W A Wijewardena: Scientific research what researchers should do and should not

Similar documents
Lesson 2 The Existence of God Cause & Effect Apologetics Press Introductory Christian Evidences Correspondence Course

Introduction to Deductive and Inductive Thinking 2017

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

PHILOSOPHIES OF SCIENTIFIC TESTING

A Quick Review of the Scientific Method Transcript

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Mathematics as we know it has been created and used by

Common Ground On Creation Keeping The Focus on That God Created and Not When

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

BIBLICAL INTEGRATION IN SCIENCE AND MATH. September 29m 2016

Message: Faith & Science - Part 3

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 3, 2002

Ilija Barukčić Causality. New Statistical Methods. ISBN X Discussion with the reader.

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Full file at

Video: How does understanding whether or not an argument is inductive or deductive help me?

Scientific Method and Research Ethics

SCIENCE The Systematic Means of Studying Creation

Ch01. Knowledge. What does it mean to know something? and how can science help us know things? version 1.5

SYLLABUS. Department Syllabus. Philosophy of Religion

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Sydenham College of Commerce & Economics. * Dr. Sunil S. Shete. * Associate Professor

Falsification or Confirmation: From Logic to Psychology

Two Ways of Thinking

ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

Introduction to Political Science

Mind (1981) Vol xc, To Save Verisimilitude

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Sample Questions with Explanations for LSAT India

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Michał Heller, Podglądanie Wszechświata, Znak, Kraków 2008, ss. 212.

Reading and Evaluating Arguments

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

someone who was willing to question even what seemed to be the most basic ideas in a

Questions for Critically Reading an Argument

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

World Religions. These subject guidelines should be read in conjunction with the Introduction, Outline and Details all essays sections of this guide.

Science, Rationality and the Human Mind. by Garry Jacobs

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

The Nature of Human Brain Work. Joseph Dietzgen

The Will To Believe by William James

Department of Philosophy

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Martha C. Nussbaum (4) Outline:

The Pressures of Ministry Life

A Brief Essay on Essays

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

Can Things Get Better?

A Note on Straight-Thinking

been programming for more than ten years and, as a result of the problems encountered, I was begindg to feel thet the automatic computer belonged

studyıng phılosophy: a brıght ıdea

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Theists versus atheists: are conflicts necessary?

Is Time Illusory?!1 Alexey Burov, FSP, Feb 1, 2019

Unit 1: Philosophy and Science. Other Models of Knowledge

AKC Lecture 1 Plato, Penrose, Popper

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

I Don't Believe in God I Believe in Science

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Introduction to Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

The evolution of the meaning of SCIENCE. SCIENCE came from the latin word SCIENTIA which means knowledge.

Supplemental Material 2a: The Proto-psychologists. In this presentation, we will have a short review of the Scientific Revolution and the

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

complete state of affairs and an infinite set of events in one go. Imagine the following scenarios:

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Dean, Northwestern College of Chiropractic

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

1.6 Validity and Truth

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

Humanistic Thought, Understanding, and the Nature of Grasp

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

2Toward Maturity LESSON

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Policy: Validation of Ministries

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

SHARPENING THINKING SKILLS. Case study: Science and religion (* especially relevant to Chapters 3, 8 & 10)

Radical Centrism & the Redemption of Secular Philosophy

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

B.A. in Religion, Philosophy and Ethics (4-year Curriculum) Course List and Study Plan

Transcription:

W A Wijewardena: Scientific research what researchers should do and should not Keynote address by Mr W A Wijewardena, Deputy Governor of the Central Bank of Sri Lanka, at the 3rd International Research Conference, organized by the Faculty of Management & Finance, University of Colombo, Colombo, 11 December 2008. The views expressed in this paper are those of the author and should not be construed as those of the Central Bank of Sri Lanka. * * * A Master Debater has once boasted that he normally employs three ploys to subdue his difficult customers. When I find that my opponent is not easily surmountable, I use mathematics, philosophy and religion to subdue him. He has confessed. Mathematical equations frighten him, philosophical expressions confuse him and religious sayings make him feel guilty. After that, he is an easy prey for the final onslaught. He has further elaborated triumphantly. The superior property of mathematical equations in frightening intellectual opponents is not without precedent. An example in this connection has been presented by Astro-physicist Carl Sagan in his Broca s Brain (p. 151). According to the story, the French encyclopaedist Diderot, being an atheist himself, had challenged anyone to prove the existence of God during a visit to Russian Empress Catherine s court. When he became an embarrassment to everyone, Euler, the master mathematician and also a temporary visitor to the Court, is said to have accepted the challenge. Euler has said, Sir, (a + b n )/n = x, therefore God exists. Disprove. The mathematics-phobic Diderot, being unable to respond, is said to have fled the Court! These examples suggest that people can sometimes use gimmicks to confuse opponents and win arguments. Such winnings do not prove or disprove any proposition. They do not add knowledge to the extant body of knowledge. They simply help a crafty person to make a temporary escape from an existing difficult situation. Scientific research is different from the employment of gimmicks to gain temporary winnings. It is the method of using human intellect to discover new knowledge and add that wisdom to the existing body of knowledge until it is disproved by a new discovery. Hence, those who are engaged in scientific research have to conform to a set of accepted principles, guidelines and a code of ethics and morality. To follow such a set of rules when playing the game called scientific inquiry is not an easy task. Yet, one has to do so in order to separate science from what is sometimes known as pseudo-science. Why scientific research? Human knowledge is as old as the history of human beings. Human beings have attempted to understand Nature, by using human intellect and experience, so that they could find answers to questions that had been puzzling them constantly. Some of these questions have been beyond direct observation such as who created the world? or what caused rains?. Hence, it is quite natural for them to hypothesise answers by using both intellect and experience. When they do so, it is also inevitable for them to base their conclusions on personal biases, fears and prejudices they have been harbouring in their minds. Such conclusions are tainted by biased or prejudiced views held by the person making the conclusions. Hence, such findings are simply an imposition of personal views on the society and, therefore, fail to explain reality and Nature. Therefore, discoveries made in that manner do not enhance the human knowledge. In this background, it is necessary to build the knowledge base of mankind free from biases, fears and prejudices. This could be attained by pursuing scientific inquiry which bases itself on a set of principles, guidelines and an ethical and moral code that discipline the BIS Review 161/2008 1

researchers. It should, however, be noted that the conclusions derived through scientific inquiry are not static and permanent. The very nature of scientific inquiry is that conclusions derived from a given research study, as Karl Popper pointed out, should be capable of being refuted by a new inquiry. Hence, results produced by scientific research carry with them the property of refutability and are valid only until a new research study would replace them with new results. In this sense, the knowledge base developed through scientific inquiry could be equated to a reservoir from which water would flow out and fresh water would flow in continuously. But the core knowledge, just like the permanently stored water in the reservoir, would remain intact. The mind of a researcher engaged in scientific inquiry There are certain qualities and prerequisites which a researcher engaged in scientific inquiry should possess. The most important of these is the open mind with which the researcher should commence his inquiry. The researcher is not a propagandist, nor is he a person bent on superimposing his views on others. He should be humble enough to reject even the views he would have held for long, if his inquiry does not support them. In other words, he should conduct his inquiry, not with the objective of establishing the views held by him, but with the objective of subjecting them to a free inquiry. This is known as rational and objective thinking. The Buddha, in a discourse He preached to members of Kalama clan, outlined the nature of rational and objective thinking, though its purpose was to guide them to distinguish good from bad. Oh, Members of Kalama clan the Buddha said. Do not rely on an opinion because you have heard it often and you are familiar with it. Do not accept it because it is in accord with tradition or found in the scriptures or logical or conforms to theory. Do not accept it because it is preached by your teachers or by a respected priest (Anguththara Nikaya). The researcher who plans to engage himself in scientific inquiry should be free from the influence of previous knowledge or the traditions and should not be guided by mere logical considerations. How could an individual understand the nature of the real world? There are two approaches suggested for this purpose, namely, classicism or romanticism. Classicism shows the world by means of its underlying form. It proceeds by reason or by laws governing Nature. If a motor car engine is presented to a classicist, he would be interested in finding out its underlying mechanism as determined by mechanical laws governing the working of the engine. A romantic, on the other hand, would simply be interested only on the outer surface of the world. He would look at the world from the point of its immediate appearance. Hence, a romantic would find a motor car engine with wires and cables strewn everywhere in a disorderly manner as a dull appearance. A person with a scientific mind would get himself embroiled in classicism and not in romanticism. This is because romanticism is concerned about emotions feelings like biases, fears or prejudices which a scientist should avoid when undertaking a scientific inquiry. What is scientific method? Robert M Pirsig, the philosopher-novelist, in his novel titled Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance, raises a very pertinent question regarding scientists and scientific inquiry. Is a sideway motorcycle mechanic a scientist? The answer depends on how the motorcycle mechanic would apply himself to the problem at hand. According to Pirsig, if a motorcycle mechanic does a lousy job, then he does not qualify himself to be called a scientist. There are many mechanics of this type. When a faulty motorcycle is brought to a mechanic, he may simply jump to conclusions based on his 2 BIS Review 161/2008

previous knowledge. Instead of subjecting the motorcycle to a thorough scientific inquiry, he may conclude that the fault lies in a certain part or a certain mechanism. To reach this conclusion, he has not gathered the relevant information. The chances are that he may be correct or may not be correct. If he is correct, the repair performed on the basis of the diagnosis made with imperfect information will prove to be a success. But the mechanic in that case has behaved like a speculator and the outcome of speculation may have the chance of being a success or a failure. If it turns out to be a failure, the cost to the owner of the motorcycle would be enormous. In that case, since the correct repair has not been performed, the motorcycle will continue to remain faulty. Hence, a true scientist engaging himself in scientific inquiry should not be a speculator. Instead, he should be a person willing to follow the scientific method to arrive at conclusions. Decisions could be made by a mechanic attending to a faulty motorcycle by resorting to either inductivism or deductivism. The inductive approach requires the mechanic to look for evidence in the real world and come to conclusions. For instance, if we see crows that are black and if we continue to see black crows, we may conclude that all crows are black. A motorcycle mechanic may likewise see the faulty part and conclude that the fault lies in that part. The deductive approach, on the other hand, requires the mechanic to theorise in his mind and come to conclusions based on empirical findings he would make to support his theory. In the previous black crow example, we may theorise that crows are black and then look for black crows in the real world. When we find one black crow, our theory is proved. A motorcycle mechanic becomes a scientist, if he follows the scientific method in the diagnosis of the fault and the subsequent repair of the motorcycle. It involves starting with an open mind. There are no previously made conclusions or prejudgments. The approach is simply classical, that is, guided by underlying principles and not by the immediate appearance. There are several steps which a scientist should follow when he adopts the scientific method. A good motorcycle mechanic would also follow the same steps. The steps involved in a scientific inquiry are as follows. First, the identified problem has to be stated in clear terms. In the case of a motorcycle, the problem may be that the engine does not start. Second, based on the problem, one hypothesis or several hypotheses as required regarding the cause of the problem should be made. The motorcycle engine does not start because there is no fuel in the tank. Or there is a blockage of the tube that distributes fuel to the engine. Or the electrical system may have failed. Or carburettor would have been blocked. The mechanic would hypothesise all possible reasons for the failure of the engine. Third, experiments are designed to test each hypothesis made. The mechanic may open the fuel tank to see whether there is fuel. If there is no fuel, he will try to start the engine having filled the tank with fuel. If there is fuel in the tank, then he would examine the second hypothesis, that is, whether there is a blockage in the tube that distributes fuel to the engine. If there is a blockage, he will clean it and try to start the engine. If there is no blockage, then he would experiment the third hypothesis, namely, the working of the electrical system. In this manner, he would experiment all the hypotheses he has made one by one and make relevant conclusions. Fourth, the results of the experiments are analysed in order to ascertain whether the hypothesis is proved. Or else, when several hypotheses have been made, to ascertain which hypothesis has been proved. Fifth, making final conclusions out of the observed results of the experiments. A disciplined motorcycle mechanic would follow these steps involved in the scientific method and attend to the required repair of the fault in the motorcycle. In this sense, a sideway motorcycle mechanic is not different from a trained scientist, since both follow the scientific method in reaching conclusions. BIS Review 161/2008 3

The use of techniques and technology It has been fashionable for scientists to make use of scientific techniques and technology to facilitate the decision making process, when undertaking scientific inquiries. Extreme care should be exercised by scientists in this instance. Every technique has its own methodology and limitations and the scientist should be fully aware of same when such techniques are used. Inappropriate use of the techniques or wrong conclusions made on the basis of the results derived amount to misuse of science by the researchers. It also paves way for crafty individuals to use the results to their advantage and gullible individuals to get victimised. The use of econometrics has been one of the techniques employed by scientists to prove or disprove their hypotheses. This has also been one of the sources of misuse of science, either because wrong calculations are made or wrong conclusions are arrived at, due to the failure of the researcher to analyse the error term appropriately. Wikipedia, the cyberencyclopaedia, is full of the instances of such misuse of econometric methods in research. It is noteworthy to refer to two studies done by Deirdre N McCloskey and Stephen T Ziliak of the University of Iowa on the status of econometric studies in research articles published in the reputed journal American Economic Review in 1980s. They have found fault with authors for not analysing the error term properly and using the statistical term significance inappropriately. One of their papers published in the Journal of Economic Literature in March, 1996 under the title The Standard Error of Regressions has made the following eyeopening comment: Such misuses of statistical significance appear to depend in part on a vintage effect, measured by date of Ph.D. conferral. The papers authored by Ph.D.s conferred between 1975 and 1979, when inexpensively generated t-tests first reached the masses, were considerably worse than the papers of others at making a distinction between economic and statistical significance. They used the word significance in ambiguous ways more often than did early or later Ph.D.s and they were less likely to separate statistical significance from other types of significance in the sections on scientific and policy implications (p 111). The other findings of McCloskey and Ziliak are also startling. Of the 182 articles in the American Economic Review they have surveyed, 70 percent had not distinguished statistical significance from economic, policy or scientific significance. While they had referred to largeness of the estimators, 72 percent had not asked how large was large? At the same time, 59 percent had used the word significance in ambiguous ways. A more pronounced failure has been the non-reporting of descriptive statistics such as the means of the regression variables by 69 percent of the authors. (p 106). The problem with econometric studies is that the computations made by authors remain as a black box to ordinary readers. It is the responsibility of the editors of journals to verify the black box and assure quality on behalf the general public who consumes the outcome of research studies. It is, therefore, disheartening that learned journals have published such papers without due reference and consideration of the methodology adopted in conducting the research under reference. Today, of course, with advanced statistical packages available, it is possible for the editors of the journals to check on the appropriateness of the statistical calculations made by the paper writers. Since the ordinary readers of scientific papers are unable to gauge the wrongful way of handling econometrics by researchers, such studies by editors before papers are published become all the more important. In view of the gullibility of general readers, the misuse of econometrics in learned papers is akin to misselling that one finds in the market place when a seller has not fully apprised a buyer of the risks of buying a product. This type of mis-selling by researchers could be termed econometric dishonesty which they are not supposed to practise. Researchers find a truth and not the truth The real world is vast and complex. Hence, it cannot be mapped out by scientific research adequately, just like neurologists are unable to map out the human brain completely. What 4 BIS Review 161/2008

the science does is to discover only a flint of the truth in the vast real world. As such, there is no dearth of hypotheses which scientists could make and a dearth of theories which they can formulate. That is good news for prospective scientists. However, one theory which is valid today could be disproved by another theory to be formulated tomorrow. Hence, all theories are subject to the same property: the property of refutability. In fact, Karl Popper s argument was that if a theory cannot be refuted, then it does not become a theory. Hence, any scientific research will discover only a truth and not the truth. This means that all scientific research studies undertaken in all the disciplines would produce only a relative truth and not the absolute truth. With all the scientific apparatuses, techniques and computing capacity available today, science still cannot reach out to the absolute truth. As such, the task of finding the absolute truth has been relegated to religion and mystics. This may be discouraging news for those who are engaged in scientific research. But, that has been the way of science throughout its history and such discovery of relative truth has been adequate for the purpose of building the human knowledge base and putting it to practical use by mankind. In the modern world, the discovery of absolute truth may therefore be irrelevant. Conclusions A researcher is not a propagandist or a dictator. His task is to follow an accepted set of principles, guidelines and an ethical and moral code to discover a truth, and not the truth, and add it to the extant knowledge base. He should start his inquiry with an open mind and be ready to reject even the long held views if empirical studies do not support them. But to do so, a researcher should display a fair degree of maturity and necessarily cultivate within himself self-discipline, wisdom, objectivity and equanimity. In this sense, a perfect researcher is like the Buddha who is not guided by biased or prejudiced emotions. Hence, the most important requirement of a researcher is that he should be honest to himself. BIS Review 161/2008 5