Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Similar documents
Dumitrescu Bogdan Andrei - The incompatibility of analytic statements with Quine s universal revisability

Cory Juhl, Eric Loomis, Analyticity (New York: Routledge, 2010).

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

On Quine, Grice and Strawson, and the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction. by Christian Green

Carnap s notion of analyticity and the two wings of analytic philosophy. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle

Epistemology Naturalized

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Constructing the World

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

Defending A Dogma: Between Grice, Strawson and Quine

Comments on Scott Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, volume I

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Tuomas E. Tahko (University of Helsinki)

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

37. The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction

My self-as-philosopher and my self-as-scientist meet to do research in the classroom: Some Davidsonian notes on the philosophy of educational research

Naturalism and is Opponents

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Positive Philosophy, Freedom and Democracy. Roger Bishop Jones

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

Conceptual Analysis meets Two Dogmas of Empiricism David Chalmers (RSSS, ANU) Handout for Australasian Association of Philosophy, July 4, 2006

Assertion and Inference

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

CLASS PARTICIPATION IS A REQUIREMENT

1. A first look at the question whether Quine s epistemology is normative

Naturalism Fall Winter 2004

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Epistemic Utility and Theory-Choice in Science: Comments on Hempel

Pihlström, Sami Johannes.

Philosophy of Logic and Language (108) Comprehensive Reading List Robert L. Frazier 24/10/2009

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Ch V: The Vienna Circle (Moritz Schlick, Rudolf Carnap, and Otto Neurath)[title crossed out?]

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Introduction: Paradigms, Theism, and the Parity Thesis


What is a Theory of Meaning? (II), p. 60

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

145 Philosophy of Science

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy by Avrum Stroll

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Putnam and the Contextually A Priori Gary Ebbs University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

The Philosophy of Language. Quine versus Meaning

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh


On Katz and Indeterminacy of Translation

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

Relativism and Indeterminacy of Meaning (Quine) Indeterminacy of Translation

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

MATHEMATICS ITS FOUNDATIONS AND THEIR IMPLICAT

Carnap s Non-Cognitivism as an Alternative to Both Value- Absolutism and Value-Relativism

Critical Scientific Realism

Honours Programme in Philosophy

The Human Science Debate: Positivist, Anti-Positivist, and Postpositivist Inquiry. By Rebecca Joy Norlander. November 20, 2007

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Analyticity, Reductionism, and Semantic Holism. The verification theory is an empirical theory of meaning which asserts that the meaning of a

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Reflective Equilibrium. Hassan Masoud Jan. 30, 2012

Transcription:

[Final manuscript. Published in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews] Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN 9781107178151 Reviewed by Sander Verhaegh, TiLPS, Tilburg University Rudolf Carnap, W. V. Quine, and Hilary Putnam are probably the three most central figures in mid-twentieth-century American philosophy. Their debates about meaning, translation, and ontology largely set the agenda for analytic philosophers in the first decades after WWII. Most historians believe that beneath these philosophical debates lies a more fundamental disagreement about the nature of science, philosophy, and our methods of inquiry. That is, Quine is often viewed as slaying the (supposedly) Carnapian distinction between science and philosophy, whereas Putnam is commonly read as dismissing both Carnap s positivism and Quine s scientific naturalism. In this excellent volume of essays, Gary Ebbs offers an exciting alternative interpretation. In eleven essays, an introduction, and an afterword, he argues that at this more fundamental level, Carnap s, Quine s, and Putnam s positions are largely the same. According to Ebbs, the three all accept the following four principles about the nature of inquiry: (1) In our pursuit of truth, we can do no better than to start in the middle, relying on already established beliefs and inferences and applying our best methods for reevaluating particular beliefs and inferences and arriving at new ones.

(2) No part of our supposed knowledge, no matter how clear it seems to us or how firmly we now hold it, is unrevisable or guaranteed to be true. (3) Insofar as traditional philosophical conceptions of reason, justification, and apriority conflict with the first two principles, they should be abandoned. (4) A central task of philosophy is to clarify and facilitate our rational inquiries by replacing terms and theories that we find useful in some ways, but problematic in others, with new terms and theories that are as clear and unproblematic to us as the terms and methods of our best scientific theories. (pp. 1-2) Carnap, Quine, and Putnam, in other words, all dismiss traditional inflated conceptions of philosophical inquiry and replace them with a deeply fallibilistic, explication-based picture in which there is no perspective external to the discourses we find useful in our everyday and scientific inquiries. Or, as Carnap put it, all work is done according to strict scientific methods and not by means of higher or deeper insights (Carnap 1934, 46). In developing this alternative reading, Ebbs does not aim to downplay the philosophical disagreements between Carnap, Quine, and Putnam. Instead, he offers a reinterpretation of those discussions. Rather than dismissing the debate about the analytic-synthetic distinction, for instance, he shows that Quine, in arguing that Carnap has failed to explain [the] term analytic in a language suited for and used in the mature natural sciences (p. 133) is just adopting Carnap s method of inquiry and improving his views from within. He was, as Quine himself has argued, just being more Carnapian than Carnap in being critical in this question (Quine 1994,

228). Likewise, in discussing the Quine-Putnam debate about transtheoretical terms, Ebbs interprets Putnam as out-quining Quine in urging for an account of truth and reference that accords with the identifications of agreements and disagreements [ ] that we actually make in the midst of our everyday and scientific inquiries (p. 206). Although Ebbs historical claim raises some questions e.g. Is his reading of Carnap compatible with Michael Friedman s Kantian interpretation?; How would he explain the numerous miscommunications between Carnap and Quine in the 1940s and 1950s?; And could his fundamental principles (1)-(4) also be used to explain Putnam s frequent changes of position? the reader should not expect a detailed discussion of such questions. This is not a complaint however. For Ebbs chooses a different method to justify his reading. Rather than starting from a neutral position between several competing interpretations and trying to make a case for his interpretation over the other contenders, he starts from the assumption that his reading of Carnap, Quine, and Putnam is correct and shows that it can help us to (i) clarify their views, (ii) to dissolve some influential objections to their positions, and (iii) to improve on their views by showing how his interpretation opens new and previously overlooked alternative accounts of truth, justification, and language use. Ebbs, in other words, is himself adopting the very method of inquiry he attributes to Carnap, Quine, and Putnam; he is starting in the middle and he aims to improve, clarify, and understand their positions from within (Quine 1975, 72). Because it is impossible to discuss all eleven essays in one review, let me discuss some examples of each of the strategies (i)-(iii). In Chapter 3, Carnap and Quine on Truth by Convention, first published in Mind, 1 Ebbs shows how his 1 Nine of the eleven essays in the volume have been previously published. The Chapters 2 ( Carnap on Ontology ) and 6 ( Reading Quine s Claim that Definitional

reading of the Carnap-Quine debate can help us to clarify Quine s goals in Truth by Convention (1936). Ebbs argues that Quine s arguments against the idea that logic is true by convention were not aimed at Carnap but were the result of an attempt to evaluate an option that Quine himself found appealing. Ebbs shows that the standard interpretation of Truth by Convention is misguided on at least two points: (a) Carnap was never committed to the view that Quine dismisses and (b) Quine himself believed that some parts of science (e.g. set theory) are true by convention. But is not Quine s naturalism incompatible with the view that some claims are true by convention? It is precisely at this point that Ebbs novel interpretation illuminates Quine s position: a scientific naturalist selects and formulates the truths that count for most. [Quine] begins with the obvious point that the truths that count for most for a scientific naturalist are just the ones she affirms when, in the course of her inquiries, she adopts particular scientific theories and hypotheses. All these truths may be called explanatory in one good, though very broad, sense of that flexible word. The truths that are explanatory in this encompassing sense are just the ones that it is the aim of science to affirm. It follows that we have no grip on what it is to be explanatory in this encompassing sense apart from our own ongoing scientific inquir[i]es. In particular, if in the course of our inquiries we set forth some axioms or postulates unaccompanied by any attempt at justification other than in terms of elegance and convenience (Quine Abbreviations Create Synonymies ) as well as the Introduction and the Afterword are new.

[1963, 393]), then these truths count as explanatory in the same broad sense that theories and hypotheses in physics do. (pp. 80-81) Note that this account has serious implications for what has often been called the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument. Although Ebbs, except for some brief remarks on page 60, does not drive this point home, his account implies that Quine (and Putnam?) do not have to worry about the parts of set theory that are dispensable from a physicist s point of view. Quine s notorious defense of the axiom of constructibility (V = L), for example, can be simply read as an attempt to submit set theory to the considerations of simplicity, economy, and naturalness that contribute to the molding of scientific theories generally (Quine 1992, 95); it does not have to be interpreted as a desperate attempt to adjust his views about set theory such that they are compatible with his indispensability defense. Ebbs reading, in other words, implies that the indispensability thesis should be interpreted differently; it should simply be read as the judgment that our best overall empirical theory of nature contains set theory (in particular, in most of Quine s work, a set theory governed by the axiom of constructibility). Chapter 5 ( Quine Gets the Last Word ) is an excellent example of how Ebbs interpretation can contribute to dissolving a wide variety of influential objections to Carnap s, Quine s, and Putnam s views. This paper, first published in The Journal of Philosophy, is mandatory reading for anyone working on Quine. Ebbs shows how a broad range of influential objections to Quine s views e.g. Jaegwon Kim s argument that there is no room for a normative notion of justification in a naturalized epistemology or H. P. Grice and P. F. Strawson s claim that Quine s naturalism leads to the conclusion that our sentences are meaningless ultimately boil down to a

fundamental misunderstanding of Quine s radical minimalist understanding of language use. Kim, Grice, and Strawson (but also Thomas Nagel, Saul Kripke, John McDowell, and Michael Dummett) fail to see that if we are truly working from within, we do not require external extra-scientific criteria for justification, truth, and significance. As Ebbs puts it in his reply to Kim, for example, the objection that Quine s project has nothing to do with epistemology is valid only if we cling dogmatically to the claim that if we abandon the traditional epistemologist s assumption that there are substantive general principles for evaluating and justifying assertions, we lose our grip on what it is to justify, defend, and revise our assertions from the standpoint of a given scientific discipline (p. 125). The point of Quine s naturalism, Ebbs shows, is that the traditional epistemologist s assumption can be abandoned without loss. Chapter 10 ( Truth and Transtheoretical Terms ) is a nice example of one of Ebbs attempts to improve on the work of Carnap, Quine, and Putnam. In his Afterword, Ebbs explains that the essays in his volume together contribute to the development of a new minimalist conception of language use and justification that combines Tarski-style disquotational accounts of truth and satisfaction (reference) for the words we can directly use, with our practical identifications of words between speakers and across time, to yield a minimalist account of transtheoretical terms. (p. 257) Chapter 10 constitutes one of Ebbs most significant contributions to this new minimalist conception an account he has developed in more detail in Truth and

Words (2009). He submits that Putnam has convincingly shown that in science and in everyday life we often identify reference transtheoretically. When we now read Niels Bohr s 1911 claim that electrons at each moment have a determinate position and momentum, for example, we generally take the reference of his term electron to be the same as ours despite the fundamental changes in our theories about electrons (Putnam 1973, 197). Still, Ebbs shows that Putnam is mistaken when the latter argues that Quine s deflationary theory of truth and reference leads to the conclusion that two speakers cannot genuinely agree or disagree with each other. Ebbs goes on to sketch a new theory of truth and reference that is both deflationary and does justice to Putnam s conclusions about our actual practices of agreeing and disagreeing. Likewise, new theoretical options are revealed and developed in Chapter 7 ( Can First-Order Logical Truth Be Defined in Purely Extensional Terms? ), where Ebbs outlines a new extensional definition of logical truth, and Chapter 9 ( Conditionalization and Conceptual Change: Chalmers in Defense of a Dogma ), where he combines his account about our practices of identifying transtheoretical terms with a theory about revisable Bayesian confirmational commitments, while dismissing David Chalmers (2011) argument that Quine s and Putnam s claim that every belief is rationally revisable is incompatible with Bayesian conditionalization. Ebbs volume, in sum, is an important publication from both a historical and a systematic point of view. It offers a new perspective on the relation between Carnap, Quine, and Putnam as well as a substantive contribution to ongoing systematic debates about truth, justification, and language use. As such, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry will be of interest and value not only to historians of analytic philosophy, but also to all philosophers who believe that Carnap s, Quine s,

and Putnam s most fundamental insights deserve continuous discussion and adaptation. REFERENCES Carnap, R. (1934). Die Aufgabe der Wissenschaftslogic. Translated as The Task of the Logic of Science. In McGuinness, B. (1987, ed.). Unified Science: The Vienna Circle Mongraph Series Originally Edited by Otto Neurath, pp. 46-66. Dordrecht: D. Reidel. Chalmers, D. (2011). Revisability and Conceptual Change in Two Dogmas of Empiricism. Journal of Philosophy, 108(8):387-415 Ebbs, G. (2009). Truth and Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Putnam, H. (1973). Explanation and Reference. In Putnam (1975). Mind, Language, and Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2, pp. 196-214. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Quine, W. V. (1936). Truth by Convention. In Quine (1976). The Ways of Paradox. Revised and enlarged edition, pp. 77-106. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Quine, W. V. (1963). Carnap and Logical Truth. In Schilpp, P. A. (ed.). The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. La Salle, IL: Open Court. Quine, W. V. (1975). Five Milestones of Empiricism. In Quine (1981). Theories and Things, pp. 67-72. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Quine, W. V. (1992). Pursuit of Truth. Revised edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Quine, W. V. (1994). Exchange Between Donald Davidson and W. V. Quine

Following Davidson s Lecture. In Føllesdal, D. and Quine, D. B. (2008, eds.). Quine in Dialogue, pp. 152-156. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This research is funded by The Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO, grant 275-20-064).