Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

Similar documents
Phil/Ling 375: Meaning and Mind [Handout #10]

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

Quine on Holism and Underdetermination

WILLARD VAN ORMAN QUINE

The Philosophy of Language. Quine versus Meaning

A Priori Knowledge: Analytic? Synthetic A Priori (again) Is All A Priori Knowledge Analytic?

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

CHAPTER IV NON-EMPIRICAL CRITIQUE OF A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Class #19: November 1 Two Dogmas of Empiricism

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

LANGUAGE, TRUTH, AND LOGIC A.J. AYER

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

A Defence of Kantian Synthetic-Analytic Distinction

LENT 2018 THEORY OF MEANING DR MAARTEN STEENHAGEN

ETHOS: Felsefe ve Toplumsal Bilimlerde Diyaloglar // Sayı: 4 (1) Ocak 2011

145 Philosophy of Science

Preserving Normativity in Epistemology: Quine s Thesis Revisited

5: Preliminaries to the Argument

DAVIDSON AND CONCEPTUAL SCHEMES PAUL BROADBENT. A thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham for the degree of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Junior Research Fellow and Lecturer in Philosophy Worcester College, University of Oxford Walton Street Oxford OX1 2HB Great Britain

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Philosophy 308 The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Hamilton College, Fall 2014

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

CRITIQUE OF THE ANALYTIC/SYNTHETIC DISTINCTION. by Marty Fields

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

THE IDEA OF A PRIORI REVISITED* SANJIT CHAKRABORTY

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Quine on the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

TRANSCENDENTAL ARGUMENTS: VERIPICATIONISM OR PARASITISM? Douglas Ehring

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

Analyticity PAUL ARTIN BOGHOSSIAN

Emotivism. Meta-ethical approaches

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

When meaning goes by the board, what about philosophy? Jaroslav Peregrin

Two Dogmas of Analytical Philosophy

IN his renowned article, On the Very Idea of a Conceptual

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Metaphysical atomism and the attraction of materialism.

Indeterminacy, A Priority, and Analyticity in the Quinean Critique

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

A. J. Ayer ( )

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Although Quine is widely known as an influential critic of logical positivism, there is now a

The Coherence of Kant s Synthetic A Priori

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Assertion and Inference

The Legacy of 'Two Dogmas'

Ibuanyidanda (Complementary Reflection), African Philosophy and General Issues in Philosophy

QUINE AND DAVIDSON ON OBSERVATION SENTENCES

Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief

Alternative Conceptual Schemes and a Non-Kantian Scheme-Content Dualism

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

A CONSEQUENCE OF THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL HOLISM OF QUINE AND A REALIST/REVISIONIST INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM LOGIC: SCEPTICISM BY COLIN LESLIE DEAN

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Philosophical Review.

A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

On Katz and Indeterminacy of Translation

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

Quine and the a priori

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Analyticity and Holism in Quine's Thought Peter Hylton

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

A Distinction between Science and Philosophy

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following, social holism

NOTES ON A PRIORI KNOWLEDGE 10/6/03

356 THE MONIST all Cretans were liars. It can be put more simply in the form: if a man makes the statement I am lying, is he lying or not? If he is, t

Logical Content and Empirical Significance

Consciousness might be defined as the perceiver of mental phenomena. We might say that there are no differences between one perceiver and another, as

Transcription:

24.251: Philosophy of Language Paper 1: W.V.O. Quine, Two Dogmas of Empiricism 14 October 2011 Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a sentence is precisely the methods by which we could go about determining the truth of that sentence. That is, the meaning of a sentence is specified by the set of observations we could perform in order to either confirm or infirm the sentence; we call these observations the verification condition of the sentence. The verification theory thus rules out as meaningless any sentences whose content makes no difference at all to our empirical experiences, so that meaning is intimately associated with our perception and expectations for the world around us. By its nature, then, the verification theory is a theory of reductionism, aiming to reduce the theory of linguistic meaning to a theory of verification conditions, drawn from our sensory experience. Of course, it seems reasonable to conclude also that there are also sentences which are true just by their very content. The verificationists call such sentences analytic sentences, in the spirit of analyticity used by Leibniz, Kant and others, that the sentence is true in all possible worlds, and whose very negation is a contradiction. Taking this for granted at the moment, this would then imply a rather sharp distinction between these analytic sentences and synthetic sentences, those whose verification condition is not null, and whose truth is grounded on empirical facts. These two aspects of the verification theory are drawn from the more general philosophical theory of empiricism, which holds that all knowledge ultimately comes from sensory experience. Thus, W.V.O. Quine calls these two beliefs, the first of the distinction between analytic and synthetic truths, and the second of the validity of reductionism in general, the two dogmas of empiricism. In his 1951

paper Two Dogmas of Empiricism, Quine attacks both of these dogmas, first questioning the distinction between analytic and synthetic truths, and then moving on to cast doubt on the feasibility of reductionism in the philosophy of language. He argues that, in fact, the first dogma is not independent of the second, and, more pointedly, the only way to save the first is to assume the second. Thus, by rejecting reductionism on a sentence-by-sentence basis (the second dogma) as untenable, he concludes that the only way to preserve empiricism itself is to turn to a more holistic approach for meaning, wherein the meaning of sentences cannot be understood nor even considered individually, but rather in terms of the entire language as a whole. Quine spends a great deal of his paper arguing for the dependence of analyticity on that of verificationist reductionism. To accomplish this, Quine considers a number of ways by which we could define analyticity separately from verification he considers definition, interchangeability, and even the use of sematical rules. We discuss two of these, definition and interchangeability, in brief, to get a flavor of Quine s argument. The essence, however, is that any attempt to nail down the analyticity of a sentence in the end seems to double back to the concept of analyticity itself, in the form, figuratively speaking, of a closed curve in space, as he describes it. To take his example, a sentence like No bachelor is married, is a typical example of what the verificationists would call an analytic truth. But Quine notes that this requires the concept of synonymy we need to first substitute unmarried man for bachelor in order to obtain the logical truth No unmarried man is married. But how do we go about finding out this synonymy? Quine argues that this is a difficult problem. The obvious attempt at using the idea of definition fails because it simply is not the case that people sat down at some point in history and defined bachelor to be unmarried man. The only case in which definition is sufficient for synonymy is when a word has been chosen specifically to be shorthand for a longer phrase; unfortunately, this is not how most language

works. To attempt to define bachelor we must appeal to other synonyms to eventually arrive at unmarried man. But then synonymy is just as difficult as analyticity. Another attempt Quine consider is the use of interchangeability salva veritate, where interchanging the word unmarried man for bachelor does not cause the truth-value of the sentence change. It certainly does seem possible to use this approach, since the statement Necessarily, all and only bachelors are unmarried men, has the same truth condition as Necessarily, all and only bachelors are bachelors. But the problem lies in the use of the word necessarily, which Quine argues is a feature of our language that presupposes an independent understanding of analyticity. Without the use of necessarily, as in an extensional language, we lose the kind of synonymy we are looking for; interchanging a creature with a heart with a creature with kidneys preserves the truth-value of any sentence containing the phrase a creature with a heart, but this accidental matter of fact does not have the same kind of status as seemingly more direct synonymy as with bachelor and unmarried man. Thus, since the only way to use interchangeability is to assume we have precisely what we are looking for, Quine rejects this attempt at a solution as well. Once Quine establishes the difficulty of determining the analyticity of a sentence independently of the verificationist criterion, he then turns to verification as the only source of hope. In this program, Quine notices that we can define an analytic sentence as precisely those sentences whose verification condition is null that is, sentences which do not require any empirical observation to establish their truth. Thus, we can simply define analyticity in terms of verification, and have the first dogma of empiricism depend on the second. As Quine puts it, if the verification theory can be accepted as an adequate account of statement synonymy, the notion of analyticity is saved after all. This is a big gamble, as the collapse of the second dogma will inevitably drag the first with it as well, but Quine is left with no alternatives after the apparently hopeless attempts in nailing down analyticity independently. And of course, this collapse, Quine pursues, is precisely what happens.

Quine interprets the second dogma to be the claim that the meaning of a single, individual sentence is just the verification condition of that sentence that associated with each (synthetic) sentence is a set of empirical observations which could be done in order to verify the truth of the sentence. But Quine questions whether this could actually be done. To accomplish this kind of reduction, there must be some way of translating a sentence to a sense-datum language of purely sensory data, so that we can associate each meaningful sentence with a statement about immediate experience. The problem is that it is very difficult to do so for single sentences. Given a hypothesis, it is not, in general, possible to verify that hypothesis without any additional assumptions. Lycan in Chapter 8 gives an illuminating example, of the statement There is a chair at the head of this table. The observation statement of this sentence could be that there is an object with four legs and a seat located near another object with a flat top, and so on, but this presupposes that we can trust our eyes to tell us what is in the room. Other concerns might be whether our eyes are open, the room is lighted, the chair is in plain view, we are not hallucinating, etc. The point is that verifying a sentence involves a set of observation statements which directly involve other sentences, ones which we have no desire to consider. But consider them we must, or else we cannot uphold the program of verification. It appears then that both dogmas of empiricism have come down on this problem of the complexity of verification. But instead of rejecting empiricism because of this, Quine bites the bullet and suggests that perhaps we could embrace the difficulty of verification. That is, if we accept that statements confront empirical verification along with a mass of other statements, then we can still hold onto the theory of empiricism at, at least, the spirit of verificationism. We no longer have reductionism on single sentences standing on their own, nor can we maintain a sharp distinction between analytic and synthetic sentences. But, Quine argues, the downfall of these two dogmas leads instead to a holistic approach to empiricism in the theory of meaning which has implications for the philosophy of both language and science.

Quine urges for empiricism without the two dogmas, or in his words, a theory of meaning where our statements about the external world face the tribunal of sense experience not individually but only as a corporate body. Reductionism in the sense of the second dogma thus becomes impossible, and without that, it is consequently difficult to define a sharp distinction between analytic and synthetic truth, for any statement can be held true come what may, if we make drastic enough adjustments elsewhere in the system of all our statements about the world. Thus, the meaning of language becomes as inextricably tied up as our beliefs about the world, and the best we can do from an empirical standpoint is to compare the meaning of our sentences in the context of all our other sentences to the external world; in the same spirit as the verificationists ruled out talk about matters of no difference to our experiences, Quine states, it is nonsense, and the root of much nonsense, to speak of a linguistic component and a factual component in the truth of any individual statement, which is as much of a death knell to simplistic, radical reductionism as verificationism was to the metaphysics before it. More interestingly, Quine in fact widens the scope of his new take on empiricism to involve much more than just the philosophy of language. He describes the very structure of our beliefs and knowledge about the world as a man-made fabric which impinges on experience only along the edges total science is like a field of force whose boundary conditions are experience. A conflict with experience at the periphery occasions readjustments in the interior of the field. Thus, the great collection of our sentence and our beliefs are only connected to experience via a network of many others, and when we meet a conflict with experience, we can pick any of the nodes in the network to tweak. The converse to this is that there are no statements immune to revision, as Quine gives the example of the rejection of the law of the excluded middle in the face of quantum mechanics. It is not the case that we merely have a single sentence or belief which is either falsified or verified. Rather, we need to consider all the possible contingencies of which our statement and the sense-datum are functions. It then is up to the individual to determine which of these contingencies

might be worth falsifying or verifying, or whether they all hold together, and it is in fact the sentence which the empirical verdict falls upon. This is, in some sense, a reformulation of the spirit of pragmatism, only elevated beyond the scope of an individual belief or thought to a sort of pragmatism on the whole of our knowledge and beliefs. Quine remains a steadfast empiricist, but in his view, the limited dogmas, though tidy and satisfyingly detailed in their treatment of individual beliefs and statements, cannot hold up against the very nature of empiricism, and especially against the complicated and interdependent ways by which we gain experiential knowledge. Quine put questions about the meaning of sentences on par with questions about our knowledge of the world, and he maintains that this duality prevents us from saying whether a difference in meaning is a difference in words or a difference in fact. Either way a difference is a difference, but this time, it is up to us to pick out the distinction for ourselves, in a manner not quite unlike the pursuit of natural science.