Who Should Judge?. Page 1

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Text 1: Philosophers and the Pursuit of Wisdom. Topic 5: Ancient Greece Lesson 3: Greek Thinkers, Artists, and Writers

Comments on Lasersohn

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Course Coordinator Dr Melvin Chen Course Code. CY0002 Course Title. Ethics Pre-requisites. NIL No of AUs 3 Contact Hours

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

PHIL 202: IV:

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Johnson_Understanding Ethical Statements in the Educational Learning Environment_ docx

MONEY MASTER OR SERVANT? No one can serve two masters Matthew 6:24

Knowledge, Reality, and Values CORC 1210 SYLLABUS

CHAPTER 2. The Classical School

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

EL CAMINO COLLEGE Behavioral & Social Sciences Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy, Summer 2016 Section 2510, MTWTh, 8:00-10:05 a.m.

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

PL-101: Introduction to Philosophy Fall of 2007, Juniata College Instructor: Xinli Wang

Should We Assess the Basic Premises of an Argument for Truth or Acceptability?

NORTH SOUTH UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY DHAKA, BANGLADESH

Module 7: ethical behavior 1. Steps in this module: 2. Complete the case study Framework for Ethical Decision Making

Freedom of Religion and Law Schools: Trinity Western University

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Lincoln-Douglas: The Inquistive Debate of Philosophy

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

the negative reason existential fallacy

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Transcription:

Florida State University Libraries Undergraduate Research Honors Ethical Issues and Life Choices (PHI2630) 2013 How We Should Make Moral Career Choices Rebecca Hallock Follow this and additional works at the FSU Digital Library. For more information, please contact lib-ir@fsu.edu

Rebecca Hallock How We Should Make Moral Career Choices Keywords: Ethics, Career, Decisions, Philosophy, Choices This paper will respond to previous approaches for choosing the most moral career. It will provide motivation for making an ethical career choice not based on a consequentialism. Natural Law Theory will be used in combination with Virtue Ethics to build a framework for evaluating intentions in order to make a moral career selection. A basic method for such an evaluation will be outlined. Furthermore, implications to human dignity will be discussed with reference to consequentialism. Finally, major objections to this method of career selection will be addressed. 1

Introduction In the past, sociologists and philosophers have proposed different outlooks on making ethical career choices. Most notable among these ideas are the supposed moral high-ground of working in the charity sector and the consequentialist proposal that it is best to choose a high paying career so that more resources can be donated to humanitarian efforts. I will argue that both of these proposals for the most morally beneficent career are too simplistic to deal with the basic but complex question how should (in the moral sense) each person spend their life? Essentially the question being asked is how do I know which lifestyle is the right one? The argument to follow consists of three major sections. The first portion of my proposal will show that the above two proposals for career choice are too simplistic to be applicable in our society. The second aspect of the argument will draw from ethics of Natural Law Theories and Virtue Ethics to support the importance of character development by means of identifying the best intentions involved in making a decisions; accepting those with positive intentions and rejecting those choices with negatively motivated intentions. A discussion of the implications to the dignity of the human person and the motivations for making decisions in this way will be included. Finally, I will briefly address potential objections and potential areas for future discussion. I will argue that we should adopt a method of career choice which focuses on individual intentions and character development which will more effectively uphold the dignity of the human person. Consequentialism and Career Choice Traditional ideas about choosing an ethical career often point to work in the charity sector as the most highly regarded option. In his article Replaceability, Career Choice, and Making a 2

Difference, MacAskill argues that such workers are replaceable and that it is better for a person to become a professional philanthropist than work for a charitable organization i. He makes his argument from a consequentialist perspective. Consequentialism holds that the evaluation of an act or manner of acting depends only upon the consequences of the behavior in question. If a consequentialist evaluates acts by comparing the resulting pleasure and pain of such an act he is called a Classical Utilitarian ii. Varying strands of Consequentialism emphasize a variety of schema when evaluating an action s consequences. MacAskill claims that the highest moral good when choosing a career is that which will result in the most concrete benefit to others. Essentially, he says that it is better to choose to become a philanthropist than a charity worker if one has the means to do so since a philanthropist can provide more benefit to their charity of choice iii. One problem with MacAskill s argument is that if everyone who had the skill to become a philanthropist actually did so society would likely have an excess of these philanthropists and not enough charity workers. MacAskill does qualify his argument. He knows that not everyone he convinces should go into philanthropy, but if that s the case, it doesn t put us much closer to deciding how we ought to live. Ultimately, both charity workers and philanthropists serve society well, but so do engineers, artists, doctors, clergy, etc. For example, suppose that some charitable religious organization chooses to expend the funds and related resources to design and build a church in a third-world country or in a poor area. Some people might protest to this by arguing that such money should be used to fund additional necessities such as food and shelter or education, however, once the church is completed what will the people there say? Likely many of them will be glad to have the structure there free for them to use as shelter and to appreciate and find meaning represented in it (not that we shouldn t provide for necessities, but rather this 3

also has worth). It is not realistic to say that one career has the definitive moral high ground over another. Basic Precepts for Natural Law Ethics I have chosen to format a method for choosing a career based on Natural Law Theory. There are three main reasons for this. Firstly, it will allow for the flexibility needed to be applicable to the decision making of a wide variety of people. In practice, this should yield a wide variety of chosen careers. Finally, it provides a structure and rhetoric which can be used to evaluate potential options outside of a consequentialist framework. The basic tenets of Aquinas theory, which is viewed as the preeminent Natural Law Theory, are that the natural law is God-given, it is authoritative over mankind, and man can know this law. Furthermore, the good is prior to the right, right action is that which is properly ordered to the good, there are ways in which right action might be improperly ordered to the good, and some of these defects can be described as rules iv. Not all Natural Law Theorists accept all of these precepts, and it will not be necessary for us to accept all of them in order to build a method of choosing a career. It will be sufficient to accept that there are at least some absolute moral laws, that the good is prior to the right, and that we can discern some basic rules for determining the rightness of an action. Natural Law Theory and Decision Making Aquinas theory proposes various methods for actually determining when an action is not ordered properly to the good and I will not examine all of them here. Instead I will propose two parts which will be most easily accessible for use in making an ethical choice of career. The 4

method essentially consists of utilizing Virtue Ethics to evaluate our intentions. Virtue Ethics asserts that the moral life is the virtuous life. Unlike many other moral theories, it emphasizes the importance of being a virtuous person rather than a set of rules for identifying the most moral actions. Assuming that I am successful in choosing the right action I should expect positive outcomes to result. So I will not choose to be a philanthropist because of some great good I can cause, but because it is the right thing for me to do and it benefits society as a secondary result of it being the right thing to do. Therefore, I can expect that right action will prophet the world as well as my own moral character though this is not required for an action to be right or good in the sense indicated by Natural Law. By my own examination, I should be able to determine what my intentions are behind a particular action. With some practice I should also be able to acquire an understanding of which situations will likely lead me to a moral predicament where I d be more liable to make a choice that conflicts with the good. So I could choose to become a professional philanthropist, but suppose I do this (primarily) because people tell me it will benefit society and they ll be very pleased with me. Over time it seems likely that I will simply do philanthropy as a game in which I try to help as many people as I can in order to gain moral status and feel very pleased with myself. Some critics will likely say that this doesn t decrease the moral value of my philanthropy and that might be true, but in such a case it would be useful to compare my moral fiber to that of a philanthropist who did if for selfless reasons; because they truly believed philanthropy was the highest moral ground and best way to improve society. I should also compare the case to a charity worker. My argument fails if it can be said that I, in my selfish philanthropy, still have 5

the moral high-ground over a charity worker who does their job as a selfless service. Notice that my question is not who helped more people? but rather which decision holds more closely to the moral good? To rephrase the argument I can begin by saying that there exists a moral good. This moral good is often indicated by the resulting benefit to others, and to myself (morally speaking). The benefit to my moral being can be understood through the examination of my intentions in the context of my inclinations towards or away from virtue. Hence, I should choose to live in such a way that will benefit society, and in which I can reasonable believe that my moral character will be strengthened. Our Intentions In order for the preceding argument to be useful, it will require a method for evaluating our intentions. Examining my reasons for doing or not doing some action or, in this case, for selecting a particular career will inform me of which options hold the greater moral worth for me. Therefore, an individual should choose to act in opposition to their negative moral tendencies, and in accord with their positive ones. The idea behind this is not plainly that following poor moral intentions will lead to poor moral consequences for society, but that following poor moral intentions negatively impacts my moral character and is opposed to the good, and this may in turn negatively impact society. In order to evaluate an intention to act two parts are needed. First, the intention must be examined to determine the contributing factors. When making a decision there are often multiple facets, and some of these are negative while others are positive (meaning morally ill and morally beneficial). Second, these aspects of the intention in question will need to be given different 6

weights. These need not be cardinally ranked. Some reasons for acting in a certain way are more compelling than others and the goal is to act in opposition to the most compelling negatively moral reasons and in accord with the most compelling positively moral reasons. Suppose for example that I want to choose between working in the charity sector and becoming a professional philanthropist. Suppose also that I have the tendency for greediness. I want to become a professional philanthropist because I know I can benefit many people this way, but at the same time I know that being a professional philanthropist will afford me certain luxuries that I would not have as a charity worker. I know that I would be an effective charity worker and I really want to help people, but I m convinced that I could help more people as a professional philanthropist and because of my selfish desires I m more inclined to choose this path. Where s the moral high-ground? The answer to this question depends on the weight of my various reasons. If the determining factor in my decision is that I want to keep the luxuries I would have as a philanthropist, then the better moral decision is to become a charity worker because then I am improving my moral character by acting directly against my own selfish ways. On the other hand, if helping more people is what really matters to me, then I would be justified in concluding that philanthropy is a better choice. It s not an issue that different individuals will draw different conclusions about which decision they should make. In fact, this is a strength of the argument. It seeks to get away from consequentialism and develop some basic method by which we can realistically evaluate our (career) choices, and because not everyone can have the same career it s realistic that not everyone will make their evaluation and arrive at the same decision. I would argue even that not everyone from similar socio-economic status should arrive at the same decision, since their personal tendencies will still be at least somewhat varied. 7

Human Dignity At the beginning of this essay I claimed that I wanted to put space between career choice and consequentialism, but I didn t give a more proper treatment of why we should reject the consequentialist s reasoning apart from it being too simplistic to deal with the question of career choice. In addition to the impracticality of consequentialism for this issue, the implications of using consequentialism to treat major decisions in a person s life should be considered. In MacAskill s essay, he assumes that we can be most moral by doing the most possible concrete good in the world v. Hence, as a philanthropist the measure of how good I am would be the number of people I am able to help which is quantifiable as a sum of money I donate to humanitarian efforts. Each humanitarian action gets reduced to some number value. In order for this to be the case, I effectively also reduce the value of those I m able to help to the value of the moral benefit they give to my reputation as a philanthropist. Phrased this way, professional philanthropy could almost look like an injustice. If we truly follow the implications of the consequentialist ideology then we effectively put a concrete (though not directly monetary) value on each person in need and this is objectionable. Another way to view this is to consider the moral value of other occupations according to consequentialism. Suppose Tom is a talented musician. He has just been offered a very high paying job creating commercial music arrangements. He wants to decide if he should (A) accept the job offer an use it to engage in philanthropy or if he should (B) keep his original plan to work as a concert musician and write sonatas in his spare time. Tom knows that if he chooses B he will not have an excess of wealth, but he ll be quite happy and will be able to contribute honestly to society by benefiting other people with his gift of music. He also knows that if he chooses A 8

he ll have quite a lot of money and be able to help a comparable number of people in a much more significant way, but he will do this at the price of having to produce truly awful, uninspiring music. According to MacAskill s reasoning, Tom should choose A. Isn t this unfair to Tom in that it reduces the value of his character to the amount of quantifiable good he can do? Perhaps Tom will choose B and go on to create a Mozart-worthy masterpiece which will benefit others for years to come, though in a less-direct way. The point is that consequentialism is likely to reduce either the giver or the receiver (or both) of a good deed to a concrete value, and this doesn t account for all the good which is pleasing to, and sometimes even required for the well-being of, a human person. Two Objections The method I have outlined for choosing the most ethical career still leaves much room for development, however, I will briefly address two objections which seem to be the most obvious ones. The first objection is aimed at Natural Law Theory, namely that I have made too many assumptions by forming a method around it. It will be easy to object to my argument on the grounds that there is no absolute moral good or that such good cannot be known. In defense of my argument I can appeal to its pragmatic weight. It should be useful in actually assessing career options. I need not show definitively that the precepts are true, and that is not the topic of this paper, however, someone wishing to derail my framework will need to show, at a minimum, that one or more of the precepts are false and even then he or she might also have to show that it is impractical. 9

The second objection comes from relativism. I claim that there are at least some absolute moral laws/goods, but my framework allows that everyone will have different intentions to evaluate in different contexts so does that mean I m also saying that the moral good is different for each person? The answer is clearly no. The approach is individualistic, not relativistic. Each person is different, but the good itself is not. I might not always be able to determine definitively which career between too options is closer to the ideal good, but I can at least narrow it down considerably. I might be left with two closely comparable options and have trouble deciding between them (determining which better upholds the good). This allows for personal preference, however, exercising this preference does not have any bearing on the good itself. Conclusion In conclusion, a consequentialist approach is too simplistic to realistically handle the question of ethical career choice. There are absolute moral goods, and these ought to be upheld. We can expect moral career decisions which act in accord with the moral good to have positive effects such as societal benefit and personal moral development. Hence, moral career choices can be made by evaluating intentions within a personal context which seeks the moral good. Using such a method will better serve to handle the complexities of such a decision while also seeking to uphold the dignity of the human person. Although the method outlined still has considerable flaws, it has the advantage of outlining a realistic approach for choosing a career in a moral framework. Hopefully, future thinkers can consider the details more thoroughly or provide other potential methods for career selection not based on Natural Law Theories. i (MacAskill, 2013) ii (Sinnott-Armstrong, 2011) 10

iii (MacAskill, 2013) iv (Murphy, 2011) v (MacAskill, 2013) Ed. K. Lee Lerner, B. W. (2006). It Was a Selfish Decision but I Never Regretted It. Retrieved September 16, 2013, from Opposing Viewpoints in Context, Family in Society: Essential Primary Sources: http://ic.galegroup.com/ic/ovic/primarysourcesdetailspage/primarysourcesdetailswindo w?failovertype=&query=&prodid=ovic&windowstate=normal&contentmodules=&m ode=view&displaygroupname=primarysources&limiter=&currpage=&disablehighlight ing=false&displaygroups= MacAskill, W. (2013). Replaceability, Career Choice, and Making a Difference. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. Murphy, M. (2011, September 27). The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics. Retrieved November 2013, from Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-law-ethics/ Paul, S. K. (2013, February 1). Intention. Retrieved October 15, 2013, from The International Encyclopedia of Ethics: http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee561/pdf Rachels, J. R. (2012). Kant and Respect for Persons. In The Elements of Moral Philosophy (pp. 136-145). New York: McGraw-Hill. Rachels, J. R. (2012). The Debate over Utilitarianism. In The Elements of Moral Philosophy (pp. 110-124). New York: McGraw-Hill. Rachels, J. R. (2012). Virtue Ethics. In The Elements of Moral Philosophy (pp. 157-172). New York: McGraw-Hill. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2011, September 27). Consequentialism. Retrieved November 2013, from Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/ Trout, M. A. (2008). Strategic Reliabilism: A Naturalistic Approach to Epistemology. Philosophy Compass, 1049-1065. 11