ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang. Changchun University, Changchun, China

Similar documents
A presupposition is a precondition of a sentence such that the sentences cannot be

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

Presuppositions (Ch. 6, pp )

A Linguistic Interlude

Coordination Problems

Pragmatic Presupposition

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

10. Presuppositions Introduction The Phenomenon Tests for presuppositions

Mandy Simons Carnegie Mellon University June 2010

Towards a Solution to the Proviso Problem

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

PRESUPPOSITION IN THE BUSINESS LETTERS AT GRAND CANDI HOTEL JOURNAL ARTICLE

ANAPHORIC REFERENCE IN JUSTIN BIEBER S ALBUM BELIEVE ACOUSTIC

Affirmation-Negation: New Perspective

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Russell: On Denoting

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Class #9 - The Attributive/Referential Distinction

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

An Analysis of Presupposition Used in Oedipus Rex

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Presupposition: An (un)common attitude?

Presupposition: Introduction

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

On Conceivability and Existence in Linguistic Interpretation

The projection problem of presuppositions

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Strawson On Referring. By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper

Satisfied or Exhaustified An Ambiguity Account of the Proviso Problem

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Lecture 9: Presuppositions

Question and Inference

91. Presupposition. Denial, projection, cancellation, satisfaction, accommodation: the five stages of presupposition theory.

Knowledge is Not the Most General Factive Stative Attitude

Development of Soul Through Contemplation and Action Seen from the Viewpoint of lslamic Philosophers and Gnostics

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Lecture 1. Yasutada Sudo 12 January 2018

Semantic Values? Alex Byrne, MIT

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Entailment as Plural Modal Anaphora

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Pragmatic Considerations in the Interpretation of Denying the Antecedent

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Factivity and Presuppositions David Schueler University of Minnesota, Twin Cities LSA Annual Meeting 2013

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND CONDITIONAL ASSERTIONS

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

THE ANALYSIS OF PRESUPPOSITION IN THE SHORT STORIES OF SILVESTER GORIDUS SUKUR

Parmenides PHIL301 Prof. Oakes Winthrop University updated: 9/5/12 3:03 PM

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Linguistic Society of America

Stout s teleological theory of action

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Lying and Asserting. Andreas Stokke CSMN, University of Oslo. March forthcoming in the Journal of Philosophy

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

The challenge for evangelical hermeneutics is the struggle to make the old, old

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Does Personhood Begin at Conception?

Anaphoric Deflationism: Truth and Reference

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory


MEANING AND TRUTH IN THEOLOGY

Predict the Behavior. Leonardo Caffo. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action. University of Milan - Department of Philosophy

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Halliday and Hasan in Cohesion in English (1976) see text connectedness realized by:

The main plank of Professor Simons thoroughly pragmatic account of presupposition

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Slides: Notes:

Lecture (1) Introduction

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Transcription:

US-China Foreign Language, February 2015, Vol. 13, No. 2, 109-114 doi:10.17265/1539-8080/2015.02.004 D DAVID PUBLISHING Presupposition: How Discourse Coherence Is Conducted ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang Changchun University, Changchun, China Presupposition is a complex linguistic phenomenon that involves in human linguistic intuition. The study of presupposition has aroused much interest of linguists, scholars, and experts since it was introduced into linguistics. The aim of this paper is to explicate what value presupposition bears on discourse. The heat-debated topic of the nature of presupposition is analyzed first. Then by employing the better understanding of the nature presupposition, the paper explores the roles of semantic and pragmatic presupposition play in discourse coherence. That is, semantic presupposition, by linguistic devices, contributes to discourse coherence by avoiding redundancy and ensuring economy. Pragmatic presupposition, bearing with encyclopedic, social or cultural knowledge, bridges the understanding gap, also guarantees discourse coherence. Keywords: presupposition, semantic presupposition, pragmatic presupposition, coherence, cohesion Introduction The concept of presupposition could be traced back to philosophy and was not introduced into linguistics until the 1960s. Gottlob Frege first took notice of presupposition in terms of reference. As he states, if any thing is asserted there is always an obvious presupposition that the simple or compound proper names used have reference (Frege, 1970, p. 69). As is illustrated in John is depressed presupposes there exists a name John which designates something. The referential dealt of presupposition seems too simple and leaves much to accounting for, thus leads to the wide interest of the study of presupposition. Among these studies, one of the hot debates is about whether presupposition is semantic or pragmatic in nature. Presupposition: A Semantic or a Pragmatic One Semantic Presupposition The semantic perspective of study of presupposition is mainly from the truth value, entailment and most prominent, from the linguistic items. Here due to the need of present study, the paper mainly accounts for semantic presupposition from the linguistic features. Proponents of semantic presupposition exemplify presupposition arises with certain content of the lexicon and some special grammatical structures (see Example (1)). This paper is the phased research results of the planning projects of 2014 Jilin Science Education Twelfth Five-Year Plan Study on Multiple Interactive School-based Education Model of College English Teachers (Project Number: GH14265); 2014 Jilin Social Science Fund Project Study on College English Teachers Knowledge Structure (Project Number: 2014B204). ZHANG Yan-qiu, lecturer, master, Public Foreign Languages Teaching and Research Department, Changchun University. CHEN Qiang, associate professor, Ph.D. candidate, Public Foreign Languages Teaching and Research Department, Changchun University.

110 PRESUPPOSITION: HOW DISCOURSE COHERENCE IS CONDUCTED Example (1) I know he is a teacher. This sentence carries with the presupposition that he is a teacher. The embedded that-clause is taken for granted to express a true proposition and the matrix clause makes some assertion about that proposition. However, if the predicate know is replaced by suppose as in I suppose he is a teacher, then the initial presupposition he is a teacher is cancelled. Here, know is called a factive predicate and the that-clause of a factive predicate P is presupposed to be true when P is the main lexical predicate of a main clause (Seuren, 1994, pp. 3311-3320). Like some lexical items, certain grammatical structures can also give rise to presuppositions (see Example (2)). Example (2) When Jim s mother and father divorced, he was still a little boy. Obviously, the thought Jim s mother and father once divorced is the presupposition of the whole compound sentence. Likewise, other temporal sentences can also give birth to presuppositions. Example (3) (a) After the shower, the rainbow appeared in the sky. (b) Before the earthquake, there were 300 people in the village. In Example (3), the after-clause in first sentence arouses the presupposition that there once was a shower. Similarly, an earthquake once happened is also presupposed by the before-clause in the second sentence. In addition to temporal clause, other grammatical structures like cleft and pseudo-cleft sentences, non-restrictive relative clauses and counterfactual conditionals can also trigger presuppositions. The propositions expressed by these grammatical structures presumed to be true and be the presuppositions of the whole sentences. The semantic perspective of presupposition, as is shown above, if analyzed further, treats presupposition as being stable, linguistic-related and context-independent. This is questioned by the defeasibility problem of presupposition, which means, presuppositions tend to evaporate in certain context. Example (4) (a) At least John won t have to regret that he did a Ph.D.. (b) John did a Ph.D.. (Levinson, 1983, p. 187) In Example (4), a semantically presupposes (b) obviously. However, if the participants mutually know that John failed to get Ph.D., the presupposition (b) is undoubtedly cancelled. Example (5) (a) Sue cried before she finished her thesis. (b) Sue died before she finished her thesis. (c) Sue finished her thesis. (Levinson, 1983, p. 187) Likewise, in Example (5), (c) is a presupposition of (a), but not a presupposition of (b). Since the common knowledge shows that a dead person can do nothing, not to mention finishing thesis. From the above examples, it can be seen that presuppositions can be cancelled either by immediate context or by encyclopedia knowledge. It highly depends on the context. This context-dependent feature seems to prove that presupposition is a pragmatic matter. Pragmatic Presupposition Proponents of pragmatic approach intend to prove presupposition is pragmatic rather than semantic. They account for presupposition in terms of speaker s beliefs, listener s knowledge, felicity condition, and speech acts,

PRESUPPOSITION: HOW DISCOURSE COHERENCE IS CONDUCTED 111 etc.. One of the most promising efforts was proposed by Gazdar. In Gazdar, sentences possess pre-suppositions (which are also called potential presuppositions ) all the times, but only those which are satisfiable in the context of utterance actually emerges as the presuppositions of the utterances (Gazdar, 1979, p. 90). Deep down from his accounts, there seems to be a mechanism that can either cancel pre-supposition to be nothing or make pre-supposition to be actual. Consider the following example: Example (6) Linda has three millions and Linda s three millions are invested in the real estate. In Example (6), Linda has three millions is potentially presupposed since the second conjunct Linda s three millions are invested in the real estate does, while the initial part implicates that it is not known by others that Linda has three millions, otherwise it is not necessary to say so. Therefore, the potential presupposition is suspended. Here is another example: Example (7) Linda hasn t regretted marrying because in fact he has not married. The first clause shows that Linda got married; while the second obviously entails that Linda did not marry (see Example (7)). Obviously, what is supposed in the first clause is cancelled by the entailment of the second. All enlighten that pre-suppositions can be cancelled when it is contradictory with implicature and it is context-dependent. From the above analysis, that presupposition, in nature, seems pragmatic rather than semantic is more explainable. However, as a way to approach the formation of discourse coherence, both semantic presupposition and pragmatic presupposition play a distinctive role in discourse coherence. What roles do semantic presupposition and pragmatic presupposition play in discourse coherence? Before this question is touched, it should be clarified first what is discourse coherence through the distinction of the concepts of coherence and cohesion. Coherence and Cohesion: Their Differences and Connection Discourse can refer to sentences, paragraphs, stanzas, or chapters, etc.. A coherent discourse consists of sentences not arbitrary but connected. This connectivity is typically reflected by linguistic devices which are called cohesion. A relation of cohesion is set up when the meaning of one element cannot be effectively decoded except by resorting to another somewhere in the same discourse. As Halliday and Hasan (1976) states: the potential for cohesion lies in the systematic resources of references, ellipsis and so on that are built into the language itself (p. 5). For example: Example (8) A: Look at the bird with beautiful feathers. B: Where is it? Here, the bird and it illustrate the anaphoric relation which makes the dialogue achieve cohesion and it is coherent too. The following sentence serves as another example: Example (9) I am upset and so I can t write a paper. The two conjuncts are connected by the cohesive marker so that a cause-consequence relationship is explicitly illustrated. From Examples (8)-(9), cohesion is something about linguistic devices that a coherent discourse is always employed to form connectivity. However, is cohesion sufficient enough to guarantee discourse coherence? That is to say, does a piece of discourse that lacks cohesion necessarily lack coherence? The answer is definitely no.

112 PRESUPPOSITION: HOW DISCOURSE COHERENCE IS CONDUCTED The coherence of discourse actually relies on the underlying meaning connectivity, not the explicit presence of cohesive markers. And the realization of discourse coherence does not necessarily resort to the cohesion although cohesion is usually the feature and effective device employed by a coherent discourse. The dialogue in Example (10) does not employ any cohesive markers, but it is coherent and explicitly understandable. Example (10) A: Would you like to dance with me? B: I am enjoying the wonderful sightseeing. Apparently, there are no cohesive markers but the dialogue seems coherent. This again proves that discourse coherence is not guaranteed simply by linguistic devices, but the underlying meaning relations of sentences that consisting of discourse. And this arouses another question: How do the underlying meaning relations of sentences connected? Presupposition, as is mentioned before, contributes a lot to the underlying connectivity of discourse. Presupposition: A Guarantee of Discourse Coherence Presupposition, perceived by the addresser that it is known by the addressee, is treated as background. In Halliday s (1976) view, it is also called given information. In contrast to the given information, the new information is the information that the addressor believes is not known to the addressee. In a discourse, not all the information is of equal importance. The topic-related information should be highlighted and conveyed through assertion, while less important information is backgrounded through presuppositions. Hence, the economy and the effectiveness of communication are achieved. The excerpt cited from the Frog Story (see Example (11)) can serve as an example: Example (11) How odd, I thought, last November when I first noticed him sitting atop my sound board over my computer. I figured that he (and I say he, though I really don t have a clue if she is a he or vice versa) would be more comfortable in the greenhouse. So I put him in the greenhouse. Back he came. And stayed. After a while I got quite used to the fact that as I would check my morning email and on-line news, he would be there with me surveying the world. (WU, 2002, p. 19) The main topic or the goal of the above discourse is the author found a frog sitting on his computer and he put the frog into the greenhouse, thinking that the greenhouse is better and more comfortable for it. Surprisingly, the frog went back to the computer time to time which aroused the curiosity of the author. The topic-related information in this discourse is I figured that he would be more comfortable in the greenhouse. However, I first noticed him sitting atop my sound board over my computer is exact time that I figured, which is less important and is dealt with by a time clause. Furthermore, my sound board, my computer, the greenhouse, my morning email, and on-line news are less relevant for the topic and are presupposed as background information. Suppose if all the presupposed information is asserted as of equal importance, the discourse will become redundant and the coherence of discourse is destroyed. Hence, through presupposition, the topic-related information is made prominent while the less important information is backgrounded. In this sense, presupposition plays a positive role in enhancing discourse coherence. If it is believed that the linguistic devices generated from the semantic perspective of presupposition guarantee the economy and coherence of discourse, pragmatic presupposition, in this regard, plays a determinant role in one s perception of discourse coherence. The presupposition involved in encyclopedic knowledge is taken first into consideration. For example:

PRESUPPOSITION: HOW DISCOURSE COHERENCE IS CONDUCTED 113 Example (12) A: I feel very cold. B: Here are clothes. In Example (12), speaker A feels cold and speaker B mentions the clothes available. Without certain encyclopaedic knowledge, B s response seems irrelevant to A and the dialogue is incoherent. However, the presupposed encyclopaedic knowledge shows that clothes can protect human beings from coldness, and any normal person with mature cognitive ability knows it. Thus, in this dialogue the presupposition serves as the bridge to help achieve the coherence of the dialogue. Likewise, pragmatic presupposition involved in social knowledge can also achieve discourse coherence by bridging the understanding gap. Example (13) (a) Too many new words make it difficult to read. (b) You can just give up reading. (c) I have a dictionary. In Example (13), (b) is the direct answer to (a), while (c), superficially, is not the coherent continuity of (a). However, the social constructed knowledge that a dictionary can be used for looking up news words effectively bridges the gap between the two propositions. Thus, the response of (c) is relevant in that (c) implicates that the speaker in (a) can borrow his dictionary and overcome reading difficulties by resorting to the dictionary. With this presupposed message the discourse becomes unified and coherent. Not only presuppositions involved in encyclopedic and social constructed knowledge can help form discourse coherence, but cultural-specific presupposition can also help overcome the understanding obstacles and achieve discourse coherence. Consider the following example: Example (14) A: Do you like pork? B: I am a Muslim. In Example (14), A asks B whether he/she likes pork or not. Instead of answers like Yes or No, B just shows he/she is a Muslim. The discourse seems disconnected and lacks coherence without cultural background. However, if the presupposed cultural knowledge that Muslims do not eat pork is known by the addresser, the addressee answer becomes relevant and acceptable. As is seen above, the cultural presupposition that a Muslim does not eat pork bridges the gap and makes the whole discourse coherent. Conclusion Through the analysis it can be seen both the semantic perspective of presupposition and the pragmatic perspective of presupposition are crucial to discourse coherence. By guaranteeing effectiveness and economy through linguistic devices, the formal connectivity of discourse is achieved with semantic presupposition. And by bridging the information gap through context-dependent knowledge, the underlying connectivity of discourse is conducted with pragmatic presupposition. However, since both presupposition and discourse coherence are concerned with human linguistic intuition, further study of presupposition from the perspective of discourse coherence is necessary and has much more research value. References Frege, G. (1970). On sense and meaning. In P. T. Geach & M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 56-78). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

114 PRESUPPOSITION: HOW DISCOURSE COHERENCE IS CONDUCTED Gazdar, G. (1979). Pragmatics. New York: Academic Press. Halliday, M. A. K., & Hasan, R. (1976). Cohesion in English. London: Longman. Levinson, S. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Seuren, P. A. M. (1994). Factivity. In R. E. Asher & J. M. Y. Simpson (Eds.), Encyclopedia of language and linguistics (Vo1. 6, pp. 3311-3320). Oxford: Pergamon Press. Verschueren, J. (2000). Understanding pragmatics. Beijing: Foreign Language Teaching and Research Press. WU, Z. J. (2002). Experiencing English: Intergrated book 3. Beijing: Higher Education Press. Yule, G. (2000). Pragmatics. Shanghai: Shanghai Foreign Language Education Press.