NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

Similar documents
Norm-Expressivism and the Frege-Geach Problem

finagling frege Mark Schroeder University of Southern California September 25, 2007

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

AGAINST THE BEING FOR ACCOUNT OF NORMATIVE CERTITUDE

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

SCHROEDER ON THE WRONG KIND OF

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

how expressivists can and should solve their problem with negation Noûs 42(4): Selected for inclusion in the 2008 Philosopher s Annual

Cognitivism about imperatives

Ethical non-naturalism

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD?

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Philosophy in Review XXXI (2011), no. 5

STILL NO REDUNDANT PROPERTIES: REPLY TO WIELENBERG

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Naturalist Cognitivism: The Open Question Argument; Subjectivism

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Huemer s Clarkeanism

ARE ALL NORMATIVE JUDGMENTS DESIRE-LIKE? Alex Gregory


Reply to Robert Koons

tempered expressivism for Oxford Studies in Metaethics, volume 8

Coordination Problems

Emotivism and its critics

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

Is it right to worry about the Frege-Geach problem?

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Contents. Detailed Chapter Contents Preface to the First Edition (2003) Preface to the Second Edition (2013) xiii

the negative reason existential fallacy

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

1 expressivism, what. Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Non-Cognitivism, Higher-Order Attitudes, and Stevenson s Do so as well!

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Compositional Semantics for Expressivists

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Nondescriptivist Cognitivism: Framework for a New Metaethic

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

A problem for expressivism

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

Action in Special Contexts

Miller, Alexander, An Introduction to Contemporary Metaethics, Oxford: Polity Press, 2003, pp.

what makes reasons sufficient?

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1 Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 04/15/10

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

ON LEAVING ROOM FOR DOUBT: USING FREGE-GEACH TO ILLUMINATE EXPRESSIVISM S PROBLEM WITH OBJECTIVITY

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

THE CAMBRIDGE SOLUTION TO THE TIME OF A KILLING LAWRENCE B. LOMBARD

HERMENEUTIC MORAL FICTIONALISM AS AN ANTI-REALIST STRATEGY (Please cite the final version in Philosophical Books 49, January 2008)

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Carnap s Non-Cognitivism as an Alternative to Both Value- Absolutism and Value-Relativism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

Expressing Credences. Daniel Rothschild All Souls College, Oxford OX1 4AL

A Rational Solution to the Problem of Moral Error Theory? Benjamin Scott Harrison

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Actualism, Possibilism, and Beyond 1

METAETHICAL MORAL RELATIVISM AND THE ANALOGY WITH PHYSICS

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Paradox of Deniability

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

INESCAPABILITY AND NORMATIVITY

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Transcription:

DISCUSSION NOTE NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: BY JOSEPH LONG JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE OCTOBER 2016 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOSEPH LONG 2016

Non-Cognitivism and the Problem of Moral-Based Epistemic Reasons: A Sympathetic Reply to Cian Dorr A ccording to Cian Dorr (2002), non-cognitivism has the implausible implication that arguments like the following are cases of wishful thinking: P1 If lying is wrong, then the souls of liars will be punished in the afterlife. P2 Lying is wrong. C The souls of liars will be punished in the afterlife. (Call this the Liar Argument. ) If non-cognitivism implies that the Liar Argument and similar arguments are cases of wishful thinking, then, Dorr further claims, non-cognitivism remains implausible even if one solves the socalled Frege-Geach problem. 1 Dorr s claims have faced a number of objections, but I believe that Dorr is onto something. 2 So, after summarizing Dorr s argument and briefly describing three flaws in what Dorr claims, I shall present a distinct objection to non-cognitivism and use the preceding to show what Dorr s argument gets right and what it gets wrong. Turning to Dorr s argument, Dorr s guiding question is this: Given that P1 and P2 imply C, can acceptance of P1 and P2 ever give someone reason to come to accept C? (2002: 97, emphasis in original). Intuitively, the answer is yes ; accepting P1 and P2 can give someone reason to accept C. Dorr argues that non-cognitivism implies that the answer is no, however, which is a reason to reject non-cognitivism. To show that non-cognitivism implies that accepting P1 and P2 never gives one reason to accept C, Dorr begins with a story about Edgar, who initially accepts P1 on the basis of others presumed authority on such matters. Edgar has insufficient evidence for either 1 The Frege-Geach problem is to account for the meanings and logical properties of evaluative claims in a way that is consistent with non-cognitivist semantics. If non-cognitivists cannot solve the Frege-Geach problem, then it is not clear how they can account for the validity of arguments, like the Liar Argument, that involve embedded atomic moral claims; however, if non-cognitivists can solve the problem, then presumably they can account for the validity of such arguments. For an excellent discussion of the Frege-Geach problem, see Schroeder (2008). 2 For objections to Dorr s claim that non-cognitivism renders the Liar Argument a case of wishful thinking, see Enoch (2003) and Lenman (2003). For responses to both Enoch and Lenman, see Schroeder (2011). See Budolfson (2011) and Mabrito (2013) for objections to Dorr s claim that solving the Frege-Geach problem will not suffice to solve the wishful thinking problem. Whether or not Budolfson s and Mabrito s objections to Dorr s claim are correct, this essay makes it clear that solving the Frege-Geach problem will not suffice to solve the distinct problem that I raise. 1

P2 or C, however, so he accepts neither P2 nor C. But, after reflecting for a time on the moral nature of lying, Edgar comes to accept P2. Finally, Edgar comes to accept C on the basis of inferring it from P1 and P2. We can now summarize Dorr s argument like this: (1) Initially, it was irrational for Edgar to accept C before he accepted P2. (2) If non-cognitivism is true, then Edgar s coming to accept P2 was only a change in non-cognitive attitude. (3) If it was irrational for Edgar to accept C before he accepted P2, and Edgar s coming to accept P2 was only a change in non-cognitive attitude, then it was irrational for Edgar to accept C after he accepted P2. (4) So, non-cognitivism implies that it was irrational for Edgar to accept C after he accepted P2 [from (1), (2) and (3)]. (5) But it was not irrational for Edgar to accept C after he accepted P2. (6) Non-cognitivism is false [from (4) and (5)]. The argument is valid; so, let us consider each of its premises. As for (1), it is just part of the story: in the beginning, Edgar has insufficient evidence for either P2 or C. Turning to (2), Dorr states: According to the non-cognitivist, all that happened when [Edgar] came to accept P2 was a change in his non-cognitive attitudes. He acquired no new evidence or other beliefs relevant to the fate of liars in the afterlife. Nor did he intuit the truth of C a priori, or take himself to have done so (2002: 99). So, since no additional evidence for C accompanied Edgar s coming to accept P2, and non-cognitivism implies that P2 expresses a non-cognitive attitude, non-cognitivism implies that Edgar s coming to accept P2 was just a change in non-cognitive attitude. 3 Thus, (2). As for (3), Dorr states: Only a change in one s cognitive states, or in one s evidence, can make the difference between a case in which it would be irrational to believe something and one in which it would be rational to do so. It is often rational to modify your views about one part of the world so that they cohere with your views about the rest of the world. It is irrational to modify your views about the world so that they cohere with your desires and feelings. That s wishful thinking! (2002: 99). In other words, to change one s view of the world based on only a change in one s non-cognitive attitudes amounts to wishful thinking, which is fallacious. Consequently, if Edgar s coming to accept P2 is just a matter of Edgar s changing his non-cognitive attitudes, then since it was irrational for Edgar to accept C prior to accepting P2, Edgar s accepting C after accepting P2 3 To be a bit more precise, Edgar s going from not accepting P2 to accepting P2 might have been accompanied by some other changes in cognitive attitude for example, Edgar came to believe that he now accepts that lying is wrong. But such changes are irrelevant to whether Edgar can rationally accept C given his going from not accepting P2 to accepting P2. So, we can set these changes aside.

is also irrational. Thus, (3). Together (1), (2) and (3) entail (4): if noncognitivism is true, then it was irrational for Edgar to accept C after he accepted P2. As (5) claims, however, it is intuitively not irrational for Edgar to accept C after accepting P2. Therefore, per (6), non-cognitivism is false. Having summarized Dorr s argument, I will briefly describe three flaws in what Dorr claims. Throughout, let us assume that the Frege-Geach problem has been solved and, therefore, that the Liar Argument is valid whether or not non-cognitivism is true. 4 The first flaw involves Dorr s guiding question, which is about whether accepting P1 and P2 is ever a reason to accept C. According to Dorr, non-cognitivism implies that the answer is no because non-cognitivism renders the Liar Argument a case of wishful thinking. But, even for paradigm cases of wishful thinking, accepting all of the offending argument s premises is often a reason to accept its conclusion, since paradigm cases of wishful thinking are often valid. Take, for example, the following argument: (1) If I hope that my proposal will be accepted, then my proposal will be accepted. (2) I hope that my proposal will be accepted. (3) My proposal will be accepted. (Call this the Hope Argument. ) The Hope Argument is a paradigm case of wishful thinking since it offers my hoping that my proposal will be accepted as a reason to believe that my proposal will be accepted. But, even though the argument is a case of wishful thinking, it would still be irrational to accept (7) and (8) but not (9). For accepting (7) amounts to accepting that either (7) s antecedent is false or (7) s consequent is true, and accepting (8) amounts to accepting that (7) s antecedent is not false. But, given any sentences P and Q, it would be irrational to accept ~P Q and ~~P while not accepting Q. So, even though the Hope Argument is a case of wishful thinking, it would still be irrational to accept its premises while not accepting its conclusion. Similarly, then, contrary to what Dorr claims, even if non-cognitivism renders the Liar Argument a case of wishful thinking, it does not follow that non-cognitivism allows one to rationally accept P1 and P2 but not C. 5 Turning to the second flaw, Dorr claims that if the Liar Argument is a case of wishful thinking, then Edgar s reasoning would be defective when Edgar infers C from P1 and P2. But if the Liar Argument is a case of wishful thinking, then Edgar s reasoning becomes defective at the beginning of the story when Edgar accepts P1 without sufficient reason to either reject P1 s antecedent or accept P1 s consequent. For accepting a conditional without either rejecting its antecedent or accepting its consequent amounts to accept- 4 Cf. n. 2, above. 5 Of course, there might be overriding reasons to reject C, in which case, assuming that the argument is valid, one should reject one of the premises. But it would still be irrational to accept P1 and P2 while not accepting C.

ing that, if one has sufficient reason to accept the antecedent, then one has sufficient reason to accept the consequent. So, when Edgar accepts P1 without sufficient reason to reject its antecedent or accept its consequent, Edgar ipso facto accepts that, if one has sufficient reason to accept P1 s antecedent, then one has sufficient reason to accept P1 s consequent. But if the Liar Argument is a case of wishful thinking, then the fact that one has sufficient reason to accept P1 s antecedent is irrelevant to whether one should accept P1 s consequent. The Hope Argument is similar: that one has sufficient reason to accept (7) s antecedent is irrelevant to whether one should accept (7) s consequent and to think otherwise would be irrational. So, if the Liar Argument is a case of wishful thinking, then it was irrational for Edgar to accept P1 in the first place. This is important, for it shows that if non-cognitivism implies that the Liar Argument is a case of wishful thinking, then even if non-cognitivism does not render the Liar Argument invalid, non-cognitivism still renders Edgar s reasoning fallacious. The third flaw in what Dorr claims is that, contrary to Dorr, noncognitivism does not imply that the Liar Argument is a case of wishful thinking. Wishful thinking is a kind of red-herring fallacy, and an argument commits a red-herring fallacy just in case it gives as a reason to accept a claim something that is irrelevant to whether one should accept the claim. The Hope Argument is a case in point: it gives my hoping that my proposal will be accepted as a reason to believe that my proposal will be accepted even though my hoping is irrelevant to whether one should believe that my proposal will be accepted. If non-cognitivism is true, however, then the Liar Argument does not give anything at all as a reason to believe that the souls of liars will be punished in the afterlife. To see this, consider the following question: (Hq) Why should I believe that my proposal will be accepted? Answering (Hq) requires giving a reason for belief. The answer that the Hope Argument gives is this: (Ha) I hope that my proposal will be accepted. Of course this is not a good reason, but it is still a reason. Suppose, though, that one were to respond to (Hq) with, say, a question, or a command, or some expression of approval indeed, anything other than a term that expresses a cognitive attitude. The response would be incoherent; it would be something like, One should believe that my proposal will be accepted because, yes, my proposal! That is incoherent. But if non-cognitivism is true, then the Liar Argument gives precisely that sort of answer to the question: (Lq) Why should one believe that the souls of liars will be punished in the afterlife?

The Liar Argument s answer to (Lq) is of course this: (La) Lying is wrong. But if non-cognitivism is true, then (La) expresses a non-cognitive attitude toward lying, and responding to (Lq) with the expression of a non-cognitive attitude would be incoherent. It would be like saying, One should believe that the souls of liars will be punished in the afterlife because boo: lying. That is incoherent. So, if non-cognitivism is true, then, contrary to what Dorr claims, the Liar Argument does not commit the wishful-thinking fallacy but that is because if non-cognitivism is true, then the Liar Argument does not offer a reason at all for belief. We now have the ingredients for a new objection to non-cognitivism, and, furthermore, we can see what Dorr s argument gets right and what it gets wrong. Here is the objection: (1) If non-cognitivism is true, then atomic moral claims do not give epistemic reasons. (2) Atomic moral claims do give epistemic reasons. (3) Non-cognitivism is false. (By epistemic reasons I mean reasons to believe a claim.) The argument is valid, and we have already seen why (10) is true: if non-cognitivism is true, then atomic moral claims express non-cognitive attitudes; but utterances in general that express non-cognitive attitudes cannot give reasons for belief. So, given non-cognitivism, atomic moral claims cannot give epistemic reasons. Hence, (10). That (11) is true is evinced by the fact that (La) is at least a coherent response to (Lq): if asked why one should believe that the souls of liars will be punished in the afterlife, it is at least coherent to respond with lying is wrong. Thus, (11). Given (10) and (11), we can conclude, per (12), that non-cognitivism is false. As for what Dorr s argument gets right, it points out quite correctly that, even if non-cognitivists solve the Frege-Geach problem, non-cognitivism still has a problem with atomic moral premises. But, whereas Dorr claims that non-cognitivism wrongly implies that atomic moral premises can give only bad epistemic reasons, we now see that that is not quite right. Rather, non-cognitivism implies that atomic moral premises cannot give epistemic reasons at all, which is a reason to reject noncognitivism. The College at Brockport, State University of New York Department of Philosophy jlong@brockport.edu

References Budolfson, M. (2011) Non-cognitivism and Rational Inference, Philosophical Studies 153: 243-59. Dorr, C. (2002) Non-cognitivism and Wishful Thinking, Noûs 36: 97-103. Enoch, D. (2003) How Noncognitivists Can Avoid Wishful Thinking, Southern Journal of Philosophy 41: 527-45. Lenman, J. (2003) Noncognitivism and Wishfulness, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6: 265-74. Mabrito, R. (2013) Are Expressivists Guilty of Wishful Thinking? Philosophical Studies 165: 1069-81. Schroeder, M. (2011) How Not to Avoid Wishful Thinking, in M. Brady, ed., New Waves in Metaethics, New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 126-40. (2008) Being For: Evaluating the Semantic Program of Expressivism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.