Fuller, Steve. Veritism as Fake Philosophy: Reply to Baker and Oreskes. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 10 (2017):

Similar documents
Orienting Social Epistemology 1 Francis Remedios, Independent Researcher, SERRC

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Inquiry, Knowledge, and Truth: Pragmatic Conceptions. Pragmatism is a philosophical position characterized by its specific mode of inquiry, and

3. Knowledge and Justification

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Bayesian Probability

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Comments on Lasersohn

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

COPYRIGHT 2009ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

1. Why were you initially drawn to epistemology (and what keeps you interested)?

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

The poverty of mathematical and existential truth: examples from fisheries science C. J. Corkett

ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Evidential arguments from evil

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Florida State University Libraries

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Epistemic Responsibility in Science

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Chapter 2 Ethical Concepts and Ethical Theories: Establishing and Justifying a Moral System

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Not-So-Well-Designed Scientific Communities. Inkeri Koskinen, University of Helsinki

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Questioning Contextualism Brian Weatherson, Cornell University references etc incomplete

Alexander of Hales, The Sum of Theology 1 (translated by Oleg Bychkov) Introduction, Question One On the discipline of theology

Naturalism and is Opponents

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Radical Centrism & the Redemption of Secular Philosophy

A Framework for the Good

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

Gilbert. Margaret. Scientists Are People Too: Comment on Andersen. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 5 (2017):

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Harry Collins and the Crisis of Expertise. Ylikoski, Petri Kullervo.

A CONTRACTUALIST READING OF KANT S PROOF OF THE FORMULA OF HUMANITY. Adam Cureton

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Transcription:

http://social-epistemology.com ISSN: 2471-9560 Veritism as Fake Philosophy: Reply to Baker and Oreskes Steve Fuller, University of Warwick Fuller, Steve. Veritism as Fake Philosophy: Reply to Baker and Oreskes. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 10 (2017): 47-51.

Vol. 6, no. 10 (2017): 47-51 John Stuart Mill and Karl Popper would be surprised to learn from Baker and Oreskes (2017) that freedom is a non-cognitive value. Insofar as freedom both the freedom to assert and the freedom to deny is a necessary feature of any genuine process of inquiry, one might have thought that it was one of the foundational values of knowledge. But of course, Baker and Oreskes are using cognitive in a more technical sense, one introduced by the logical positivists and remains largely intact in contemporary analytic epistemology and philosophy of science. It was also prevalent in post-war history and sociology of science prior to the rise of STS. This conception of the cognitive trades on a clear distinction between what lies inside and outside a conceptual framework in this case, the conceptual framework of science. But there s a sting in the tail. An Epistemic Game Baker and Oreskes don t seem to realize that this very conception of the cognitive is in the post-truth mould that I defend. After all, for the positivists, truth is a second order concept that lacks any determinate meaning except relative to the language in terms of which knowledge claims can be expressed. It was in this spirit that Rudolf Carnap thought that Thomas Kuhn s paradigm had put pragmatic flesh on the positivists logical bones (Reisch 1991). (It is worth emphasizing that Carnap passed this judgement before Kuhn s fans turned him into the torchbearer for post-positivist philosophy of science.) At the same time, this orientation led the positivists to promote and try to construct a universal language of science into which all knowledge claims could be translated and evaluated. All of this shows that the positivists weren t veritists because, unlike Baker and Oreskes, they didn t presuppose the existence of some univocal understanding of truth that all sincere inquirers will ultimately reach. Rather, truth is just a general property of the language that one decides to use or the game one decides to play. In that case truth corresponds to satisfying truth conditions as specified by the rules of a given language, just as goal corresponds to satisfying the rules of play in a given game. To be sure, the positivists complicated matters because they also took seriously that science aspires to command universal assent for its knowledge claims, in which case science s language needs to be set up in a way that enables everyone to transact their knowledge claims inside it; hence, the need to reduce such claims to their calculable and measurable components. This effectively put the positivists in partial opposition to all the existing sciences of their day, each with its own parochial framework governed by the rules of its distinctive language game. The need to overcome this tendency explains the project of an International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. In short, logical positivism was about designing an epistemic game which they called science that anyone could play and potentially win. Given some of the things that Baker and Oreskes impute to me, they may be surprised to learn that I actually think that the logical positivists as well as Mill and Popper were on 47

S. Fuller the right track. Indeed, I have always believed this. But these views have nothing to do with veritism, which I continue to put in scare quotes because, in the spirit of our times, it s a bit of fake philosophy. It may work to shore up philosophical authority in public but fails to capture the conflicting definitions and criteria that philosophers themselves have offered not only for truth but also for such related terms as evidence and validation. All of these key epistemological terms are essentially contested concepts within philosophy. It is not simply that philosophers disagree on what is, say, true or false but more importantly they disagree on what it means to say that something is true or false. (I summarize the issue here.) Philosophical Fakeness Richard Rorty became such a hate figure among analytic philosophers because he called out the veritists on their fakeness. Yes, philosophers can tell you what truth is, but just as long as you accept a lot of contentious assumptions and hope those capable of contending those assumptions aren t in the room when you re speaking! Put another way, Rorty refused to adopt a double truth doctrine for philosophy, whereby amongst themselves philosophers adopt a semi-detached attitude towards various conflicting conceptions of truth while at the same time presenting a united front to non-philosophers, lest these masses start to believe some disreputable things. The philosophical fakeness of veritism is exemplified in the following sentence, which appears in Baker and Oreskes (2017, 69) latest response: On the contrary, truth (along with evidence, facts, and other words science studies scholars tend to relegate to scare quotes) is a far more plausible choice for one of a potential plurality of regulative ideals for an enterprise that, after all, does have an obviously cognitive function. The sentence prima facie commits the category mistake of presuming that truth is one more albeit preferred possible regulative ideal of science alongside, say, instrumental effectiveness, cultural appropriateness, etc. However, truth in the logical positivist sense is a feature of all regulative ideals of science, each of which should be understood as specifying a language game that is governed by its own validation procedures the rules of the game, if you will in terms of which one theory is determined (or verified ) to be, say, more effective than another or more appropriate than another. Notice I said prima facie. My guess is that when Baker and Oreskes say truth is a regulative ideal of science, they are simply referring to a social arrangement whereby the self-organizing scientific community is the final arbiter on all knowledge claims accepted by society at large. As they point out, the scientific community can get things wrong but things become wrong only when the scientific community says so, and they become fixed only when the scientific community says so. In short, under the guise of truth, Baker and Oreskes are advocating what I have called cognitive authoritarianism (Fuller 1988, chapter 12). 48

Vol. 6, no. 10 (2017): 47-51 Before ending with a brief discussion of what I think may be true about veritism, it is difficult not to notice the moralism associated with Baker and Oreskes invocation of truth. This carries over to such other pseudo-epistemic concepts as trust and reliability, which are seen as marks of the scientific character, whereby scientific attaches both to a body of knowledge and the people who produce that knowledge. I say pseudo because there is no agreed measure of these qualities. Regarding Trust Trust is a quality whose presence is felt mainly as a double absence, namely, a studied refusal to examine knowledge claims for oneself which is subsequently judged to have had non-negative consequences. (I have called trust a phlogistemic concept for this reason, as it resembles the pseudo-element phlogiston, Fuller 1996). Indeed, in opposition to this general sensibility, I have gone so far as to argue that universities should be in the business of epistemic trust-busting. Here is my original assertion: In short, universities function as knowledge trust-busters whose own corporate capacities of creative destruction prevent new knowledge from turning into intellectual property (Fuller 2002, 47; italics in original). By corporate capacities, I meant the various means at the university s disposal to ensure that the people in a position to take forward new knowledge are not simply part of the class of those who created it in the first place. More concretely, of course I have in mind ordinary teaching that aims to express even the most sophisticated concepts in terms ordinary students can understand and use. But also I mean to include affirmative action policies that are specifically designed to incorporate a broader range of people than might otherwise attend the university. Taken together, these counteract the neo-feudalism to which academic knowledge production is prone rent-seeking, if you will which Baker and Oreskes appear unable to recognize. As for reliability, it is a term whose meaning depends on specifying the conditions say, in the design of an experiment under which a pattern of behaviour is expected to occur. Outside of such tightly defined conditions, which is where most scientific controversies happen, it is not clear how cases should be classified and counted, and hence what reliable means. Indeed, STS has not only drawn attention to this fact but it has gone further say, in the work of Harry Collins to question whether even lab-based reliability is possible without some sort of collusion between researchers. In other words, the social accomplishment of reliable knowledge is at least partly an expression of solidarity among members of the scientific community a closing of the ranks, to put it less charitably. An especially good example of the foregoing is what has been dubbed Climategate, which involved the releasing of e-mails from the UK s main climate science research group in response to a journalist s Freedom of Information request. While no wrongdoing was formally established, the e-mails did reveal the extent to which scientists from across the world effectively conspired to present the data for climate change in ways that obscured 49

S. Fuller interpretive ambiguities, thereby pre-empting possible appropriations by so-called climate change sceptics. To be sure, from the symmetrical normative stance of classic STS, Climategate simply reveals the micro-processes by which a scientific consensus is normally and literally manufactured. Nevertheless, I doubt that Baker and Oreskes would turn to Climategate as their paradigm case of a scientific consensus. But why not? The reason is that they refuse to acknowledge the labour that is involved in securing collective assent over any significant knowledge claim. As I observed in my original response to Baker and Oreskes, one might be forgiven for concluding from reading the likes of Merton, Habermas and others who see consensus formation as essential to science that an analogue of the invisible hand is at play. On their telling, informed people draw the same conclusions from the same evidence. The actual social interaction of the scientists carries little cognitive weight in its own right. Instead it simply reinforces what any rational individual is capable of inferring for him- or herself in the same situation. At most, other people provide additional data points but they don t alter the rules of right reasoning. Ironically, considering Baker and Oreskes allergic reaction to any talk of science as a market, this image of Homo scientificus to which they attach themselves seems rather like what they don t like about Homo oeconomicus. Climbing the Mountain The contrasting view of consensus formation, which I uphold, is more explicitly rhetorical. It appeals to a mix of strategic and epistemic considerations in a setting where the actual interaction between the parties sets the parameters that defines the scope of any possible consensus. Although Kuhn also valorized consensus as the glue that holds together normal science puzzle-solving, to his credit he clearly saw its rhetorical and even coercive character, from pedagogy to peer review. For this reason, Kuhn is the one who STSers still usually cite as a precursor on this matter. Unlike Baker and Oreskes, he didn t resort to the fake philosophy of veritism to cover up the fact that truth is ultimately a social achievement. Finally, I suggested that there may be a way of redeeming veritism from its current status of fake philosophy. Just because truth is what W.B. Gallie originally called an essentially contested concept, it doesn t follow that it is a mere chimera. But how to resolve truth s palpable diversity of conceptions into a unified vision of reality? The clue to redemption is provided by Charles Sanders Peirce, whose idea of truth as the final scientific consensus informs Baker and Oreskes normative orientation. Peirce equated truth with the ultimate theory of everything, which amounts to putting everything in its place, thereby resolving all the internal disagreements of perception and understanding that are a normal feature of any active inquiry. It s the moment when the blind men in the Hindu adage discover the elephant they ve been groping and (Popper s metaphor) the climbers coming from different directions reach the same mountain top. 1 1 One might also add the French word for groping, tâtonnement, common to Turgot s and Walras understanding of how general equilibrium is reached in the economy, as well as Theilard de Chardin s conception of how God comes to be fully realized in the cosmos. 50

Vol. 6, no. 10 (2017): 47-51 Peirce s vision was informed by his understanding of John Duns Scotus, the early fourteenth scholastic who provided a deep metaphysical understanding of Augustine s Platonic reading of the Biblical Fall of humanity. Our fallen state consists in the dismemberment of our divine nature, something that is regularly on display in the variability of humans with regard to the virtues, all of which God displays to their greatest extent. For example, the most knowledgeable humans are not necessarily the most benevolent. The journey back to God is basically one of putting these pieces the virtues back together again into a coherent whole. At the level of organized inquiry, we find a similar fragmentation of effort, as the language game of each science exaggerates certain modes of access to reality at the expense of others. To be sure, Kuhn and STS accept, if not outright valorise, disciplinary specialisation as a mark of the increasing complexification of the knowledge system. Not surprisingly, perhaps, they also downplay the significance in the sort of capital T sense of truth that Baker and Oreskes valorise. One obvious solution would be for defenders of veritism to embrace an updated version of the unified science project championed by the logical positivists, which aimed to integrate all forms of knowledge in terms of some common currency of intellectual exchange. (My earlier comments against neo-feudal tendencies in academia should be seen in this light.) This would be the analogue of the original theological project of humanity reconstituting its divine nature, which Peirce secularised as the consensus theory of truth. Further considerations along these lines may be found here. Contact details: S.W.Fuller@warwick.ac.uk References Baker, Erik and Naomi Oreskes. Science as a Game, Marketplace or Both: A Reply to Steve Fuller. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 9 (2017): 65-69. Fuller, Steve. Social Epistemology. Bloomington IN: Indiana University Press, 1988. Fuller, Steve. Recent Work in Social Epistemology. American Philosophical Quarterly 33: 14966, 1996. Fuller, Steve. Knowledge Management Foundations. Woburn MA: Butterworth-Heinemann, 2002. Fuller, Steve. What are You Playing At? On the Use and Abuse of Games in STS. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 6, no. 9 (2017): 39-49. Reisch, George A. Did Kuhn Kill Logical Positivism? Philosophy of Science 58, no. 2 (1991): 264-277. 51