Plato's Introduction of Forms (review)

Similar documents
THE UNITY OF COURAGE AND WISDOM IN PLATO S PROTAGORAS LINO BIANCO

Plato & Socrates. Plato ( B.C.E.) was the student of Socrates ( B.C.E.) and the founder of the Academy in Athens.

Collection and Division in the Philebus

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2014/15

PHL 200Y Teaching Assistants:

The Priority of Definition. Continuum Companion to Socrates Edd. Bussanich and Smith. Hugh H. Benson

Edinburgh Research Explorer

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2013/14

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Plato and the art of philosophical writing

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Review of Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith, "Socratic Moral Psychology"

Topics and Posterior Analytics. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

What conditions does Plato expect a good definition to meet? Is he right to impose them?

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

Government 203 Political Theorists and Their Theories: Plato Spring Semester 2010 Clark University

Plato - Five Dialogues: Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Meno, Phaedo By Plato, G. M. A. Grube

Philosophy as preparation for death (59d-69c) Soc. asks Cebes to tell a friend that if he is wise he will follow me as soon as possible.

Reading Euthyphro Plato as a literary artist

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Plato versus Aristotle

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2015/16

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

Plato's Doctrine Of Forms: Modern Misunderstandings

(4) PLATO. (i) PLATO- LIFE and WORK

Divine command theory

ONE of the reasons why the thought of Paul Tillich is so impressive

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Plato BCE Republic, ca BCE

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

Curriculum Vitae: Dr. Scott LaBarge (current as of 7/2012)

Why Plato's Cave? Ancient Greek Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Plato s Rationalistic Method. Hugh H. Benson. (please cite that version)

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

Overview Plato Socrates Phaedo Summary. Plato: Phaedo Jan. 31 Feb. 5, 2014

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

First Treatise <Chapter 1. On the Eternity of Things>

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

INTRODUCTION TO EPISTEMOLOGY

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Kant and his Successors

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Plato s Protagoras Virtue & Expertise. Plato s Protagoras The Unity of the Virtues

Ancient Greek Philosophy. Instructor: Dr. Jason Sheley

What is Philosophy? Four Suggestions for What Philosophy Is. 2. Wisdom as Self-understanding. 1. Love of Philosophy

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?


But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

latter case, if we offer different concepts by which to define piety, we risk no longer talking about piety. I.e., the forms are one and all

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

MENO. We must first define Platonic Dialogue and then consider the Meno.

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Informalizing Formal Logic

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Knowledge in Plato. And couple of pages later:

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

CONCEPT OF IMMORTALITY IN PLATO S PHAEDO

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

4AANA001 Greek Philosophy I Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Previous Final Examinations Philosophy 1

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

The Socratic Fallacy in the Early Dialogues

Lecture 14 Rationalism

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Introduction: Goddess and God in Our Lives

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Lists in the Meno and the Euthyphro

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Transcription:

Plato's Introduction of Forms (review) Lloyd P. Gerson Mouseion: Journal of the Classical Association of Canada, Volume 7, Number 1, 2007, LI Series III, pp. 83-87 (Review) Published by University of Toronto Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/mou.0.0000 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/238083 No institutional affiliation (24 Jul 2018 06:55 GMT)

velle technique numérique. BOOK REVIEWS/COMPTES RENDUS 83 PENELOPE SKARSOULI ECOLE DES HAUTES ETUDES EN SCIENCES SOCIALES PARIS, FRANCE pinelopi.skarsouli@wanadoo.fr R.M. DANCY. Plato s Introduction of Forms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp. xii + 348. $75.00. ISBN 0-521-83801-0. In this carefully constructed monograph, Dancy aims to show in painstaking detail how Plato s theory of Forms emerged out of Socrates quest for definitions. Thus, Dancy subscribes to a traditional developmentalist approach to Plato, eschewing the increasingly common approach that seeks to impose some sort of unitarianism on the philosophy in the dialogues (2). By Socrates Dancy means the literary character in the dialogues, not the historical person. So the development from a search for definitions to the positing of Forms is taken to be a development within Plato s thinking, not a development from adherence to one philosopher s view (Socrates) to another, Plato s (3). Dancy accepts the standard developmentalist division of the dialogues into early, middle, and late. He divided the early dialogues into those whose focus is on definition and into those whose focus is not. The former group includes: Charmides, Euthyphro, Hippias Major, Laches, Lysis, and Republic I. It is to the presuppositions underlying the search for definitions in these dialogues that Dancy devotes the bulk of this book. Scant attention is paid to the other dialogues said to be in this group: Apology, Crito, Euthydemus, Hippias Minor, Ion, Menexenus, Protagoras, and Gorgias. What are usually called middle dialogues Dancy calls doctrinal. The first of these, Meno, Dancy argues is a transitional dialogue. That is, in it is found a sort of bridge from the search for definition to the theory of Forms. To this dialogue Dancy devotes one lengthy chapter. The other doctrinal dialogues discussed in this book are Phaedo and (in a very brief chapter) Symposium. In these dialogues, Dancy finds expression of the theory of Forms. The actual discussion of the theory of Forms thus takes up roughly one fifth of the book, making Dancy s introduction to the introduction of Forms very lengthy, indeed. Notably absent from the material treated in this the last part of the book is any discussion of the central books of Republic or Cratylus and Phaedrus, dialogues usually taken to belong to Plato s middle period in which the theory of Forms is constructed. Altogether

84 BOOK REVIEWS/COMPTES RENDUS absent is any discussion of subsequent developments in the theory of Forms in Plato s so-called later dialogues. Dancy rests his developmentalist account of the genesis of the theory of Forms on Aristotle s testimony in his Metaphysics to the effect that Plato began by embracing Socrates concern with the definitions of the virtues. Having been influenced by Heraclitus and Cratylus, however, Plato came to hold that these definitions could not correspond to anything in the constantly changing sensible world (11 13). Aristotle in his testimony is explicit that Plato was influenced by the flux doctrine in his youth. Presumably, this makes it at least possible or even likely that when Plato came under Socrates influence he already held that the sensible realm could not contain objects suitable for definition but that the objects of definition had to be separate. If that is so, then it is difficult to see the justification for insisting that Plato s theory developed from an adherence to definitions (sans Forms) to a postulation of Forms. Why not suppose that his postulation of Forms was coincident with his concurrence with Socrates that definitions of the virtues were vital? But then, against Dancy s repeated claims that the discussions of definitions in the early dialogues do not presuppose Forms, it may be in fact that they do. Dancy would no doubt want to make the reasonable reply that Plato s beliefs at the time of writing the dialogues are unrecoverable and so irrelevant. We are only able to focus on the logic of the actual arguments in the text. The dichotomy of psychology or logic is a false one. As he himself argues, one of the assumptions that Socrates brings to the definitional dialogues is that the Forms are paradigms or essences (115 133). On the face of it this is a metaphysical claim and deserves analysis. It is also certainly worth asking how separation arises out of the postulation of paradigmatic entities. To explore this question, however, is to open up the possibility that there is indeed a theory of Forms in the early dialogues, or perhaps even the possibility that Plato assumed at the time of writing these dialogues that the definitions sought must be of separate Forms. Dancy, however, holds that the search for definitions is a metaphysically innocent enterprise and that only with the introduction of separate Forms does metaphysics enter the picture. This would I think be plausible only if the Socratic search for definitions treated the object of these definitions as terms or concepts. This seems to me to be as far from the truth as anything one could say about these dialogues, and for a reason to which Dancy himself subscribes, namely, that the objects of the definitions are supposed to serve an explanatory role in reality (134 147). Thus, a deed is pious owing to the Form of Piety. This would make no sense if the sought-for definition of piety were of a concept or of a word. But if Piety is a thing (a very strange thing,

BOOK REVIEWS/COMPTES RENDUS 85 indeed), then a refusal to explore what Plato meant by claiming this is simply not justified by adducing Aristotle s testimony that Plato separated the Forms. Adding to the suspicion that Dancy supposes that Socratic definitions are of concepts or terms is the third requirement he adduces for a proper definition, namely, substitutivity (80 114). This is the requirement that the definiens must be substitutable salva veritate with the definiendum. The definiens includes necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of the definiendum. This is a standard and reasonable requirement for definitions in any context other than one in which the definiendum is a thing. There are no conditions for the application of such a thing. And there is nothing else to which the thing is identical but itself. The sought-for logos of a Form (which Dancy recognizes is not exactly a definition or a horismos) may well be required to give us necessary and sufficient conditions for the presence of an instance of it. The very idea, though, of the Form as a thing being definable or even expressible in a logos raises a host of metaphysical issues. One wonders if the aporetic nature of the early definitional dialogues is intended to reveal this fact. Dancy will not allow that even in Meno is there a theory of Forms (240). He rejects the standard interpretation of the Doctrine of Recollection according to which knowledge is recollection of the Forms with which we were acquainted prior to embodiment, though he acknowledges that this interpretation works for Phaedo. We are to suppose that, when Socrates uses the word eidos, either he is not talking about the things we recollect or, if he is, this does not imply a theory of Forms (211 215). Both alternatives seem frankly far fetched. Leaving aside the question of the cogency of the argument that learning is recollection, if Plato held that we do recollect that which we encountered in a disembodied state, and that it is this fact that solves Meno s paradox, why resist the obvious implication that separate Forms are here in play? The only reason I can see that Dancy gives for his denial of this is that if it were true in Meno, this would cast doubt on his thesis that the discussion of Forms in the earlier dialogues does not amount to a theory of Forms. When we finally do get to the theory of Forms, Dancy finds it to be necessarily connected to separation and to the consequent diminution of the intelligibility of the sensible world (253 283). This seems right, though his discussion of both points is all too brief. He does not address the question of whether separation means that Forms can exist uninstantiated or not. Nor with respect to the diminished reality of the sensible world does he go beyond explaining it in terms of the Argument from Relativity and conflating this argument with the Argument from

86 BOOK REVIEWS/COMPTES RENDUS Flux. But it is not clear why if it is the case that x is f with respect to y and not-f with respect to z, this in any way diminishes the being or intelligibility of x. Nevertheless, in Republic (cf. 479c d) this seems to be exactly what Plato wants to maintain. Since Dancy apparently does not maintain that Republic adds an essential feature of the theory of Forms that is not contained in Phaedo, it is at least puzzling why the central and perhaps most notorious implication of the separation of Forms is not here scrutinized. Nor is it clear why Dancy thinks that Plato s embrace of the Argument from Flux amounts to the Argument from Relativity. Plato s acceptance of the former is in any case qualified; otherwise, there would be no cases of predication or sameness in difference in the sensible world to explain. His endorsement of this Argument is, on Aristotle s account, based on his conviction that knowledge exists and knowledge cannot be of ta gignomena. If relativity is supposed to entail separate Forms, flux does not. It is only with the added premise that knowledge exists, and that knowledge is not of sensibles, that separate Forms follow. But then relativity is irrelevant to this argument. It seems rather that what Dancy takes to be an argument from relativity in Phaedo 74a is really an argument from the deficiency (ti elleipei) of sensible equals, not from the fact that something equal to one thing appears unequal to another. Dancy s insistence on focusing on the analytic core of the theory of Forms is wholly admirable. But his exclusion of the material contained in Republic from this core means, among other things, that he has no idea how to connect Socrates insistence in Phaedo 99b on teleological explanations with the explanatory role that Forms are given in the final argument for the immortality of the soul. The most we can say, Dancy argues, is that teleological explanations are not incompatible with the essential explanatory role of Forms (293). There is a problem in Dancy s locating the core of the theory of Forms in those passages where Forms are explicitly adduced in order to prove the immortality of the soul. It seems a gratuitous inference to say that the essential features in the introduction of Forms do not include teleological explanation just because teleological explanation does not figure into the proof for the immortality of the soul. It is not even entirely clear that teleological explanation is excluded from the method of hypothesizing Forms that Socrates describes. If, as he says, hypothesizing is to continue until one reaches something adequate (ti hikanon, 101e1 2), it is not implausible that this something adequate is the unhypothetical first principle of all in Republic, namely, the Idea of the Good. This interpretation leads us back to the explanatory role of Forms in the early dialogues and the possibility that Dancy s analysis of the theory of Forms is based on a spurious essentialism, not about Forms, but about

BOOK REVIEWS/COMPTES RENDUS 87 Plato s theorizing. This book contains a virtuoso display of what might be termed analytic Platonism, and as such it may help clarify one s thinking about Forms. It does not, however, advance our understanding of Plato s metaphysics very much. LLOYD P. GERSON DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO TORONTO, ON M5S1J4 lloyd.gerson@utoronto.ca C. BOWEN and ROBERT B. TODD, intro. and trans. Cleomedes Lectures on Astronomy: A Translation of The Heavens. Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press, 2004. Pp. xvi + 238. US $17.95, Can. $25.95. ISBN 0-521-81586-X. With Cleomedes Lectures on Astronomy: A Translation of The Heavens, Alan C. Bowen and Robert B. Todd (hereafter B/T) have produced an exemplary and eminently useful translation, the first in English, of an important late Stoic pedagogical text on astronomy. By design this collaborative effort, based on Todd s 1990 Teubner of Cleomedes Caelestia (Greek Meteora), is intended both for a varied readership most of whom will not know the ancient languages and especially for those whose interests lie in later Stoic philosophy, in ancient mathematical astronomy, or in the history of ancient astronomy proper (xii). Enhanced and enriched by an expansive introduction and a comprehensive running commentary on the translated text, this finely produced and affordable volume also features a substantial array of appended explanatory materials supplementary to the translation proper. Taken together, these features render the work a model of what a modern translation of an ancient technical work ought to be. To appreciate fully the significance of the Caelestia a familiarity with the foundational concepts and background information provided in B/T s very detailed and lucidly organized Introduction (1 18) is essential. Divided into three sections, it will reward the patient reader s attention when encountering the translation itself. The first section, Cleomedes Date (1 4), shows how the text s internal evidence is absolutely parmount. For example, in the absence of any external biographical data for its author, information drawn from The Heavens itself, both philosophical and astronomical, can establish only that Cleomedes