Evidence and the epistemic theory of causality

Similar documents
FAILURES TO ACT AND FAILURES OF ADDITIVITY. Carolina Sartorio University of Wisconsin-Madison

Resultant Luck and the Thirsty Traveler * There is moral luck to the extent that the moral assessment of agents notably, the

The Causal Relata in the Law Page 1 16/6/2006

Degrees of Belief II

*Please note that tutorial times and venues will be organised independently with your teaching tutor.

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

is knowledge normative?

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Aboutness and Justification

what makes reasons sufficient?

Causation and Freedom * over whether the mysterious relation of agent- causation is possible, the literature

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Sensitivity to Reasons and Actual Sequences * Carolina Sartorio (University of Arizona)

Postmodal Metaphysics

What is a counterexample?

Max Deutsch: The Myth of the Intuitive: Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Method. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, xx pp.

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

Failing to Do the Impossible * and you d rather have him go through the trouble of moving the chair himself, so you

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

UNRAVELLING THE METHODOLOGY OF CAUSAL PLURALISM 4. Anton Froeyman & Leen De Vreese

Pollock s Theory of Defeasible Reasoning

The Question of Metaphysics

IS EVIDENCE NON-INFERENTIAL?

Two reasons why epistemic reasons are not object-given reasons

Causation and Responsibility

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

The readings for the course are separated into the following two categories:

Analogy and Pursuitworthiness

Self-Knowledge for Humans. By QUASSIM CASSAM. (Oxford: OUP, Pp. xiii +

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

The Level-Splitting View and the Non-Akrasia Constraint

Vihvelin on Frankfurt-Style Cases and the Actual- Sequence View

Inferential Evidence. Jeff Dunn. The Evidence Question: When, and under what conditions does an agent. have proposition E as evidence (at t)?

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Living on the Edge: Against Epistemic Permissivism

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

This handout follows the handout on Hume on causation. You should read that handout first.

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

-INFSTITUTEE LOGY. Probability, Explanation, and Reasoning LISE 2RARIES2000. Roger White. B. A. Philosophy University of New South Wales

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

HOW TO BE RESPONSIBLE FOR SOMETHING WITHOUT CAUSING IT* Carolina Sartorio University of Wisconsin-Madison

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Analysis Advance Access published June 12, On the Parallels between Theoretical and Practical Rationality: Reply to Setiya

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Abstract: According to perspectivism about moral obligation, our obligations are affected by

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Intentionality and Partial Belief

Keywords precise, imprecise, sharp, mushy, credence, subjective, probability, reflection, Bayesian, epistemology

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

My brain made me do it: The exclusion argument against free will, and what s wrong with it 1. Christian List and Peter Menzies

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Hume's Representation Argument Against Rationalism 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina/Chapel Hill

Plato's Epistemology PHIL October Introduction

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Constructing the World

Probability: A Philosophical Introduction Mind, Vol July 2006 Mind Association 2006

Critical Scientific Realism

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

My brain made me do it: The exclusion argument against free will, and what s wrong with it 1. Christian List and Peter Menzies

A Priori Bootstrapping

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Jones s brain that enables him to control Jones s thoughts and behavior. The device is

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Mark Schroeder s Hypotheticalism: Agent-neutrality, Moral Epistemology, and Methodology

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Bayesian Probability

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Statement of Research

Causation as Metaphor a Catachresis

Chances, Credences and Counterfactuals

Explanatory Indispensability and Deliberative Indispensability: Against Enoch s Analogy Alex Worsnip University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill

Believing and Acting: Voluntary Control and the Pragmatic Theory of Belief

Disjunctive Effects and the Logic of Causation. Roberta Ballarin ABSTRACT

Platonism, Alienation, and Negativity

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Mental Processes and Synchronicity

Crawford L. Elder, Familiar Objects and Their Shadows, Cambridge University Press, 2011, 222pp., $85.00 (hardback), ISBN

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice Andrés Perea Excerpt More information

Argumentation without arguments. Henry Prakken

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

WHAT IF BIZET AND VERDI HAD BEEN COMPATRIOTS?

Epistemic Akrasia. SOPHIE HOROWITZ Massachusetts Institute of Technology

knowledge is belief for sufficient (objective and subjective) reason

Transcription:

Evidence and the epistemic theory of causality Michael Wilde and Jon Williamson, Philosophy, University of Kent m.e.wilde@kent.ac.uk 8 January 2015 1 / 21

Overview maintains that causality is an epistemic relation, so that causality is taken to be a feature of the way a subject represents the world rather than a nonepistemic feature of the world. Objective: In this paper, we take the opportunity to briefly rehearse some arguments in favour of the epistemic theory of causality, and then present a version of the theory developed in [Williamson, 2005, Williamson, 2006, Williamson, 2009, Williamson, 2011, Williamson, 2013]. Lastly, we provide some possible responses to an objection based upon recent work in epistemology. 2 / 21

Overview 1 2 3 4 3 / 21

Standardly, there are mechanistic and difference-making theories of causality. The different types of theory have conflicting implications regarding the epistemology of causality. However, there are well-known proposed counterexamples to mechanistic and difference-making theories of causality. There are cases involving absences, which seem to be cases of causality but without any appropriate sort of mechanism [Williamson, 2011]. There are also cases of over-determination, which seem to be cases of causality but without any appropriate sort of differencemaking relationship [Hall, 2004, pp. 232 241]. 4 / 21

How should one respond to these proposed counterexamples? There are two standard lines of response. The standard lines of response: 1 The first line of response is simply to dismiss the relevant counterexamples [Coady, 2004, Thomson, 2003]. 2 The second line of response is to advocate pluralism, e.g., by maintaining that there is both a mechanistic type and a difference-making type of causality; see, e.g., [Hall, 2004]. 5 / 21

The first line of response looks implausible. The overdetermination cases look like paradigmatic cases of causality without an appropriate difference-making relationship [Paul and Hall, 2013, pp. 70 172]; mutatis mutandis for cases involving absences [Schaffer, 2004]. It is generally agreed that there is currently neither a difference-making nor a mechanistic theory of causality that can accommodate all the proposed counterexamples in this manner [Paul and Hall, 2013, p. 1]. Reasons to doubt the second line of response are presented in [Williamson, 2006]. For instance, it is argued there that nonpluralist theories of causality should be preferred on the grounds of simplicity. 6 / 21

One major problem is that both these lines of response have difficulty accounting for the practice of scientists when establishing causal claims [Williamson, 2006, pp. 73 74]. In particular, when establishing a causal claim, health scientists typically require evidence both that there exists an appropriate difference-making relationship and that there exists an appropriate mechanism [Russo and Williamson, 2007]. 7 / 21

Firstly, establishing only that there exists an appropriate sort of difference-making relationship is typically not sufficient for a health scientist to consider the corresponding causal claim established [Gillies, 2011]. Secondly, establishing only that there exists an appropriate mechanism is also typically not sufficient for a health scientist to consider the corresponding causal claim established [Clarke et al., 2014, p. 345]. 8 / 21

Difference-making theories of causality are susceptible to overdetermination counterexamples. Mechanistic theories are susceptible to counterexamples, viz., the cases involving absences. In addition, difference-making and mechanistic theories of causality struggle to account for the correct epistemology of causality. Pluralist theories similarly struggle to explain the epistemology of causality. How should the theorist respond to this state of affairs? 9 / 21

One response is to plump for an epistemic theory of causality [Williamson, 2005, Williamson, 2006, Williamson, 2009, Williamson, 2011, Williamson, 2013]. According to this theory, causality is epistemic in the sense that our causal claims are purely representational: they enable us to reason and interact with the world in certain ways; they are not claims about some causal relation that exists independently of us and our epistemic practices. 10 / 21

D C L P O G Figure : Trihoral relationships involving Canterbury (C), London (L), Gatwick (G), Dunkirk (D), Paris (P) and Orléans (O). By way of analogy, consider the following relation, which we shall call the trihoral relation: two places stand in this relation if it is reasonable to expect to be able to travel between them within three hours. One can chart this relation, as in Fig. 1. 11 / 21

If the graph is correct, it is in virtue of a complex array of facts about the presence and absence of train, air, ferry and road connections, as well as normal conditions relating to travel. In that sense, the trihoral relation is purely representational. The graph is not correct due to the existence of some single, unified, worldy (non-epistemological) connection between places that we can call trihorality. Similarly with the causal relation. Our causal claims are extremely useful particularly for prediction, explanation and control. It is this utility which accounts for our having the concept of cause: not the existence of some simple kind of worldly connection to which our causal claims refer that we can call causality. 12 / 21

Consider another analogy, to Bayesian probability. Bayesian probabilities are epistemic rational degrees of belief, not directly physical entities and they underwrite certain predictions and bets. Moreover, at least on the objective Bayesian view, there is typically a fact of the matter as to what the correct Bayesian probabilities are, given the extent and limitations of the evidence available. 13 / 21

In one version of objective Bayesianism, three norms constrain the strengths of one s beliefs [Williamson, 2010]. Objective Bayesian norms: Probability: One s degrees of belief should be representable by a probability function P E. Calibration: One s degrees of belief should fit evidence: P E E, the subset of probability functions that fit evidence. Equivocation: One s degrees of belief should otherwise equivocate as far as possible between the elementary outcomes. 14 / 21

Objective Bayesian probability is instructive in that it suggests a particular connection between evidence and epistemic probabilities. An epistemic theory of causality can posit similar norms that constrain one s causal claims. Epistemic causality norms: Acyclicity: One s causal claims should be representable by an acyclic graph C. Calibration One s causal claims should fit evidence: C E, the subset of acyclic graphs that fit evidence. Equivocation C should otherwise be as non-committal as possible about what causes what. 15 / 21

Acyclicity: Let C be an acyclic graph whose nodes correspond to variables, which contains an arrow from variable A to variable B if it is claimed that A is a cause of B, a gap between A and B if it is claimed that neither causes the other, and an undirected edge between A and B if neither of the above two claims is made involving A and B. Calibration: If evidence establishes that A is a cause of B, represented by A B, then there should be some chain of arrows from A to B in C; if evidence establishes that A is not a cause of B, A B, then there should be no chain of edges and arrows from A to B. Equivocation: A causal graph C is maximally non-committal, from all those in E, if there is no other causal graph D in E which makes more causal claims than C. 16 / 21

It looks like this recipe for arriving at one s causal claims requires that an ideally rational subject has perfect access to her evidence. The problem is that recent work in epistemology claims to show that evidence is not as accessible as following the above recipes seems to require [Williamson, 2000, pp. 93 113]. How should the proponent of the epistemic theory of causality respond to this objection? Responses: 1 Deny that evidence is not perfectly accessible in the relevant sense. 2 Propose an alternative epistemic theory of causality that dispenses with the requirement that evidence is perfectly accessible. 17 / 21

Is there a viable alternative epistemic theory of causality? Once again, the analogy with Bayesian probability is instructive. Objective Bayesian probabilities require that evidence is such that an ideally rational subject has perfect access to her evidence. Timothy Williamson proposes an alternative evidential theory of probability [Williamson, 2000, pp. 209 237]. On this theory, there exists an objective degree to which a belief is entailed by a given body of evidence, and it is evidential probabilities that measure this partial entailment relation between evidence and beliefs. 18 / 21

In a similar manner, the proponent of the epistemic theory might propose an analogous evidential theory of causality. This theory hypothesizes that there exists a unique causal graph given one s body of evidence, where this causal graph licenses certain inferences concerning explanation, prediction, and control. This theory of causality remains epistemic, since the causal graph depends upon one s body of evidence rather than some non-epistemological feature of the world. Instead, one s causal claims are rational insofar as they match this unique causal graph. Arguably, then, a version of the epistemic theory of causality survives the objection based upon recent work in epistemology, viz., the evidential theory of causality. 19 / 21

Overview It looks like the epistemic theory of causality is the way to go, given the counterexamples to alternative theories and their struggle to explain the epistemology of causality. While some might object that such an epistemic theory of causality conflicts with recent work in epistemology, we have suggested some lines of response to this objection. To conclude: It still looks like the epistemic theory of causality is the way to go. 20 / 21

Bibliography I Overview Clarke, B., Gillies, D., Illari, P., Russo, F., and Williamson, J. (2014). Mechanisms and the evidence hierarchy. Topoi, 33:339 360. Coady, D. (2004). Preempting preemption. In Collins, J., Hall, N., and Paul, L., editors, Causation and Counterfactuals, pages 325 339. MIT Press. 21 / 21

Bibliography II Overview Gillies, D. (2011). The Russo-Williamson thesis and the question of whether smoking causes heart disease. In Illari, P., Russo, F., and Williamson, J., editors, Causality in the Sciences, pages 110 125. Oxford University Press. Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In Collins, J., Hall, N., and Paul, L., editors, Causation and Counterfactuals, pages 225 276. MIT Press. Paul, L. and Hall, N. (2013). Causation: A User s Guide. Oxford University Press. 22 / 21

Bibliography III Overview Russo, F. and Williamson, J. (2007). Interpreting causality in the health sciences. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21:157 170. Schaffer, J. (2004). Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: the case for negative causation. In Hitchcock, C., editor, Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science, pages 197 216. Blackwell. Thomson, J. (2003). Causation: Omissions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66:83 103. 23 / 21

Bibliography IV Overview Williamson, J. (2005). Bayesian Nets and Causality. Oxford University Press. Williamson, J. (2006). Causal pluralism versus epistemic causality. Philosophica, 77:69 96. Williamson, J. (2009). Probabilistic theories of causality. In Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., and Menzies, P., editors, The Oxford Handbook of Causation, pages 185 212. Oxford University Press. 24 / 21

Bibliography V Overview Williamson, J. (2010). In Defence of Objective Bayesianism. Oxford University Press. Williamson, J. (2011). Mechanistic theories of causality part II. Philosophy Compass, 6:433 444. Williamson, J. (2013). How can causal explanations explain? Erkenntnis, 78:257 275. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its Limits. Oxford University Press. 25 / 21