As a long-time advocate of the ecological approach to perception, and an implacable

Similar documents
Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Mark Coeckelbergh: Growing Moral Relations. Critique of Moral Status Ascription

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

Consciousness Without Awareness

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

Craig on the Experience of Tense

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

What is consciousness? Although it is possible to offer

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

The British Empiricism

Nathan Oaklander IS THERE A DIFFERENCE BETWEEN ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE SPACE?

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Thomas Reid on personal identity

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Presuppositional Apologetics

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

1/8. The Third Analogy

The Existence of Material Substance. A Response to George Berkeley s Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. Philosophy 104

NON-COGNITIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL-BASED EPISTEMIC REASONS: A SYMPATHETIC REPLY TO CIAN DORR

Normativity and Philosophical Naturalism - Peircean Lessons. Henrik Rydenfelt University of Helsinki

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Epistemology and sensation

Against the No-Miracle Response to Indispensability Arguments

PHILOSOPHY A.S. UNIT 2 PAPER, JANUARY 2009 SUGGESTED ANSWERS TO SELECTED QUESTIONS

Nation, Science and Religion in Nehru s Discovery of India

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

This is, of course, quite correct; one cannot argue for narrow states of mind simply from the existence of error. Descombes goes on:

Rational Answers to Ideological Commitments. Jaafar Sheikh Idris. website

5 A Modal Version of the

Is God Good By Definition?

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2016 (Daniel)

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

DO SENSE EXPERIENTIAL STATES HAVE CONCEPTUAL CONTENT?

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Aboutness and Justification

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Ronald Dworkin, Religion without God, Harvard University Press, 2013, pp. 192, 16.50, ISBN


Rashdall, Hastings. Anthony Skelton

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Reasons for Belief Session 1 I Struggle With Doubt. Is That OK?

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

1/12. The A Paralogisms

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

ETHICS AND THE FUTURE OF HUMANKIND, REALITY OF THE HUMAN EXISTENCE

Transfiguration of human consciousness and eternal life

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

Every simple idea has a simple impression, which resembles it; and every simple impression a correspondent idea

Ethical non-naturalism

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Higher-Order Approaches to Consciousness and the Regress Problem

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Review of Collins, The Language of God: A Scientist Presents Evidence for Belief

Summary Kooij.indd :14

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

Title: Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction.

The question is concerning truth and it is inquired first what truth is. Now

Objectivism and Education: A Response to David Elkind s The Problem with Constructivism

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Kant and his Successors

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Part I: The Structure of Philosophy

THE JOY OF LOVE. THE CHURCH AS THE GUARDIAN OF HUMAN LOVE Maryvale, 21 May 2016

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Anselmian Theism and Created Freedom: Response to Grant and Staley

Lesson 2. Systematic Theology Pastor Tim Goad. Part Two Theology Proper - Beginning at the Beginning I. Introduction to the One True God

The Kennewick Man as person : Ethical Considerations and Cultural Perspectives. Haley Adams

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

Transcription:

Religious perception and the education of attention Tim Ingold University of Aberdeen As a long-time advocate of the ecological approach to perception, and an implacable opponent of cognitivism in all its forms (Ingold 2000), I am much in sympathy with the argument of this paper. I agree that the cognitive science of religion, with its stress on explaining the tenacity of apparently irrational beliefs (Boyer 2000), completely misses the point. For in sourcing religion to compendia of beliefs about the world, and about what may or may not exist in it, cognitive theorists interpose an ontological barrier between the mind in which such beliefs are to be found and the world to which they pertain which flies in the face of the very existential commitment and the passion that infuses it or in a word, the faith that surely lies at the foundation of religious sensibility. Religion, as theologian Peter Candler (2006: 30-40) has put it, is enshrined in a grammar not or representation but of participation, in a recognition that knowledge and understanding are not superimposed on the world from the outside, in the attempt to explain or interpret it, but grow from the inside, from the crucible of our involved participation in a world in the continual becoming of which our lives and feelings are necessarily enmeshed. In the cognitive science of religion, religious intuitions couched in the performative grammar of participation are refracted through the distorting lens of a grammar of representation that denies, a priori, the very commitment on which participation depends. The inevitable result is to recast these intuitions as a spectrum of beliefs in spiritual entities which, if they existed in fact, would defy obvious principles of physical and biological causation. Thus cognitivism, 1

having already corrupted what it sets out to explain, is locked in a circularity of its own making. As Barrett puts it, theories that invoke belief to explain experiential differences are merely begging the question. We should rather start from perceptual experience itself, and James Gibson s (1979) theory of direct perception, with its emphasis on the skilled engagement of the perceiver with the furnishings and textures of a richly structured environment, offers a way to do so. Nonetheless, though I remain an enthusiast, I am no longer sure whether Gibson s approach takes us quite far enough. What I like about it is the focus on attention. Learning to perceive, for Gibson, is learning to attend to notice, to discriminate, to pick things out. The skilled perceiver is an active explorer of his or her surroundings, not a passive recipient of stimuli that have then to be processed by the intellect in order to arrive at a hypothetical picture of what is out there. Yet there is a contradiction at the heart of the approach, for while the perceiver is described as moving, dynamic and exploratory, the world to be perceived appears to have been already laid out, like a furnished room awaiting its occupants or a stage with all its scenery waiting for the actors to make their entry. The environment is there, for Gibson (1979: 139): its objects afford what they do because of what they are, irrespective of the presence of any creature that might happen upon them. Yet religious experience, I would contend, does not lie in the perception of a ready-made world, nor does religious practice lie in mastering the skills for engaging with its constituents. It lies rather in the perception of a world that is itself continually coming into being both around and along with the perceiver him- or herself. It is because such perception is intrinsic to the process of the world s coming-into-being that it is also imaginative, rather than opposed to imagination as Gibson thought (Ingold 2012: 6-7). And while we may endorse 2

Gibson s apt characterisation of perceptual learning as an education of attention (Gibson 1979: 254), I would argue that the education to which novices lay themselves open, in religious practice, is just the opposite of what Gibson had in mind. Recall that the word attendre, in French, means to wait, and that even in English, to attend to things or persons carries connotations of looking after them, doing their bidding, and following what they do. In this regard, attention abides with a world that is not ready made but always incipient, on the cusp. Thus, rather than world s lying in wait for the perceiver, it is the perceiver who waits upon the world. As the philosopher Jan Masschelein (2010) has observed, this kind of education is not an instilling of meaning and value into the person, but a leading out of the person along a line of movement. That is what education (from the Latin ex = out + ducere = to lead ) literally means. To be thus thrust out, into a world that has yet to reveal its hand, is unsettling. It implies not the mastery of the skilled practitioner but the submission of one who being out of position, or ex-posed is at the mercy of what transpires. As indigenous people versed in the way of being that westerners call animism tell us, only a fool would presume to know what the world will bring. The wise man, or woman, looks, listens and waits for things to reveal themselves for what they are. Along these ways of perception lie experience, understandings and transformations of the self. Indeed animism, contrary to what Barrett suggests, is not really about ascribing intentionality to non-human entities, as though for humans and non-humans alike, the executive cast of action followed the reflective cast of thought. It is rather about attending to other beings, in perception and action, as they attend to you or, in a word, about corresponding with them (Ingold 2013: 105-8). As with animism in particular so religion in general, I would argue, is about neither belief nor direct perception 3

but mutual attention or correspondence. As the philosopher Michel Serres (1995: 48) puts it, the opposite of religion is not atheism or lack of belief but negligence. Apart from these qualifications, only one thing really jarred in my reading of this paper, and that is the author s insistence on a distinction between insiders and outsiders, and between insider and outsider experiences. This strikes me as rigid and insensitive to context, and somewhat out of kilter with the overall tenor of the argument, which would put any such division in doubt. Moreover it tends to obscure the much more fundamental distinction, between inside and outside ways of knowing. As I have shown, it is by eliding this distinction that cognitive theorists miscast religious intuitions as irrational beliefs. Finally, I did wonder about the stress on the scientific search for explanations of religious experience. This does seem to put science and religion on opposite sides of a fence, with science doing the explaining and religion the object to be explained. It seems to me that this division is untenable. What if the source of religious experience lies in those pre-objective commitments to the world in which we find our being, and which in turn underwrite the very possibility of science? References Boyer, P. (2000). Functional origins of religious concepts: ontological and strategic selection in evolved minds. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 6, 195-214. Candler. P. M. Jr. (2006). Theology, rhetoric, manuduction, or reading scripture together on the path to God. Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans. Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. 4

Ingold,T. (2000). The Perception of the Environment: Essays on Livelihood, Dwelling and Skill. London: Routledge. Ingold, T. (2012). Introduction. In Imagining Landscapes: Past, Present and Future, eds. M. Janowski and T. Ingold. Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 1-18. Ingold, T. (2013). Making: Anthropology, Archaeology, Art and Architecture. Abingdon: Routledge. Masschelein, J. (2010). E-ducating the gaze: the idea of a poor pedagogy. Ethics and Education 5: 43-53. Serres, M. (1995). The natural contract (trans. E. MacArthur and W. Paulson). Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press. 5