Logic clearly dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few or the needs of the one (Spock and Captain Kirk).

Similar documents
Ethical non-naturalism

Emotivism. Meta-ethical approaches

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

The Subject Matter of Ethics G. E. Moore

Moore on External Relations

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

(naturalistic fallacy)

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

The hallmark of a good moral theory is that it agrees with and improves

It is not at all wise to draw a watertight

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

Theme 1: Ethical Thought, AS. divine command as an objective metaphysical foundation for morality.

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Pastor-teacher Don Hargrove Faith Bible Church September 8, 2011

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

ON THE NATURALISTIC FALLACY AND ST. THOMAS. The debate about the naturalistic fallacy, or about whether value judgments and ought

The CopernicanRevolution

DEONTOLOGY AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Royal Institute of Philosophy

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

The Ontological Argument

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

NOT SO PROMISING AFTER ALL: EVALUATOR-RELATIVE TELEOLOGY AND COMMON-SENSE MORALITY

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

1/9. Locke on Abstraction

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Look at this famous painting what s missing? What could YOU deduce about the value of human life from this picture? If there is no God then.

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Preparation for A Level Religious Studies Year 11 into Year 12 RS Summer Transition Work

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Situation Ethics. Key Features. Strengths & Weaknesses

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

Baronett, Logic (4th ed.) Chapter Guide

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Logic & Philosophy. SSB Syllabus

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

Logic: A Brief Introduction. Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

1/9. The First Analogy

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza

The Ontological Argument

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Peter Bornedal, General Lecture, 203. Copyright (C) by P. Bornedal

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

God has a mind- Romans 11:34 "who has known the mind of the Lord

Free will & divine foreknowledge

c Peter King, 1987; all rights reserved. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM: ORDINATIO 1 d. 2 q. 6

Transcription:

Logic clearly dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few or the needs of the one (Spock and Captain Kirk). Discuss Logic cannot show that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few without an assumption being made that is entirely illogical. To address this question, it must first be established whether the proposition at hand may be arrived at purely through logic, that is, entirely a priori. Once it has been shown that it may not be validly deduced, it becomes necessary to examine the assumptions that any such argument must rest upon, in order that one may reason from empirical observations to the conclusion that the needs of the many indeed outweigh the needs of the few. At this juncture it will become evident that the argument under discussion presupposes that different needs are comparable, that it commits the naturalistic fallacy, and that even when it is assumed that various needs may be balanced against each other and that there is indeed value in addressing a need, it will be shown that it by no means follows that the needs of the many actually outweigh the needs of the few. This process, therefore, indicates that logic in no way dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few. For there to be any debate whatsoever about the needs of the many taking precedence over the needs of the few, this statement must be a judgment of value. If outweigh is taken to mean a numerical dominance, then it is selfevident that the needs of the many, who are by definition numerically greater than the few, outweigh, or are greater in number than, the needs of the few. There would thus be no discussion to be had. Rather, for the purposes of this discussion, outweigh must have a different meaning. A. J. Ayer 1 recommends that when words used in propositions have various meanings or connotations, then a definition in use of the word under question must be provided, namely, how the word is actually used. Otherwise, confusions arise, such as the use of is to indicate existence and is to indicate the possession of an attribute. How is weight used in the English language, then? It has two primary senses either weight as in mass, or weight as in carrying value, such as moral weight. It is apparent that the first meaning is irrelevant to our discussion, for it would be nonsensical to suggest that certain needs have a greater mass than others. By process of elimination, then, we are left with weight and hence outweigh as indicative of some value. To say that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few, thus, is to say that the needs of the many have a greater value than the needs of the few. The assertion under question is one concerning logic it states that logic dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few. When considering the meaning of the word logic in this assertion, a dichotomy of meanings arises: that logic dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few may either mean that it is possible to reach such a conclusion purely through reason, or that, having noted something about the empirical world, the application of logic to such observations provides our conclusion. Essentially, these two approaches represent two different paths to knowledge 1 Ayer, Alfred Jules. Language, Truth, and Logic. London: Penguin Books Ltd, 1971.

the a priori and the a posteriori. To begin with the former, it is evident that no question of value, such as the assertion at hand, may be reached simply only through logic. For pure logic consists of the process of deduction, that is, revealing hidden propositions within other propositions. Deduction simply reveals predicates that are entailed within a subject but are not necessarily explicit Kant gives the example of a triangle having interior angles of a sum of 180 degrees. This is true by the very definition of a triangle, but is a truth not obvious in considering one: it is the process of deduction that allows us to know that the interior angles do indeed have a sum of 180 degrees. It does not matter whether this is termed the synthetic a priori, as Kant does, or strictly analytic, as in the view of Ayer: the point is that only propositions that are true by definition may be deduced purely through logic, without any recourse to the empirical world. Can a statement of value, then, ever be true by definition? The method to examine if any statement is true by definition is to see if its contrary is selfcontradictory. For example, that two and two make four is true by definition, for it would be self-contradictory to claim that two and two do not make four. This is the method that Ayer adopts in rejecting subjectivism to say that an action is right if it is generally approved of is not true by definition, for it would not be self-contradictory to say that some actions which are generally approved of are not right 2. To apply this to the assertion at hand, it is not true by definition that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few, for it would not be selfcontradictory to claim that the needs of the few outweigh the needs of the many It can hence be seen that it may not be known, only through logic, that the needs of the many do outweigh the needs of the few. It has thus been established that it may not be deduced that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few, for no matter of value may be deduced a priori. Therefore, the reasoning that leads to the assertion under debate must begin in the empirical world. However, it is clear that this assertion is reliant upon numerous assumptions, which may not be taken for granted. To begin with, as Bernard Williams suggests in his critique of utilitarianism in Morality 3, to be able to say that one set of needs outweighs another requires the ability to compare different needs in some sort of common currency, for otherwise it would be like attempting to compare apples to pears. How does one compare the need for food and drink and the need for emotional security, for example? At this point, it becomes necessary to define need in some way. It can be suggested, along the lines of Bentham, that need represents that which the fulfillment of provides a balance of pleasure over pain 4. This would therefore allow a common currency between different needs, namely the amount of pleasure provided by the fulfillment of a need. Yet it may be argued that there are different types of pleasure, from the sensations derived from food to sexual pleasure. Yet these may also be reduced further, for example simply into amounts of dopamine released by the brain when experiencing certain pleasures. It is of no concern to the debate which particular definition of need is used, for all definitions may ultimately be reduced to activity in the brain, which could be ascertained by a MRI scan. This allows a comparison to be made between the needs of different 2 Ayer, Alfred Jules. Language, Truth, and Logic, Chapter 6. 3 Williams, Bernard. Morality 4 vide Bentham, Jeremy. Principles of Morals and Legislation

groups. Furthermore, this is not limited to the value of needs any type of value, be it moral, aesthetic or otherwise, can be reduced in such a way to a currency of exchange, allowing the value of one thing to be balanced against another. If one is going to assert that different needs must be weighed against each other, then it seems absurd not to take into account the size of the needs. In effect, not to do so creates a tyranny of the majority. This is best illustrated through the use of an example. Let us imagine that 51% of people voted for a particular decision to be made, which would fulfill a minor need of theirs. The 49%, however, voted for another decision, from which they stood to fulfill a very large need. It seems bizarre to favour the many very slightly, at the expense of slightly fewer people gaining very much. This does not just apply at a sociopolitical level, but also at a personal level. To take a more extreme example, let us suppose that a group of ten people wish to murder one person, and the ten, sadistically, would enjoy the murder a small amount. The proposition under question would have it that the value of the need that ten would fulfill from the murder would outweigh the value of the need of the victim that would be fulfilled by not being murdered. The former would outweigh the latter simply because the ten are greater in number than one, although the total need fulfilled, if the size of needs can be quantified, would be larger if the victim is not murdered, for the need to live is much greater than the apparent need to murder even when the latter is multiplied by ten. For the assertion under discussion to be tenable, hence, it must be modified to state that the larger total need outweighs the smaller total need. It must be noted here that need is interchangeable with any word that denotes a concept of value, such as goodness, pleasure and beauty, for the proposition the pleasure of the many outweighs the pleasure of the few would be of identical logical structure to our initial proposition. In considering the sum total of need, we therefore arrive at a sort of utilitarianism, except that rather than being limited to hedonism, it is simply a consequentialist theory applicable to any value: that which produces the most of some value must take precedence. The crude assertion that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few must hence be qualified for it to be of any sense what is important is not the number of individual pieces of value, but the sum total of value on either side of a decision being made. The qualifications and modifications that are necessary for the proposition at hand to be even potentially tenable have hence been established: firstly, it is possible to reduce questions of value to the changes in brain chemistry that result when we experience the value; and secondly, that to avoid a tyranny of the majority, it is better to give weight to the greater in sum value rather than the greater in the simple number of stakeholders. Consequently, our discussion has arrived at a proposition along the lines of the greater total need outweighs the lesser sum need. However, this proposition is ultimately flawed, in that a logical step is missing, and that this step may only be filled by committing the naturalistic fallacy. It was discussed above that outweigh indicates a judgment of value, showing that one side of a dichotomy is greater in value than another: the greater aggregate need s fulfillment has more value than the lesser aggregate need s fulfillment. But to say that the fulfillment of some needs has more value than the fulfillment of others is to postulate that the

fulfillment of needs has value in itself, for how else could one have more value than the other? Hence our proposition can be restated in a syllogism thus: Premise 1: There exist needs. Premise 2: The fulfillment of needs has value. Conclusion: We should therefore act in such a way that fulfills the most possible needs. While this argument is logically valid, it is by no means sound, for the second premise seems entirely arbitrary why should the fulfillment of needs have value? It would be rash to say that the fulfillment of needs has intrinsic value, for where would it derive its intrinsic value from? Appeals to God or other deontological theories of ethics open up a veritable Pandora s Box of problems, which are far too great both in number and scope to be discussed suitably here. Can the fulfillment of need have value in a teleological sense, in that it produces desirable consequences? Potential effects of needs being fulfilled may be happiness, or perhaps satisfaction, or comfort we return to our original idea that if the needs outweigh the needs of the few, this must be known a posteriori, perhaps observing that this produces the most happiness. But why are effects such as happiness themselves desirable? To take a consequentialist view of the fulfillment of need merely delays the problem of finding value to the effects of an action, rather than the action itself. It can thus be seen that the proposition the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few is either based on groundless premises, or must accept another premise, along the lines of pleasure has value. Yet this is evidently the naturalistic fallacy, as outlined by G. E. Moore in Principia Ethica : just because something is natural, such as pleasure, does not mean it is good, or has any other value. It has conclusively been demonstrated, in following, that even if the initial proposition is modified to read greater total needs as opposed to needs of the many, the proposition contains a premise that is groundless, and that any attempt to show how this premise may be valid involves a naturalistic fallacy. Do the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few, then? Taking the above into consideration, it is apparent that such an affirmation cannot be made with authority. There are two approaches to gaining knowledge of such a kind through logic, either the a priori or the a posteriori. The former may not provide assertions that are not already known, for it deals with truths that are true by definition. Applying Ayer s principle of self-contradiction, it can be seen that the statement at hand is patently not true by definition. Our statement may thus only be the conclusion of a posteriori observations formulated logically, such as the syllogism outlined above. For our statement s truth to be possible, it is necessary to find a currency of exchange between various needs, or even various values: a reduction of emotions to brain chemistry provides such a currency. Furthermore, our statement is absurd if limited to numerical dominance, that is, in only comparing the number of needs on either side of a choice. Yet even if such qualifications are allowed, our statement assumes that the fulfillment of need has value. This forces the statement into a fork either it is based upon a groundless premise, the fulfillment of need has value, or, it must commit the naturalistic fallacy in asserting that the fulfillment of need has value because it creates happiness, or some other desirable emotion. By this process of reasoning, it may

be concluded that logic in no way dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few. Word Count (excluding headings and bibliography): 2479 Bibliography Ayer, Alfred Jules. Language, Truth, and Logic. London: Penguin Books Ltd, 1971. Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. London: Fontana Press, 1962. Mill, John Stuart. Bentham, taken from Dissertations and Discussions, Vol. 1. London: Fontana Press, 1962. Bentham, Jeremy. Principles of Morals and Legislation. London: Fontana Press, 1962. Williams, Bernard. Morality. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1962. Moore, George Edward. Principia Ethica. http://fair-use.org/g-emoore/principia-ethica Panahi, Omid. Could there be a solution to the trolley problem?, Philosophy Now, 116 (2016). Baker, Katy. The Consequences of Consequentialism, Philosophy Now,115 (2016).